Выбери формат для чтения
Загружаем конспект в формате pdf
Это займет всего пару минут! А пока ты можешь прочитать работу в формате Word 👇
3
Inflectional morphology
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Introduction
The prototypical inflectional categories include number, tense, person, case,
gender, and others, all of which usually produce different forms of the same
word rather than different words. Thus leaf and leaves, or write and writes,
or run and ran are not given separate headwords in dictionaries. Derivational
categories, in contrast, do form separate words, so that leaflet, writer, and rerun
will figure as separate words in dictionaries. In addition, inflectional categories
do not in general alter the basic meaning expressed by a word; they merely add
specifications to a word or emphasize certain aspects of its meaning. Leaves, for
instance, has the same basic meaning as leaf, but adds to this the specification
of multiple exemplars of leaves. Derived words, by contrast, generally denote
different concepts from their base: leaflet refers to different things from leaf;
and the noun writer calls up a somewhat different concept from the verb to
write.
That said, finding a watertight cross-linguistic definition of ‘inflectional’
which will let us classify every morphological category as either inflectional or
derivational is not easy. Nor can ‘inflectional’ be defined simply by generalizing
over attested inflectional systems or paradigms; the cross-linguistic variation
in both forms and categories is too great. Rather, we define inflection as those
categories of morphology that are regularly responsive to the grammatical
environment in which they are expressed.1 Inflection differs from derivation
in that derivation is a lexical matter in which choices are independent of the
grammatical environment.
1
Bickel’s research was supported by grant 8210-053455 from the Swiss National Science Foundation. Nichols’s work on Ingush and Chechen was supported by NSF grant 96-16448. Some
of her work on verbal categories was supported by NSF grant 92-22294. We are indebted to
Fernando Zúñiga, David Peterson, Enrique Palancar, and Louis Boumans for comments on an
earlier draft. This chapter was circulated in Spring 2001 on the AUTOTYP project website
(http://socrates.berkeley.edu/∼autotyp).
In this we follow S. R. Anderson (1992:74–85), but we extend the definition to cover not only
syntactic but also more generally grammatical sensitivity, as explained below. For a different
approach to the definition of inflection, based on prototype theory, see chapter 1 of this volume.
169
170
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
The relevant grammatical environment can be either syntactic or morphological. The syntactic environment is relevant, for example, when morphological
choices are determined by agreement. Many languages require determiners and
adjectives to agree in form with the head noun in an np, as in the following
German examples:2
(1)
German
a. ein-e
gut-e
Lehrerin
a.nom.sg.fem good-nom.sg.fem teacher(fem).nom.sg
‘a good (female) teacher’
b. ein-es
gut-en
Lehrer-s
a.gen.sg.masc good-gen.sg.masc teacher(masc).gen.sg
‘of a good teacher’
Morphological choice – case, number, and gender in ein- ‘a’ and gut- ‘good’ –
here depends directly on the syntactic environment, specifically on the status
of these words as modifiers of a head noun. In (1a), the head noun Lehrerin
has feminine gender and is inflected as nominative singular. This determines
feminine nominative singular forms of the article and the adjective. In (1b),
the head noun is masculine and in the genitive singular case, and this triggers
masculine genitive singular forms of the article and the adjective. The choice
of these article and adjective forms is thus an automatic response to the form
and nature of the head noun. In contrast, the choice of derivational categories –
in this example, between Lehrer and Lehrer-in – is a purely lexical matter which
specifies the reference of the head noun. The effect that derivational morphology
has on syntax is at best indirect, by reassigning words to different parts of the
lexicon: the suffix -in, for example, reassigns Lehrer ‘teacher’ to the class of
feminine nouns, and this property shows up in agreement. Note that it is not
the derivational suffix -in that triggers agreement, but the more general notion
of feminine gender, which mostly includes nouns without such a suffix (e.g.
Schule ‘school’ would trigger exactly the same determiner and adjective forms
in (1a) as Lehrerin).
Other examples of inflectional categories sensitive to syntax are case assignment (government), tense choice in complex sentences (sequence of tenses),
switch reference, and many more which we will review in this chapter.
Often, however, inflectional categories are sensitive not so much to the syntactic environment as to the morphological environment in which they appear.
As an example of this, consider aspect in Russian, which consists of a highly
irregular morphological distinction between what are called perfective and
imperfective verbs, e.g.:
2
See the list of abbreviations at the beginning of the volume.
Inflectional morphology
(2)
Imperfective
pisat
govorit
kupit
delat
saditsja
otcvetat
staret
pit
Perfective
napisat
skazat
pokupat
sdelat
sest
otcvesti
postaret
vypit
171
‘write’
‘say’
‘buy’
‘do’
‘sit down’
‘bloom’
‘get old’
‘drink’
That Russian aspect is inflectional is shown by the fact that it figures in a
morphological rule: the future tense is formed analytically (periphrastically)
if the verb is imperfective, but synthetically if it is perfective. For example,
in the future tense the third person singular form of the imperfective verb pit
‘drink’ is budet pit ‘(he or she) will be drinking, will drink’, i.e. the future is
expressed analytically by combining an auxiliary verb budet ‘(he or she) will’
and an infinitive pit ‘drink’. The same future tense of the perfective verb vypit
‘drink, drink up’, by contrast, is expressed by the synthetic word form vypet
‘(he or she) will drink, will drink up’. Thus, the realization of future tense forms
is determined by the aspect of the verb. In other words, aspect is part of the
structural context of the future tense formation rule in the same way as gender of
the head noun is part of the structural context of the agreement rules illustrated
by example (1) above.
Again, derivational categories are different. German, for example, has verb
morphology that is in many ways similar to that of Russian, and it even has
pairs of verbs that look similar to the perfective versus imperfective contrast of
Russian; compare Russian pit ‘drink (ipfv)’ versus vypit (lit.: ‘out-drink’), ‘to
drink up, drink to the end, empty (pfv)’, and German trinken ‘drink’ versus austrinken (lit.: ‘out-drink’), ‘to drink up, drink to the end, empty’. The difference
is that, in German, there is no syntactic or morphological rule that refers to
this opposition: all tense forms, for example, are formed in exactly the same
way. The choice between trinken and austrinken is simply a lexical one, so the
difference is one of derivation.
The difference between inflection and derivation often coincides with differences in morphological typology: inflection is often more transparently and
more regularly marked than derivation. Also, inflectional categories are typically more general over the lexicon than derivational categories. While these
are typologically significant tendencies, they are by no means necessary or universal. Russian aspect, for example, is very opaque and irregular. Sometimes,
as in the example of pit and vypit above, it is marked by a prefix, but sometimes it is signalled by a stem difference or by suppletion (e.g. ipfv otcvetat
vs pfv otcvesti ‘to bloom’; ipfv govorit vs pfv skazat ‘to say’). Transparency
172
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
of marking has to do not with inflection versus derivation but with the choice
between what we will describe below as concatenative and nonlinear, and also
with that between flexive and nonflexive morphology, structural distinctions
that will be reviewed in section 1.
The other frequent concomitant of inflection, generality over the lexicon, is
not a necessary correlate either. It is possible for inflectional categories to be
restricted to a subset of lexemes. The Nakh-Daghestanian languages Chechen
and Ingush, for example, limit verb agreement to about 30 per cent of the
verbs, yet the category is as sensitive to syntax as verb agreement is in English
or Russian. Case morphology is sometimes different for different parts of the
lexicon, e.g. following, as in some Australian languages (Silverstein (1976)), a
nominative–accusative schema for pronouns and an ergative–absolutive schema
for nouns; and in many languages, case paradigms are often defective (lacking
some cases) for some nouns but not others. These and other examples will be
discussed below.
In the following, we will concentrate mainly on the formal aspects of inflection – i.e. how and where inflectional categories such as case or agreement are
expressed – and on how such categories interact with syntax. The content of
inflectional categories is dealt with in detail in other chapters, (see vol. i, chapter
5, on mood and illocutionary force, and chapters 4 and 5 of this volume on gender, and tense, aspect and mood, respectively), and we limit ourselves to a brief
survey of those categories that are not covered or only partially covered in this
work.
The chapter is organized as follows. In section 1 we discuss the difference
between inflectional and lexical categories, review the notion of clitic, and
dissect the traditional typological parameters of morphology, i.e., phonological fusion, flexivity, and semantic density (exponence, synthesis). Sections 2
to 6 are devoted to further parameters of typological variation: the place and
position of inflectional markers, paradigm and template structure, and obligatoriness of marking. In section 7 we briefly review the content of a few
inflectional categories, and in section 8 we summarize some of the ways in
which inflection interacts with syntax, concentrating on agreement and case
marking.
1
Formatives and morphological types
1.1
Words versus formatives
At the heart of inflectional morphology are what we will call formatives. Formatives are the markers of inflectional information. (In (1) above, the endings
-e, -es, -en, and –s are all formatives.) They are different from words in that
Inflectional morphology
173
they cannot govern or be governed by other words,3 cannot require or undergo
agreement, and cannot head phrases: formatives are morphological entities,
words syntactic. In the better-known Western European languages, formatives
are typically realized through bound morphology and words through phonologically independent elements. Case markers (formatives), for example, are often
tightly fused endings (e.g. English he versus hi+m), while adpositions, words
which govern case and head PPs, are often free-standing units (e.g. with him,
where with governs objective case on the pronoun).
However, this need not be the case, and indeed often is not. In East and
Southeast Asian languages, case formatives are generally realized in the form
of phonologically free units, sometimes called ‘particles’. In Lai Chin, a TibetoBurman language of Burma, for example, phonologically bound affixes all have
a CV shape (i.e. they are monomoraic or ‘light’), whereas independent words
all follow a CVC or CV syllable canon (i.e. they are bimoraic or ‘heavy’). Case
markers, unlike agreement prefixes, follow the pattern of words:
(3)
Lai Chin (Tibeto-Burman; W. Burma)
Tsew Máŋ niʔ ʔ a-ka-thoʔŋ
t.
erg 3sg.a-1sg.p-hit
‘Tsew Mang hit me’
It is a general characteristic of these languages that the phonological notion of
the word is largely at odds with grammatical considerations: not only is the case
formative niʔ an independent phonological word, but so are both parts of the
proper name it marks in the example (Tsew and Máŋ). It is as if the rhythmical
articulation of speech goes its own ways – ways that are quite distinct from the
conceptual and syntactic segmentation, in which for instance Tsew Máŋniʔ is
a single, indivisible unit (a single grammatical word, as we will see).
Turning to words in the sense of syntactic units, we find variation in their
phonological independence no less than for formatives. While words are often
realized as free morphemes, many languages allow them to be (morpho-)
phonologically incorporated into other words, and a number of languages have
large sets of what are called lexical affixes which have their own syntactic properties (e.g. assigning specific cases and semantic roles to nps in the clause).
These are all issues of derivational morphology and compounding and are
discussed in chapters 1 and 6 of this volume. Another common instance of
3
We use the term govern in the traditional sense of determination by one word of the grammatical
form (i.e., the inflectional categories) of another. For instance, English prepositions govern the
objective case of pronouns: with me and not *with I. Russian prepositions lexically govern
different cases on their objects: s ‘with’ takes the instrumental (s drugom (with friend.instr),
‘with a friend’), bez ‘without’ takes genitive (bez deneg (without money.gen), ‘without money’),
and so on. In contrast to agreement, the governed category is not contained in the governing
word: contrast (1) above, where the gender is contained in the head noun that triggers gender
agreement (Lehrer is masculine, Lehrerin feminine).
174
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
phonologically bound words is cliticizing adpositions. This is a widespread
phenomenon, for instance, in Slavic and Indo-Aryan languages. Many Russian
prepositions, for example, are proclitic and behave much like prefixes: they
are subject to word-internal voicing and pretonic vowel reduction rules, e.g.
ot=druga4 ‘from friend:gen.sg’ is realized as [addrugə ], just as the singleword expression otdaj ‘give back’ is realized as [addaj]. That prepositions are
grammatical words on their own, however, is still evident from the fact that they
govern case, cf. ot=druga ‘from (the/a) friend’, with ‘friend’ in the genitive,
versus s=drugom (phonetically, [zdrugə m]) ‘with a friend’ where ‘friend’ is
in the instrumental case. Yet another instance of a phonologically bound word
arises from incorporation, to which we will briefly return below.
Words often develop into formatives through grammaticalization. It is no
surprise, therefore, that there are many transitional cases where the distinction
between, e.g., pronouns and agreement formatives, or between adpositions and
case markers, is blurred. See Hopper and Traugott (1993) and Lehmann (1995)
for surveys of grammaticalization phenomena.
1.2
Clitics
As we saw in the preceding section, the word versus formative distinction is
a purely syntactic one and crosscuts the phonological difference between free
and bound units. The traditional notion of a word conflates the syntactic and
phonological criteria: it implies that words are both syntactically and phonologically independent units and that affixes are in both respects dependent units.
With regard to the word, a distinction is often made between grammatical word
(in our terms, word as opposed to formative) and phonological (or prosodic)
word (free as opposed to bound unit). The same distinction could be made
for affixes as well: a grammatical affix would be a formative, a phonological
affix any bound unit (a bound formative, a lexical affix, an incorporated noun,
etc.). However, for most practical purposes it is safe to talk about formatives
and affixes without qualification. ‘Formative’ then refers to any inflectional
exponent whether bound or free, and ‘affix’ refers to any bound unit whether
grammatical or lexical.
A third notion besides word and affix that is often invoked is that of
clitic. The term is used in two quite different senses. In one sense, clitics are simply phonologically bound words, i.e., syntactic units like the
Russian prepositions that, as we saw above, are phonologically dependent
on their objects. In the other, typologically more important but often less
straightforward, sense, clitics are categorially unrestricted bound formatives,
4
Here and in the following, we mark clitic boundaries by ‘=’; affix boundaries are marked by
hyphens.
Inflectional morphology
175
i.e., formatives that are unrestricted as to the syntactic category of the word they
attach to. In this they contrast with affixes, which are usually more selective
in what host they take. Case affixes, for example, are usually restricted to nominals, tense affixes to verbs. A clitic like the Turkish interrogative =mi (and its
vowel-harmonic variants), by contrast, attaches to whatever word it marks as a
question, regardless of that word’s syntactic category, e.g. sen=mi ‘me?’ (pronoun), yarn=m ‘tomorrow?’ (adverb), or gördün=mü ‘did you see?’ (finite
verb: gör-dü-n ‘see-past-2sg’).
An important way in which formatives can come to be categorially unrestricted is that they can be affixed to phrases (constituents) rather than to words,
and then it does not matter what kind of word happens to be in the place at the
edge of the phrase where the formative is attached. A classic example is the
English genitive -s, which is suffixed to the right edge of an np regardless of
what element is found there. The rightmost word can even be a verb form, as
in examples like [np [np a guy you [V know]]’s idea]. In many languages, this
pattern is more general, comprising all case markers. In the Papuan language
Kâte, for example, case formatives cliticize to any word that ends an np (np-final
words are boldfaced):
(4)
Kâte (Finisterre-Huon; Papua New Guinea; Pilhofer (1933))
a. [np e=le
fiʔ ]=ko
mi fe-naŋ !
3sg=dest house=adl neg climb-1pl.hort
‘Let’s not climb into his house!’ (p. 113)
b. [np ŋ iʔ
moʔ -moʔ =sawa]=tsi
e-mbiŋ
man indef-indef=restr= erg do-3pl.rem.pt
‘Only some of the men did it’ (p. 110)
c. [np ŋ iʔ wiaʔ e-weʔ ]=tsi
dzika ki-tseyeʔ
man thing do-3sg.rem.pt=erg sword bite-3sg.rem.vol
‘The man who did these things should be killed’
(literally ‘should bite the sword’) (p. 142)
In (4a), the adlative =ko is cliticized to a noun; in (4b), the ergative =tsi is
attached to an indefinite pronoun which already hosts another clitic (=sawa
‘only’); and in (4c), we find the same ergative marker on a finite verb form,
indicating the function of the internally headed relative clause.5
Another common type of phrasal clitic is bound articles (determiners, specifiers) that attach not only to nominals but also to verb forms, where they function as nominalizers or relativizers. This phenomenon is particularly common
in many North and Central American languages.
Phrasal clitics typically have scope over the whole np they are attached to,
i.e. they modify the whole np expression although formally they are not copied
5
See vol. ii chapter 4 for more on relative clauses.
176
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
onto each element. The ergative in (4c), for example, specifies that the whole
expression ‘man who did these things’ is an agent, but, formally, the ergative
appears only on the last element (eweʔ ‘did’). Phrasal scope is an important
issue in np morphosyntax and we will return to it in section 8.2. However,
it is important to note that, while phrasal scope is a common concomitant of
clitics, this property is not a sufficient criterion for clitichood. To decide whether
something is a clitic, it is imperative to carefully analyse the category structure
of the language. An element is a clitic only if it can attach to hosts of diverse
categories.
In all of the preceding examples of clitics, they attach directly to the phrase
or word they modify. However, since clitics are category-neutral, this is not a
necessary condition. Clitics can also be detached from the element they modify.
In North Wakashan languages, for example, case formatives (=i ‘subject’, =x.a
‘object’, =sa ‘instrumental’) and determiners (=da) regularly attach to the
preceding phrase:
(5)
Kwakw’ala (Wakashan; NW America; S. R. Anderson (1985b))
nep’id=i=da
gə nanə m=x.a gukw =sa
t’isə m
throw=subj=det child=obj
house=instr rock
‘The child threw a rock at the house’
Here the instrumental formative on ‘rock’ is cliticized to ‘house’, whose object
marker is in turn cliticized to the preceding word ‘child’. While uncommon,
such patterns are also occasionally attested in Australian languages (Evans
(1995b)).
Some languages have detached clitics whose position appears to be syntactically unconstrained: they can attach to any constituent in the clause, depending
on the information structure. Such is the case in Tsakhur, discussed by Kibrik
(1997), where the auxiliary complex =wod can adjoin to any of the three words
in (6). If the clitic attaches to an np, that np is focussed (indicated by small
caps in the translation). If the clitic follows the verb, the entire proposition is
focussed.
(6)
Tsakhur (Nakh-Daghestanian; NE Caucasus; Kibrik (1997:306))
a. MaIhaImaId-e Xaw
alyaʔ a =wo=d
m.-erg
house(iv):nom build =aux=iv
‘Muhammed is building a house’
b. MaIhaImaId-e Xaw
=wo=d alyaʔ a
m.-erg
house(iv):nom =aux=iv build
‘Muhammed is building a house’
Inflectional morphology
177
c. MaIhaImaId-e =wo=d Xaw
alyaʔ a
m.-erg
=aux=iv house(iv):nom build
‘Muhammed is building a house’
A similar situation is found in the Tibeto-Burman language Belhare, where the
reported speech marker =phu/=bu can occur after any part of speech in the
clause, sometimes even on two at once (Bickel (2003)). While Tsakhur and
Belhare illustrate unconstrained clitic placement in the clause, some languages
spoken in the Kimberley region of Australia exemplify the same pattern on the
np level. Case markers in these languages can appear on any element of the np,
whether it is the head or not:
(7)
Gooniyandi (Bunuban; NW Australia; McGregor (1990:227))6
a. ngooddoo=ngga garndiwiddi yoowooloo
that=erg
two
man
‘by those two men’
b. marla doomoo=ngga
fist
clenched=erg
‘by a fist’
The most frequent position for detached clitics, however, is what is traditionally called the Wackernagel position (named after the famous Indo-Europeanist
who first described the phenomenon in 1892). This position is especially common for clause- and verb-level inflectional properties such as tense, mood,
and agreement. In the best-known examples, the Wackernagel position is right
after the first accented phrase or subconstituent of it. This is characteristic, for
instance, of South Slavic, Wakashan, and many Uto-Aztecan languages:
(8)
6
Luiseño (Uto-Aztecan; S. California; Steele (1976))
a. ʔ iviʔ ʔ awaal =up
waʔ i-q
dem dog
=3sg.pres bark-pres
‘This dog is barking’
b. ʔ iviʔ =up
ʔ awaal waʔ i-q
dem =3sg.pres dog
bark-pres
‘This dog is barking’
c. hamuʔ =up
wiiwiš kwaʔ -q
already =3sg.pres w.
eat-pres
‘She is already eating her wiwish’
McGregor (1990) calls the case clitics ‘postpositions’ because they have phrasal scope. As
discussed above, we restrict the term adposition to syntactic words, which govern case and head
adpositional phrases. See section 8.2 for further discussion.
178
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
In (8a), the tense- and agreement-indicating clitic =up attaches to the first np,
in (8b) to the first subconstituent of this np. Example (8c) shows that the host
phrase need not be an np, but can just as well be an adverbial phrase.
In Luiseño, and also in South Slavic languages not illustrated here (but see
Spencer (1991:355ff.)), the definition of the Wackernagel position rests on the
prosodic criterion of accent: the first accented string, whether constituent or
word. In other languages, the Wackernagel position is defined syntactically and
limited to complete phrases. As a result, in such languages clitics cannot attach
to subconstituents of phrases. In Warlpiri, a Central Australian language, clitics
occur after the first complete syntactic phrase:
(9)
Warlpiri (Pama-Nyungan; C. Australia; Hale, Laughren, and Simpson
(1995); T. Shopen (p.c.))
a. kurdu yalumpu-rlu =ka=jana
jiti-rni
jarntu wita
child dem-erg
=pres[3sg.a]=3pl.p tease-npt dog little
b. jarntu wita =ka=jana
jiti-rni
kurdu yalumpu-rlu
dog little =pres[3sg.a]=3pl.p tease-npt child dem-erg
c. jiti-rni
=ka=jana
jarntu wita kurdu yalumpu-rlu
tease-npt =pres[3sg.a]=3pl.p dog little child dem-erg
‘The child is teasing the little dogs’
In all of these examples, the clitic complex =ka=jana follows the first constituent (nps in (9a,b), a verb in (9c)), but it would not be possible for the clitics
to follow part of a constituent, e.g. kurdu ‘child’ or jarntu ‘dog’ alone in (9a)
and (9b), respectively.
On the level of phrases, second-position clitics are found in Wakashan languages of North America. In Nuuchahnulth (previously known as Nootka), for
example, determiner phrase (DP) formatives like the definite article =ʔi often
follow the first word of the phrase they modify:
(10) Nuuchahnulth (Wakashan; NW America; Nakayama (1997))
a. hin=a či
[DP minwaʔ ath=ʔ i] (p. 190)
there:mom=go.out.to.meet
British.soldier=def
‘They went out there to meet the British soldiers’
b. ʔ u-ch.i=n
[DP u=aq=ak=ʔ i
h.a kw a ] (p. 107)
her-married.to=mom
nice=very=dur=def girl
‘He got married to the very beautiful girl’
Since in (10a) the head noun minwaʔath ‘British soldier’ is the only word in
its DP, the article cliticizes to this word. In (10b), however, the article is found
on the preceding modifier u=aq=ak ‘very nice’ because this is now the first
Inflectional morphology
179
word in the DP. (Note, incidentally, that the pattern is the same on the clause
level: aspectual formatives like =n ‘momentaneous’ and entire words like
=ači ‘go out to meet’ are clitics in the clausal Wackernagel position.)
Wackernagel formatives are typically clitics, but not always. In many Kru languages of Western Africa, for example, negation is marked by a phonologically
free, tone-bearing second-position particle ni:
(11)
Bete (Kru; Ivory Coast; Marchese (1986:197))
ná dı̄bà ni fl lı̄ kɔ̀kɔ
my father neg eat chicken
‘My father doesn’t eat chicken’
Similarly, what are traditionally called clitics in Tagalog are mostly free formatives in the Wackernagel position: as phonologically independent units, they do
not lose stress or show any other reduction that is associated with phonological
affixes or clitics (S. R. Anderson (1992:204)). As illustrated by the following example, pronominal ‘clitics’ like siya ‘he’ are fixed in their Wackernagel
position:
(12)
Tagalog (Schachter and Otanes (1972:183))
a. nakita
siya
ni Pedro
saw:p.voice 3sg.nom gen p.
‘Pedro saw him’
b. *nakita
ni Pedro siya
saw:p.voice gen p.
3sg.nom
‘Pedro saw him’
Despite this special positioning, pronouns like siya are phonologically independent words, not clitics.
Free Wackernagel formatives often develop into bound clitics. Indeed, after
pronouns, the Bete negation particle (see (11) above) reduces to a high tone
clitic, which triggers vowel lengthening so as to have a place for realization
(i.e., `ɔ = } is realized as `ɔɔ).
(13)
Bete (Marchese (1986:197))
ním
3sg=neg drink
‘He doesn’t drink’
ɔ̀=
In some languages, there is considerable variation in the phonological dependence of Wackernagel formatives. Consider the following examples from Toura,
a Mande language spoken in the same area as Bete:
180
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
(14)
Toura (Mande; Ivory Coast; Bearth (1971))
a. nέ
ké ló-ı̀ı̄
boı́
child ind go-progr field
‘The child is going to the field’
b. nέ=`
lò
boı́
child=act go.decl field
‘The child goes to the field’
c. kó
ló boı́
1pl.opt go field
‘Let’s go to the field’
Interacting with verbal morphology, the Toura detached formatives express a
variety of tense–aspect and modal notions and are placed in the Wackernagel
position. Some of the formatives, such as the indicative mood particle ké in
(14a), are phonologically free. Others, e.g. the ‘actual’ (‘act’) mood marker
in (14b), are tonal clitics. After pronominal subjects, mood-indicating formatives are completely fused with their host (14c): compare kó ‘we (optative)’ in
(14c) with such forms as kwéé ‘we (actual, resultative)’ or kwéè ‘we (actual,
ingressive)’.
1.3
Degree of fusion
In the preceding section we noted that formatives are often phonologically fused
to their host, and that there is a gradient in how tightly they are fused. This is a
general characteristic of morphology, and it is suitable here to set up a scale of
phonological fusion:7
(15)
Fusion
isolating > concatenative > nonlinear
1.3.1
Isolating
At one end of the spectrum is complete isolation, where formatives are fullfledged free phonological words on their own. This is common in many Southeast Asian languages, and we saw an example in the Lai Chin ergative case
marker in (3) above. Most languages, however, have at least some isolating
formatives or ‘particles’. They are particularly frequent as markers of negation, mood, and various evidential and illocutionary categories (conveying such
notions as the source of evidence or the firmness of assertion).
7
The scale is also useful in derivational morphology, cf. chapter 1 in this volume.
Inflectional morphology
181
1.3.2
Concatenative (bound)
Concatenative8 formatives are phonologically bound and need some other word
for their realization. They include inflectional desinences as well as cliticized
formatives. The hallmark of concatenation is that formatives are readily segmentable. The paradigm example is Turkish number and case formatives, e.g.
ad-lar ‘name-pl’, ad-n ‘name-gen’, ad-lar-n ‘name-pl-gen’, where each formative is a clear cut sequence of phonological segments. In this regard, concatenative formatives are similar to isolated (independent) formatives. However,
unlike these, concatenative formatives trigger some phonological and morphophonological adjustments in the word they build up together with their
host – and the more such adjustments there are, the tighter the degree of fusion.
In Turkish, a well-known phonological adjustment is vowel harmony: when the
stem vowels have front instead of back articulation, the affixes follow suit: cf.
el-ler ‘hand-pl’, el-in ‘hand-gen’, el-ler-in ‘hand-pl-gen’ versus ad-lar, ad-n,
ad-lar-n just above.
Another, cross-linguistically very frequent, concomitant of concatenative
morphology is assimilation. This involves the spreading of phonological features across formative boundaries and can be illustrated by another example
from Turkish: the past tense marker -ti assimilates in voice to the preceding
consonant, cf. git-ti ‘go-past’ versus gel-di ‘come-past’.
Dissimilation, i.e. prohibition against the same features in adjacent segments,
is less common. An example is found in Belhare, where the coronal glide
in the non-past marker -yu forces a preceding /t/ to lose its coronal point of
articulation. As a result, this stop is realized by the default consonant of the
language, the glottal stop; cf., e.g., khaʔ-yu ‘s/he’ll go’ from khat- ‘go’ and -yu
‘nonpast’.
Another process sometimes affecting concatenative formatives is elision.
In Turkish, for example, stem-final /k/ is deleted in polysyllabic words when
followed by a vowel-initial suffix: e.g. çocuk-un ‘child-gen’ is realized as
/çocu n/. Vowels are particularly prone to elision. In Belhare, for example, /i/ regularly deletes before /u/, cf. -chi-u → ch-u in tar-he-ch-u-ŋ a
‘bring-past-du-3p-[1]excl’, i.e. ‘we (two, without you) brought it’, with
plain -chi in ta-he-chi-ŋa ‘come-pt-du-[1]excl’, i.e. ‘we (two, without you)
came’.
A final type of effect to be noted results from general prosodic constraints. Often, epenthetic elements are inserted when the concatenation of
an affix would result in a structure that violates the language’s syllabic
8
An alternative term is agglutinative, but, as we will see in section 1.4 below, this term traditionally
has connotations that go far beyond phonological boundness. We avoid the simpler term bound
because it is already functionally overloaded in other parts of grammatical description.
182
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
templates. In the Austronesian language Lenakel (spoken in Vanuatu), for example, a prefix–stem sequence like r-va ‘3sg-come’ is broken up by an epenthetic
vowel /-i/ so as to fit into the CV(C) syllable canon of the language, resulting in
r-iva ‘s/he came’. Where the syllable canon is satisfied, there is no epenthesis,
cf. r-imarhap-ik ‘s/he asked’ from r--im-arhap-ik ‘3sg-past-ask’ (Lynch (1978)).
Prosodic constraints can also lead to the truncation of extrasyllabic material. The
Belhare temporary aspect marker -hett, for example, is reduced to -het unless
there is some additional suffix whose syllable onset the second /t/ could form:
cf. ta-het ‘come-temp’, i.e., ‘s/he is coming’ versus ta-hett-i ‘come-temp-1pl’,
i.e., ‘we are coming.’
1.3.3
Nonlinear
Despite (morpho)phonological adjustment rules that blur formative boundaries,
concatenation results in linear strings of segmentable affixes. Nonlinear formatives, in contrast, are not segmentable into linear strings but are instead realized
by direct modification of the stem, i.e. by a simultaneous realization of formative
and stem. The best-known instance of this is morphology in Semitic languages.
In Modern Hebrew, for example, inflected word forms are the result of superimposing on a consonantal skeleton (e.g. g-d-r ‘enclose’) various vocalisms
indicating tense, mood, or voice: e.g. a-a ‘active’ (gadar ‘he enclosed’) versus u-a ‘passive’ (gudar ‘he was fenced in’), or -o- ‘future, imperative’ (gdor
‘enclose it!’) (Glinert (1989)). Similar in nature but more common is the superimposition of prosodic formatives (tone, stress, length) onto word stems. Many
Bantu languages, for example, distinguish temporal and modal values by purely
tonal patterns. In Kinyarwanda (Overdulve (1987)), one set of subordinate verb
forms (called ‘conjunctive’, used mainly for complement and adverbial clauses)
is distinguished from indicative forms by high tone on the agreement-marking
prefix, another set (‘relative’, used mainly for relative clauses) by high tone on
the last stem syllable: cf. conjunctive múkora ‘that we work’, relative mukorá
‘which we work (at)’, and indicative mukora ‘we work’ (all with agreement
prefix mu- ‘1pl’).
A different type of non-concatenative formative involves substitution or
replacement of a stem segment. Replacive formatives are common, for instance,
in Nilotic languages, where the plural of nouns is often formed by replacing the
stem-final vowel by one of a set of plural-marking endings, e.g. in Lango (Lwo;
Uganda; Noonan (1992)): bùrâ ‘cat’ versus bùrê ‘cats’, or láŋô ‘Lango’ versus
lə́ŋ´ ‘Langos’. This is sometimes accompanied, as the latter example shows,
by tonal substitutions and ablaut. In Ute (Uto-Aztecan; Givón (1980)), substitution of an individual phonological feature is recruited for case marking, cf.
nominative ta’wáci ‘man’ with devoicing of the final vowel versus accusative
ta’wáci ‘man’ without devoicing.
Inflectional morphology
183
Still another type of nonlinear formatives is subtractive formatives. This is
a rare phenomenon, but it is attested in the morphology of aspect in Tohono
‘O’odham (previously known as Papago; Uto-Aztecan; S. California; Zepeda
(1983:59–61)), e.g. him (ipfv) vs hi (pfv) ‘walk’, hink (ipfv) vs hin (pfv)
‘bark’, ʔeipig (ipfv) vs ʔeip (pfv) ‘peel’, med. (ipfv) vs me (pfv) ‘run’, etc.
Each perfective form is derived from the imperfective by subtracting whatever happens to be the final consonant. (In some cases, a side effect of this is
compensatory lengthening of the root vowel.)
A final type of nonlinear formatives to be mentioned is reduplication. An
example of this widespread phenomenon is given by Ancient Greek perfect tense
forms. Under reduplication, the first consonant of the stem is repeated together
with a supportive vowel /e/, e.g. dé-deikha ‘I have shown’ from deı́knūmi ‘I
show’, me-mákhēmai ‘I have fought’ from mákhomai ‘I fight’, dé-drāka ‘I
have done’ from dráō ‘I do’, etc. Reduplication can also be analysed as the
prefixation of a syllabic skeleton Ce-, where the value of C is determined
by the stem. On such a view (especially prominent in the theory of Prosodic
Morphology; McCarthy and Prince (1995)), reduplication would be a (very
tightly fused) concatenative affix rather than a nonlinear formative: the Ceskeleton would be a well-segmentable prefix and the value of C would result
from a simple phonological spreading rule, similar in fact to consonant harmony. Either way, it is evident that reduplication involves a tighter interlacing
of formative and stem material than what is common in canonical exemplars
of concatenative morphology. The degree of fusion is not as high, however,
as with the other subtypes of nonlinear fusion, and on the scale of fusion
in (15), reduplication holds a position between concatenative and nonlinear
morphology.
This completes the scale of fusion. It is important to note that the scale
applies to individual formatives, or sets of formatives, and not, as is sometimes
suggested, to languages as wholes. Isolating formatives, for example, are found
almost everywhere: virtually all languages have at least a few phonologically
unbound particles, regardless of the kind of formatives they employ in the
rest of their morphology. But mixtures of formative types can also be more
intricate. For instance, while in Arabic and Kinyarwanda most verbal categories
(aspect, mood, etc.) are expressed by nonlinear formatives, person and number
inflection is realized through concatenative affixes in both languages. Given
such distinctions, it clearly makes little sense to talk about concatenative or
nonlinear languages per se. However, languages differ in the degree to which
they employ one or the other type of formative, and from this point of view,
Kinyarwanda is more nonlinear, as a whole, than, say, Turkish, which has only
rudimentary and non-productive traces of nonlinear morphology borrowed from
Arabic (Lewis (1967: esp. 27f.)).
184
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
1.4
Flexivity (variance, lexical allomorphy, inflectional classes)
Another important parameter along which formatives vary typologically is flexivity. Flexive9 formatives come in sets of variants called allomorphs. Allomorphs are selected on lexical, i.e. item-based, principles. One example is
Lango plural marking discussed above: some nouns take endings in -ê, some
in -ı́, and so on. Conservative Indo-European languages have sets of case allomorphs which are selected depending on the declension class to which a noun
belongs. Thus, the Latin nominative singular formative is -s after most nouns,
but some nouns select an ending in -m (most of what are called the neuter
o-stems) and yet other nouns have a zero ending (the a-stems, among others);
cf., e.g., diē-s ‘day’ versus v¯nu-m ‘wine’ versus poēta-ø ‘poet’.
Instead of the formatives themselves, it can also be the stems that show
item-based alternations in flexive morphology. In German, for example, some
verbs show characteristic ablaut or umlaut patterns, where person- and tenseindicating formatives trigger different vocalisms. From tragen ‘carry’, we get
first person singular present trage ‘(I) carry’, second person singular present
trägst ‘(you) carry’, and third person singular past trug ‘(s/he/it) carried’, each
with different stem vowels. The set of verbs exhibiting such alternations is lexically restricted (to what are traditionally called ‘strong’ verbs). Thus, other
verbs (called ‘weak verbs’), such as nagen ‘gnaw’, show forms like nage (1st
sing. pres.), nagst (2nd sing. pres.) and nagte (1st sing. past) without stem
alternation. A similar but more complex example of this is provided by Dumi,
a Tibeto-Burman language of the Himalayas (van Driem (1993)). In this language, verbs divide into eleven conjugation classes, each characterized by a
distinct ablaut pattern. A selection is illustrated in table 3.1. Verbs of conjugation class ii (e.g. dzeni ‘to speak’ in table 3.1) have one stem form in the first
person singular and another one in the first person dual and plural non-past.
Verbs of class iii (e.g. botni ‘to shout’) have also two stems, but in this case
it is the first person singular and dual that share the same stem, distinct from
the first person plural. Verbs of class iv (e.g. l n ‘to commence’) have three
different stem forms. Conjugation and declension classes are an important and
frequent characteristic of inflectional paradigms, and we will return to them in
section 4.1.
The hallmark of flexive formatives is that their variation is item-based,
i.e. allomorphs are selected by some lexical contexts but not others. Some
9
The original, nineteenth-century term is ‘(in)flectional’ (German flektierend), but this term is also
(and nowadays more commonly) used in opposition to ‘derivational’ rather than as a concept
in morphological typology. To avoid confusion of ‘flexive’ and ‘inflectional’, we use flexivity
(rather than ‘flection’) as the abstract noun. Comrie (1981a) suggests ‘fusional’ but this conflates
flexivity with phonological fusion, a distinction for which we argue below.
Inflectional morphology
185
Table 3.1 Dumi nonpast verb inflection (selection)
1sg
1du.incl
1du.excl
1pl.incl
1pl.excl
ii: dzeni
‘speak’
iii: botni
‘shout’
iv: l n
‘commence’
dze-tə
dzi-ti
dzi-t
dz -k t
dzi-kta
bus-tə
bus-ti
bus-t
boʔ-kti
boʔ-kta
lo-tə
lu-ti
lu-t-i
l -kti
l -kta
stem forms are selected by one formative but not another, or some forms of
formatives are selected by some words but not others. In contrast, nonflexive
formatives are invariant across the lexicon and do not trigger formative-specific
or lexeme-specific stem alternation.10 The kind of variation they show is due
to general morphophonology or phonology: examples are Turkish vowel harmony and Belhare dissimilation, discussed in section 1.3.2 above. Note that
the distinction between flexive (item-based, allomorphic) and nonflexive (general, morphophonological) variation is independent of whether the variationtriggering context is defined morphologically or phonologically (see Kiparsky
(1996)). Examples of morphologically triggered allomorphy were discussed in
the preceding paragraphs. An example of phonologically triggered allomorphy
comes from Warlpiri. The Warlpiri ergative desinence is -ngku after disyllabic
stems (cf. kurdu-ngku ‘child-erg’) and -rlu after longer stems (cf. nyumpala-rlu
‘you(dual)-erg’: Nash (1986)). Although the triggering context is phonologically defined, the allomorphy does not result from a general phonological rule
that systematically associates the number of syllables with the choice between
/ngk/ and /rl/; the variation depends on a binary division of the lexicon into two
inflectional classes, and the formative is thus flexive.11
Since the nineteen century, morphological typology has tended to integrate
these various differences into a single scalar hierarchy:
(16)
isolating > agglutinative > flexive > nonlinear (or introflexive)
These have generally been presented as whole-language typologies, with prototypical examples probably being (respectively):
(17)
10
11
Chinese > Turkish > Latin > Arabic
Apart from irregular verbs; nearly every language has a few irregular or exceptional stems whose
forms do not follow the morphological rules, but these are not at issue here.
This kind of phonologically defined inflectional class distinction is common in many Australian
languages. Examples from Papuan languages are discussed in detail by Aronoff (1994).
186
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
This scale conflates the concatenative/nonlinear and flexive/nonflexive parameters. However, from a broader typological perspective, flexivity is orthogonal
to fusion, and all possible combinations of values on the two parameters are
attested, although not all are equally common. The commonest combination
is flexive–concatenative (and the traditional notion of flexive or ‘(in)flecting’
is often restricted to just this combination). Latin and Dumi illustrate this
type: while they display lexical allomorphy of stems and/or formatives, the
formatives are all more-or-less well-segmentable affixes, undergoing various
(morpho-)phonological rules. Latin case declension, for example, shows various patterns of assimilation and elision. Thus, the Latin nominative singular allomorph -s triggers regular (pan-lexical) voicing assimilation (e.g. leks
‘law’ from leg-s), vowel raising (lupus ‘wolf’ from lupo-s), and simplification
of consonant clusters (dens ‘tooth’ from dent-s). Likewise, Dumi stem–suffix
boundaries are subject to various morphophonological adjustments (van Driem
(1993:91–5)): an example in the paradigm selection in table 3.1 is the stem-final
glottal stop in boʔkti ‘we (incl.) shout’ and boʔkta ‘we (excl.) shout’ which is
a regular morphophonological variant of /t/ before /k/ (cf. infinitive bot-ni ‘to
shout’).
Flexive–nonlinear formatives are abundant in Afroasiatic languages, especially in Semitic languages, and the prominent role that these languages played
in early typology has motivated the label introflexive for just this combination
of parameter values. In Semitic languages, the verb lexicon is compartmentalized into several inflectional classes traditionally called binyanim (singular
binyan), and these classes determine much of the allomorphy of agreement and
tense–aspect morphology. In Modern Israeli Hebrew (Glinert (1989); Aronoff
(1994); Orin Gensler (p.c.)), for example, the past versus future opposition
is expressed by different vowel and consonant alternations dependent on the
binyan (as well as on subclasses of these): cf. gadar ‘he enclosed’ and yi-gdor
‘he will enclose’ in the first binyan versus kipel ‘he folded’ versus ye-kapel
‘he will fold’ in the second binyan. In the first (subclass of the first) binyan,
past is characterized by a-a and future by -o- vocalism, while in the second
binyan, past has i-e and future a-e vocalism. In addition to this, there is allomorphy of the agreement prefixes in the future tense: yi- in the first, ye- in
the second binyan. (In the past tense, third person masculine agreement is
zero-marked.)
Flexive–isolating formatives are by far the rarest combination, which is to say
that lexical allomorphy is much more common within phonological (prosodic)
words than across phonological word boundaries. But examples are found in
some Pama-Nyungan languages in Australia. Yidi has a set of suffixed formatives which Dixon (1977) calls non-cohering because they constitute their
own phonological word, i.e. are isolating. Some of these are at the same time
flexive since they show lexical allomorphy based on verbal conjugation class:
Inflectional morphology
187
the verbal comitative,12 for example, has two allomorphs, -ŋa ∼ lmaŋa. The
disyllabic allomorph is selected by what are called l- and r-stems, and it commences its own phonological word, cf., e.g., [word magil][word maŋ a l] from
magi-lmaŋa-lnyu ‘climb.up-appl:com-pt’. The phonological autonomy of the
formative is shown by the fact that it counts as its own domain for (i) stress
assignment rules, according to which primary stress falls on the first or the
first long-vowelled syllable of the word, and (ii) two rules that operate only in
phonological words with an odd number of syllables: a penultimate lengthening and a final syllable reduction rule, both operating here on the trisyllabic
sequence [ma.ŋ al.nyu], which is reduced to [ma.ŋ a l].
Another example comes from the Mesoamerican language Sierra Otomı́, in
which tense–aspect, person, and sometimes deixis are marked in a phonologically free formative that precedes the lexical verb word. These formatives show
flexivity conditioned by four lexical classes of verbs:
(18)
Sierra Otoḿ (Otomanguean; Mexico; Enrique Palancar (p.c.), from
Voigtlander and Echegoyen (1985))
dı́
pε̌ʔ tsʔ i ‘I keep (it)’ (conjugation class i)
dı́n
nú
‘I see (it)’ (conjugation class ii)
dı́dı́
hóki
‘I fix (it)’ (conjugation class iii)
dı́dı́m pε‘pfi ‘I work’ (conjugation class iv)
1sg.prs [verb]
n o n f l e x i v e i s o l at i n g : Nonflexive formatives are often isolating; and
the most common type of isolating formative is nonflexive. An example is case
in Lai Chin as in (3). In Lai Chin there is no allomorphic variation for the
ergative marker niʔ; it is the same for any noun in A function.
n o n f l e x i v e c o n c at e n at i v e : When nonflexive formatives are concatenative, they are traditionally called agglutinative. This combination of
parameter choices is also very common, one of the best-known examples being
Turkish morphology, discussed above in section 1.3.2.
n o n f l e x i v e n o n l i n e a r : Finally, nonflexive nonlinear formatives are
common with suprasegmental (tonal or accental) morphology. An example is
Kinyarwanda tense and mood inflection, as discussed in section 1.3.3.
In the discussion of fusion, we noted that languages sometimes use concatenative techniques for some categories and nonlinear techniques for others.
Similar splits are found in flexivity. Thus, while Russian case desinences are
mostly dependent on lexical declension classes and are therefore flexive (e.g.
12
The suffix has an applicative function, turning a comitative np into a direct object. Dixon
classifies this form as derivational, but on our criterion it is inflectional because its occurrence is
an obligatory response to at least some syntactic environments. An example where -ŋ a is used
in response to such an environment appears in (63) below.
188
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
dative sing. in -u with o-stems like stol-u ‘table’, but in -e with a-stems like
kryš-e ‘roof’), the dative, instrumental, and locative plural formatives are invariant, nonflexive formatives (e.g. dat. pl. stol-am ‘table’, kryš-am ‘roof’).13
1.5
Semantic density
The difference between flexive and nonflexive is often conflated with the question of whether grammatical and semantic categories are realized through separate formatives or whether they accumulate in a single formative, i.e with the
question of the semantic density of formatives. However, there is no logical
necessity for flexivity or, for that matter, phonological fusion (concatenative
versus nonlinear) to covary with semantic density (cf. Plank (1999)). There
are two dimensions of semantic density that need to be distinguished. One is
density on the level of the formative. This is traditionally called exponence. The
other dimension is density on the level of the word. This is traditionally called
synthesis. (For more on semantic density of words see Talmy, chapter 2 in this
volume.)
1.5.1
Exponence
Exponence refers to the degree to which different categories, e.g. number
and case, or person and tense, are grouped together in single, indivisible
formatives. Two prototypes are typically distinguished: cumulative and separative formatives. Cumulative formatives are common in Indo-European,
where number and case, for example, are most often cumulated into a single set of formatives. Thus, in Russian one gets gen. sg.-a ∼ -i, but gen.
pl. -ov ∼ -ø ∼-ej (allomorphs dependent on lexical declension class), where
there is no correspondence whatsoever between categories and parts of formatives (segments), i.e. no part of, say, genitive plural -ov that can be identified with genitive case or plural number. A concept related to cumulative
formatives is portmanteau formatives. Like cumulative formatives, portmanteau formatives express more than one category, but each of the categories
expressed corresponds to a separate formative that also exists in the language. For example, the French portmanteau form du ‘of the’ has corresponding formatives de ‘of’ and le ‘the’. By contrast, there are no case-only or
number-only formatives corresponding to the cumulative genitive formatives of
Russian.
The opposite of cumulative formatives is separative formatives. Separative
formatives encode one category at a time. In Turkish, for instance, case and
number are, as we saw, each expressed by their own suffix, e.g. gen. sg.
13
Such splits are not random. See Plank (1999) for a preliminary survey.
Inflectional morphology
189
-in, gen. pl. -ler-in (all with vowel-harmonic alternations). There is some tendency for nonflexive concatenative (‘agglutinative’) morphology to go with
separative exponence as in these Turkish examples and for flexive formatives
to be cumulative as in Latin or Russian, but this need not be so. The Turkish
first person plural ending -k (as in gör-dü-k ‘see-pt-1pl’, i.e. ‘we saw’) cumulates person and number, but is invariant across the lexicon and thus clearly
nonflexive. And flexive formatives can be separative. In the preceding section we saw that Dumi person, number, and tense formatives are flexive in
that they select lexically defined ablaut classes. But this does not entail that
the three categories are always expressed cumulatively: in a desinence like
-tə, for instance, -t marks nonpast tense separatively from -ə for first person singular (cf. -ø-ə ‘1st person singular past’). Thus exponence type is
independent of flexivity. And it is independent of fusion: although cumulative exponence is best known from bound morphology (e.g., Russian case–
number exponence as mentioned above), some West African languages have
isolating (free) formatives cumulating person agreement and tense/aspect/mood
values. This is illustrated for Hausa with two examples in the completive
aspect:
(19)
Hausa (Afroasiatic; West Africa; Newman (2000:569))
a. Mūsā yā
tàfi Bicı̀
m.
3sg.masc:compl go b.
‘Musa went / has gone to Bichi’
b. yârā
sun
ga mac¯`jı̂-n?
children 3pl.compl see snake-art.pl
‘Did the children see the snake?’
1.5.2
Synthesis and wordhood
The second dimension of semantic density, synthesis, applies to the level of the
word. It is customary to distinguish three prototypes on a scale from analytic
to synthetic to polysynthetic, measured by the number of formatives and lexical
roots that are bound together in one word: one or very few formatives and at
most one root in the case of analytic words, a moderate number of formatives
together with one root in synthetic words, and an abundant mixture of formatives and lexical roots in polysynthetic words. The relevant notion of word
here is the grammatical word, not the phonological word. The grammatical
word is defined as the smallest unit of syntax, technically the terminal node
or minimal projection (X0 ) in phrase structure. In He worked, for instance, he
and worked are grammatical words, one simple (he), one complex (worked,
containing the root work and the past tense suffix -ed). The formatives that
are combined into a single grammatical word (work+ed) cannot be interrupted
by phrasal constructions. They exhibit only morphological and phonological
190
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
dependencies (such as allomorphy selection and phonological fusion), but never
enter into syntactic dependencies such as agreement or government. They usually have fixed morpheme order, while the ordering of grammatical words with
respect to each other is commonly (though not always) freer. Typically, grammatical words are also phonologically coherent, but, as we saw in the Yidi
and Sierra Otomı́ examples in section 1.4, the phonological word can be a
smaller unit than the grammatical word. Phonological words can also be larger
units than grammatical words; common examples of this arise from cliticization. Russian prepositions, for instance, form a single phonological word with
the noun they govern. As we saw in section 1.1, however, the relationship
between preposition and noun is still one between independent grammatical
words.
Analytic words comprise just one or a very limited number of formatives or
they comprise just one lexical root. Examples are the words he (one pronominal root and one nominative case formative) and worked (one lexical root
and one past tense formative) we looked at just before. Sometimes analytic
words combine syntactically in the expression of inflectional categories. This
is called periphrastic expression. An example is the expression of tense and
aspect values by means of auxiliary constructions in European languages. The
English future (will go), for instance, involves two distinct grammatical words,
each comprising only one formative (the auxiliary will) or one root (go). The
two words occupy variable phrase-structural positions (Your friend will go vs
Will your friend go?) and the expression is interruptible by phrase-heading
expressions (He will definitely go). (Note that analytic words can be phonologically bound: English auxiliaries typically cliticize to preceding words (he’ll
go). They are no less grammatical words for being phonologically bound,
however.)
Words such as the auxiliary have in English, which comprises two formatives,
a tense-indicating root and an agreement marker (cf. has vs have), are traditionally classified as analytic just like single-formative auxiliaries. The notion
of synthetic words is usually restricted to words with more elaborate formative
sequences, but the difference between synthetic and analytic is one of degree,
and any categorial distinction ultimately misses the point. When flexive formatives are involved, synthetic words typically comprise two or three formatives
along with a lexical root, e.g. a verb root and formatives expressing aspect,
tense, and agreement, or a nominal root and formatives expressing case and
number. An example of this is found in Russian verb forms like vyp et ‘will
drink’, which express tense (future), aspect (perfective), person (third), and
number (singular). Nonflexive concatenative (i.e. ‘agglutinative’) morphology
usually allows longer and more complex synthetic words. An extreme example
of this is Turkish word forms like the one in (20), which includes no less than
ten formatives suffixed to the stem tan- ‘know’.
Inflectional morphology
(20)
191
Turkish
tan-ş-tr-l-a-ma-dk-lar-n-dan-dr
know-recip-caus-pass-pot-neg-nzr-pl-3poss-abl-3cop
‘It is because they cannot be introduced to each other’
(literally, ‘[it] is from their not being able to be made known to each
other’)
Synthetic words mostly involve bound (concatenative or nonlinear) formatives, but, as pointed out before, phonologically isolating formatives can also
combine into single grammatical words and can thereby constitute complex
synthetic words. Indeed, many isolating formatives in Southeast Asian and
East Asian languages form a single grammatical word together with the lexical
root they modify. In Lai Chin, for instance, formatives indicating agreement,
tense and mood are phonologically free, i.e. isolating, but any sequence of a
verb and one or more of these formatives constitutes a single, uninterruptible
word from the point of view of syntax:
(21)
Lai Chin (Ken Van Bik (p.c.))
a. na-tuk
nhaa
2sg.a-hit.with.stick:2 3pl.p
‘You will hit them’
b. na-kan-tuk
2sg.a-1pl.p-hit.with.stick:2
‘You will hit us’
làay
fut
làay
fut
In strings of formatives like these, the ordering of formatives is rigidly fixed
(*natuk laay nhaa), and this contrasts with the relatively free ordering of grammatical words in Lai Chin sentences. Moreover, the third person plural object
agreement marker nhaa is obligatory and is in direct opposition with the first
person plural object agreement marker which is a phonologically bound prefix
(kan-). Further, as shown by the contrast in (22), no phrasal constituent can
intervene:
(22)
Lai Chin (Ken Van Bik (p.c.))
a. *na-tuk
nhaa, ʔ ùy tsaw làay
2sg.a-hit.with.stick:2 3pl.p dog
fut
Intended: ‘You will hit the dogs’
b. na-tuk
nhaa làay, ʔ ùy tsaw
2sg.a-hit.with.stick:2 3pl.p fut dog
‘You will hit the dogs’
These facts suggest that the sequence natuk nhaa làay ‘you will hit them’ forms
one single, synthetic grammatical word, just like the expression ʔùy tsaw, which
192
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
is a single lexical item meaning ‘dog’. Thus, even though at first sight one is
tempted to compare the syntactic status of làay to that of the English auxiliary
will and the status of nhaa to that of the English pronoun them, làay and nhaa are
formatives within a word, and not grammatical words in syntactic combination.
This is all completely independent of the fact that Lai Chin grammatical words
often comprise several phonological words as shown in section 1.1 above.
While synthetic forms comprise only formatives and one lexical word (the
stem), matters are different with polysynthesis, which brings together not only
formatives but also incorporated stems and lexical affixes into a single grammatical word (an X0 in phrase structure). This phenomenon is widespread in
North American languages (for which it was first described by Du Ponceau in
1819), but it is also found elsewhere. The following examples of polysynthetic
words are from Siberia and Papua New Guinea, respectively:
(23)
Telqep Chukchi (Chukotko-Kamchatkan; Siberia; Dunn (1999))
utt-ə n-ejmew-jə w-ə -ninet=ʔ m
wood-caus-approach-collective-epen-3sg.A:3pl.p=emph
‘He brought them wood’
(24)
Yimas (Lower Sepik-Ramu; Papua New Guinea; Foley (1991))
paŋ kra-kaykaykay-kwalca-mpi-kulanaŋ -tal-kia-ntu-ŋ kt
1pauc.s-quickly-rise-seq-walk-start-at.night-rem.pt-pauc
‘We few got up at night and quickly started to walk’
In these verb forms, not only grammatical information like person, number, and
tense, but also various lexical concepts like ‘wood’ or ‘at night’ are expressed
by bound morphology.
Polysynthesis often involves grammatical words that are phonologically
coherent, but, as with synthesis, not necessarily. Indeed, unlike the Chukchi
example in (23), a Yimas string like the one in (24) consists of several phonological words,14 defined by stress and allophone distribution (Foley (1991:80–7)),
but the string nevertheless forms a single grammatical word in syntax (i.e. a
V0 or minimal projection constituent). Its grammatical wordhood is evidenced,
among other things, by the fact that the string involves purely morphological,
non-syntactic dependencies: the appearance of the paucal suffix -ŋkt, for example, is contingent on the presence of a person-indicating prefix, here paŋkra- ‘we
few’. The suffix cannot appear if the person reference is established by means
of syntactically independent pronouns rather than prefixed formatives. The first
person paucal pronoun, for example, is incompatible with the paucal suffix
because the pronoun projects its own analytic grammatical word. (First person
14
This has also been shown for polysynthetic words in the two North American languages Cree
(Algonquian) and Dakota (Siouan); see Russell (1999). The analysis of Algonquian and similar
languages (e.g. Kutenai) as polysynthetic has become a matter of debate, however. See, e.g.,
Goddard (1988) and Dryer (2000) for controversial discussion.
Inflectional morphology
193
reference is expressed periphrastically for first person paucal, compensating for
the lack of a corresponding synthetic form.)
(25)
Yimas (Foley (1991:223))
paŋ kt ŋ kul-cpul(*-ŋ kt)
1pauc 2du.p-hit(*-pauc)
‘We few hit you two’
If suffixing -ŋkt were possible here, this would mean that the second word was
agreeing with the first and that the relationship between the two was therefore
one of syntactic agreement. By analogy, one could then argue that -ŋkt appears
in (24) above because of agreement with paŋkra-; the relationship between
these two elements would then be a syntactic relationship holding between
two distinct grammatical words. A case could then be made for analysing
the expression as analytic. But the fact is that the distribution of -ŋkt is not
governed by agreement between grammatical words but is instead subject to
morphological rules that are operative within, rather than across, grammatical
words.
One of the typologically most important characteristics of polysynthesis is
that pronominal and even lexical arguments are incorporated into their governing verb. The Yimas words in (24) and (25) exemplify incorporated pronouns:
in (24) the first person paucal prefix paŋkra- functions as an affixed subject pronoun. In (25), the second person dual prefix -ŋkul functions as an incorporated
object pronoun, while the subject pronoun paŋkt ‘we few’ is not incorporated.
The Chukchi example in (23) illustrates incorporation of a lexical argument.
The direct object utt-‘wood’ is incorporated into the verb (as a regular response
to low discourse saliency of the object; see Dunn (1999)). Incorporated elements are no longer grammatical words heading their own constituents in the
clause. They typically lose many of their syntactic abilities and could thus be
called semi-words. We will briefly come back to pronoun incorporation in our
discussion of agreement systems in section 8.
2
Locus
Locus is the term we propose for what has been known as head/dependent marking (Nichols (1992)). The essential distinction can be illustrated by examples
from Hungarian and English (the relevant formatives are in boldface):
(26)
Hungarian (Uralic)
az ember ház-a
the man house-3sg
‘the man’s house’
(27)
English
the man-’s house
194
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
In both of these, the possessed noun ‘house’ is the syntactic head of the construction and the possessor is non-head. Hungarian puts an inflectional suffix on
‘house’ (the head) while English puts it on the possessor. The Hungarian inflectional suffix is a possessive suffix which agrees in person and number with the
possessor; the English one is a case clitic and not an agreement marker. As these
examples show, the syntactic relation of adnominal possession can be reflected
by placing a formative on either the head or the non-head of the phrase. The
inflectional categories differ, but not because the syntactic relation they reflect
differs; rather, certain inflectional categories have affinities for one or another
locus. Person and number, for instance, are almost always on heads and almost
always due to agreement, while case is on non-heads and is not always (and in
fact not often) due to agreement.
The locus of marking can be not just on the head or the non-head, but also
on both or on neither. The following examples give some idea of the variety
of locus types and the variety of inflectional categories that mark them, using
possessive nps (Nichols (1992:49ff.)).
On head (h e a d m a r k i n g ):
(28)
Tadzhik (Indo-European; J. R. Payne (1980:167–8))
xona-i
padar
house-ez father
‘father’s house’
(29)
Abkhaz (West Caucasian; Hewitt (1979:116))
à-č’k◦ ’ə n yə -y◦ nə̀
art-boy 3sg-house
‘the boy’s house’
In (28), the formative -i on the head noun ‘house’ indicates that there is a
dependent present in the np but that it does not agree with it. This construction
is known as izafet or ezafe in the grammatical traditions of many Turkic and
Iranian languages (and glossed here as ‘ez’). In (29), the dependency relation is
indicated by possessor agreement, again marked on the head. This is the inflectional category generally known as possession or possessive affixes, common in
languages of Siberia, the Himalayas, and the Americas. For more on possessor
agreement, see sections 4.1 and 8.1 below.
On dependent (d e p e n d e n t m a r k i n g ):
(30)
Chechen (Nakh-Daghestanian; Caucasus)
dee-n
aaxcha
father-gen money
‘father’s money’
Inflectional morphology
195
On both (d o u b l e m a r k i n g ):
(31)
Nogai (Turkic; Baskakov (1963:539)):
men=im kullyg-ym
1sg=gen work-1sg
‘my work’
On neither (j u x ta p o s i t i o n ):
(32)
!Kung (Khoisan; S. Africa; Snyman (1970:92)):
dzheu =
| xanu
woman book
‘woman’s book’
On neither (d e ta c h e d m a r k i n g ):
(33)
Tagalog (Austronesian; Philippines; Schachter and Otanes
(1972:116, 123)):
a. nasa mesa=ng
libro
on table=link
book
‘the book on the table’
b. libro=ng
nasa mesa
book=link on table
‘the book on the table’
This Tagalog example is another instance of a Wackernagel position clitic on
the np level (cf. example (10) in section 1.2). We call this marking detached
because the clitic is not attached to either the head (libro ‘the book’) or the
dependent (nasa mesa ‘on the table’). It is placed between the two.
Marking can also be split. Many languages use two different loci of marking
to implement what is often termed ‘alienable’ versus ‘inalienable’ possession.
The ‘inalienables’ are often nouns such as kin terms and body parts (called
‘inalienable’ because they typically cannot be sold or given away) and the
‘alienables’ are the rest. It is common for ‘inalienable’ possession to be headmarked and ‘alienable’ not, as in (34):
(34)
Amele (Madang; New Guinea; Roberts (1987:139)) (‘mouth’ and
‘son’ are inalienable)
a. ija na jo
1sg of house
‘my house’
b. Naus na jo
n.
of house
‘Naus’s house’
196
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
c. ija co-ni
1sg mouth-1sg
‘my mouth’
d. Naus mela-h-ul
n.
son-3sg-pl
‘Naus’s sons’
or for ‘inalienable’ possession to have no marking and ‘alienables’ to have case
marking or the like:
(35)
Dyirbal (Dixon (1972:61, 105))
a. balan ugumbil mambu
[inalienable]
det woman
back
‘the woman’s back’
b. bayi waŋ al
baŋ ul
yaa-ŋ u [alienable]
det boomerang det.gen man-gen
‘the man’s boomerang’
The different locus types can also be distinguished in the marking of clause
relations. Here are examples of languages that mark the relations of subject
and object only on the verb (head marking, as the verb is the head of the
clause):
(36) Abkhaz (West Caucasian; Georgia; Hewitt (1989:67))
a-p◦w ə s
a- aca a- arp Ø-yə -zə -lə - w a-yt
det-woman det-man det-shirt 3sg.p-3sg.m.io-for-3sg.f.a-wash-aor
‘the woman washed the shirt for the man’
only on the arguments (dependent marking, as the arguments are the dependents):
(37)
Martuthunira (Dench (1994:75))
ngayu
tharnta-a nhuwa-lalha parla-ngka
1sg.nom euro-acc spear-past hill-loc
‘I speared a euro in the hills’
on both:
(38)
Belhare
unchik-ŋ a yeti
n-thuu-t-u?
3nsg-erg what.nom 3nsg.a-cook-npt-3p
‘What do they cook?’
and on neither:
Inflectional morphology
(39)
197
Thai (Jenny (2001), from a popular Thai song)
phruŋ 2 nii3 chan4 cə
rak3 khun tə lɔɔ t1 pai
tomorrow 1fam prospective love 2hon whole continuative
‘Tomorrow I will love you forever’
Certain grammatical categories favour particular loci, and the traditional
terminology for various grammatical categories contains implicit reference to
locus of marking. Case, for instance, is always marked on dependents, and in
fact case can be defined as dependent-marked affixal indication of clause and
phrasal relations. The same information can perfectly well be marked on heads,
but then it is not called case. In the following Georgian examples, the form of
the first person agreement prefix indicates the role of the first person referent:
subject in the first example, object in the second.
(40)
Georgian (Kartvelian; Caucasus)
a. v-xedav
1sg.a-see
‘I see (him/her/it)’
b. m-xedav
1sg.p-see
‘You see me’
In the following examples from a Mayan language, the agreement markers are
glossed with case names: abs = absolutive and erg = ergative.
(41)
Jacaltec (Mayan; Mesoamerica; Craig (1977:122, 111))
a. x-Ø-haw-il
naj
asp-abs.3-erg.2-see 3sg
‘You saw him’
b. xc-ach
w-abe
asp-abs.2 erg.1-hear
‘I heard you’
3
Position
By position we mean the location of an inflectional formative relative to the word
or root that hosts it. The formative may precede the host, follow it, occur inside
of it, be detached from it, or various combinations of these. There is a standard
terminology which accounts for most of these positions together with the formative type and degree of fusion. Table 3.2 expands this terminology somewhat.
Latin prepositions or truncated adverbs label the position categories. Types that
may not be self-evident or have not been illustrated earlier are explained and
exemplified in what follows.
198
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.2 Typology of positions and formatives. * = example below in this
section
Position
Formative type and/or degree of fusion
Prae
Preposed free formative *
Proclitic
Prefix
Initial reduplication (cf. Ancient Greek example in section 1.3.3 for
illustration)
Substitution (cf. section 1.3.3)
Ablaut (i.e. bare ablaut; if ablaut is triggered by an affix, the combination of
affix and ablaut constitutes simulfixation, described below)
Infix (including Interposition *)
Endoclisis *
Subtraction (cf. Tohono ‘O’odham example in section 1.3.3)
Prosodic formatives (cf. Kinyarwanda example in section 1.3.3)
Final reduplication
Suffix
Enclitic
Postposed free formative
Simulfix, simulclitic, etc. (including circumfix) *
Detached (word or formative, cliticized or free; see sections 1.2 and 2 for
discussion)
In
Post
Simul
None of the above
Examples:
F r e e f o r m at i v e s Like affixes, free (or isolating) formatives are typically fixed in their position. Plural words and other grammatical number words
(Dryer (1989)) are often free formatives. The singular and plural words of
Yapese, shown in the following examples, are in a fixed position in the nominal
modifiers.
(42)
Yapese (Austronesian; Dryer (1989:868) from J.T. Jensen
(1977:155))
a. ea rea kaarroo neey
art sg car
this
‘this car’
b. ea pi kaarroo neey
art pl car
this
‘these cars’
E n d o c l i s i s A clitic inserted into a word constitutes endoclisis. The phenomenon is rare, but well documented for Udi by Harris (2000). In (43), the
person–number agreement marker is a clitic ( = first element of split simplex
stem; see Harris for the full argument that =z= is a clitic):
Inflectional morphology
(43)
199
Udi (Nakh-Daghestanian; Caucasus; Harris (2000))
kaghuz-ax a=z=q-e
letter-dat =1sg=receive-aor
‘I received the letter’
I n t e r p o s i t i o n Interposition is a typologically and historically distinct
subtype of infixation. In general, infixation places formatives into a phonologically or prosodically defined environment (e.g. after the stem’s onset consonant(s), or after the first syllable), but in the case of interposition, the environment is more nearly morphological, reflecting morphologized infixation
or petrified derivational morphology or compounding. Interposition typically
involves formatives placed between the two parts of a bipartite stem. A bipartite
stem is a stem where only part, but not the whole, is the target of morphological
rules (affixation, reduplication, mutation, particle hosting, etc.), and the location
of the boundary between the two parts is morphologically defined, i.e. neither
semantically (e.g., by scope as in the juxtaposition of independently inflected
stems) nor phonologically (e.g. by syllable structure as with infixation) (Jacobsen (1980); DeLancey (1996, 1999)). Interposition in verb stems is particularly
well known in languages spoken in the American Pacific Northwest, but it is
also attested in various Caucasian and Himalayan languages:
(44)
Washo (Jacobsen (1980))
suʔ m-te -ı́tiʔ
throw-pl-down
‘to throw down repeatedly’
(45)
Andi (Nakh-Daghestanian; Caucasus; Gudava (1959:197))
a-b-ch-o
wash-gender.agreement-wash-past
‘(I/you/he/she/we/they) laundered, washed (it)’
(46)
Belhare15
a. la-ŋŋ -u-yakt-he
dance-3nsg.s-dance-ipfv-past
‘They were dancing’
b. tha-tok-ka-tok
n-ca-he
(< tha-tok- ‘to know s.o.’)
know-know-recip-know 3nsg.s-aux-past
‘They knew each other’
15
Phonologically, these strings bracket into two or more prosodic words: [laŋ ][ŋ uyakthe],
[tha][tokka][tok], but, syntactically, they are indivisible wholes, i.e. single grammatical words;
cf. the discussion of synthesis in section 1.5.2.
200
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
In all these examples a formative is affixed only to the second part of the
stem. In (46b), we find in addition, a process of reduplication affecting only
one part of the stem (tok-). Sometimes, the two parts of bipartite stems have
independent meanings and the properties of independent verb stems, as in the
Washo example, where šuʔm means ‘throw’ and determines the transitivity
of the complex, and ı́tiʔ means ‘down’ and shows the morphophonological
behaviour of independent stems. But despite its position on only one stem part,
the plural affix has scope over both parts simultaneously, and the stem as a
whole behaves as a single grammatical word (a terminal node) in the syntax
(see Jacobsen (1980)). The elements ach- ‘wash’ in Andi and lau-‘dance’ in
Belhare are simplex expressions that cannot be further analysed into component
parts, at least not synchronically.
It is chiefly verbs that are bipartite, but bipartite nominal stems that undergo
interposition are attested in Limbu (Tibeto-Burman, Nepal). The third person
singular possessive form of teʔlphuŋ ‘garments, clothing’, for instance, is kudeʔl-ku-bhuŋ (van Driem (1987:27)), with the possessive marker ku- occurring
not only at the beginning of the word but also at the beginning of its second
(etymologically separate) part. (This example also illustrates simulfixation, as
is discussed just below.)
S i m u l f i x at i o n : This term, which was first proposed by Hagège
(1986:26), involves several tokens of a single morpheme, realized at different places in the word. The most common subtype is circumfixation (as, e.g.,
the circumfix ge- . . . -t marking German participles such as ge-lieb-t ‘loved’),
but there are other options. The formatives can be both suffixes, both prefixes,
or one can be internal, the other external. The Belhare perfect exemplifies concatenative simulfixes of which both pieces (-ŋa and -ha) are postposed:
(47)
Belhare
khai-ŋ a-ŋŋ -ha
go-perf-1sg-perf
‘I’ve gone’
Combinations of internal and external marking are abundant in Germanic languages, e.g. in words such as English children, whose plural number is marked
by both ablaut (internal) and a suffix (postposed). A more complex example of this kind is found in Lak, where in some verbs gender is marked both
by initial mutation (b/d/Ø) and, internally, by ablaut of the medial consonant
(v/r).
(48)
Lak (Nakh-Daghestanian; Caucasus; Zhirkov (1955:93, 1962:418))
a. b-u-v-na
b. d-u-r-na
Inflectional morphology
201
c. Ø-u-v-na
g e n d e r . a g r e e m e n t -go-g e n d e r . a g r e e m e n t -p a s t
‘went’ (different genders)
The Limbu example used above to illustrate interposition (ku-deʔl-ku-bhuŋ
‘his/her clothes’) also illustrates simulfixation: it has one token of the possessive
formative preposed and one interposed into a bipartite stem.
The apparent position of affixes in a word can be deceptive, so that what
appears to be (say) an infix to the naked eye proves to be a prefix or suffix when
the morphological analysis has been done. For example, Tagalog infixes have
been successfully analysed as prefixation under prosodic constraints against
closed syllables (see McCarthy and Prince (1995), and Crowhurst (1989) for
critical discussion): cf. um-ibig ‘love’ versus s-um-ulat ‘write’ and gr-um-adwet
‘graduate’. Here, the actor-voice prefix um- is forced to shift to after the first
onset in order to avoid the ungrammatical closed syllables *( um) (as in *umsulat, *um-gradwet) or *( gum) (as in *gumradwet).16
Another potential source of confusion in the analysis of affix positions is
internal constituent structure within inflected and derived words. In the following examples from the Daghestanian language Kubachi Dargi, the gender
formatives b and w appear both at the beginning and in the middle of the word:
(49)
Kubachi Dargi (Nakh-Daghestanian; Magometov (1963:76))
a. b-e n-ka-b-išši-j
gender-in-down-gender-go-inf
‘insert, put in’ (B gender)
b. w-e n-ka-w-išši-j
gender-in-down-gender-go-inf
‘go in’ (W gender)17
This is not simulfixation, however, but simultaneous prefixation to both a verbal
preverb and the verb root.
4
Paradigms
Inflectional systems are typically organized into paradigms of variable size,
ranging from, e.g., the two-member paradigm of English verb agreement, with
third person singular versus everything else (e.g. goes vs go) to large case
paradigms. Plank (1991:16) notes that very large case inventories are found
only in languages with separative exponence and do not occur in languages
with chiefly cumulative exponence (see section 1.5.1).
16
17
Following standard conventions, ‘’ stands for syllable and the parentheses are syllable brackets.
The verb is ambitransitive, and is interpreted as transitive (semantically causative) when it agrees
in the inanimate B gender but as intransitive when it agrees in the animate W gender.
202
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.3 Latin noun paradigms
Singular:
Nom.
Voc.
Acc.
Gen.
Dat.
Abl.
Plural:
Nom.
Voc.
Acc.
Gen.
Dat.
Abl.
‘wolf’
‘war’
‘road’
‘foot’
‘attack’
lupus
lupe
lupum
lup¯
lupō
lupō
bellum
–
bellum
bell¯
bellō
bellō
via
–
viam
viae
viae
viā
pēs
–
pedem
pedis
ped¯
pede
impetus
–
impetum
–
–
impetū / -e
lup¯
lup¯
lupōs
lupōrum
lup¯s
lup¯s
bella
–
bella
bellōrum
bell¯s
bell¯s
viae
–
viās
viārum
vi¯s
vi¯s
pedēs
–
pedēs
pedum
pedibus
pedibus
impetūs
–
impetūs
–
–
–
The organization of inflectional forms into paradigms brings with it a series of
properties not typically found in other parts of morphology: inflectional classes,
syncretism, defectivity, suppletion, deponence, and eidemic resonance. Case
inventories and the terminology for them will be discussed briefly at the end of
this section.
4.1
Inflectional classes
Case paradigms are paradigms par excellence and display most of the important properties of paradigms. Tables 3.3 and 3.4 show Latin and Chechen case
paradigms, respectively. (Gaps in some of the Latin paradigms illustrate defectivity, discussed below.)
The Latin nouns shown in table 3.3 fall into distinct declension classes based
on the stem-final (traditionally,‘thematic’) vowels (-u∼-o vs -a vs -u) or consonants (-d in ped- ‘foot’) and the considerable allomorphy of the endings
(e.g. nominative singular -s vs -m vs zero). The Chechen nouns in table 3.4
have mostly the same endings but considerable variation of stems. The noun
‘daughter-in-law’ has stem ablaut, and most nouns have stem extensions in the
plural paradigms: -ar- in ‘daughter-in-law’, -arch- in ‘pig’, -o- in ‘mother’,
-an- in ‘grief’. The -i- found in several oblique cases in the singular of ‘grief’
and ‘pig’ is another extension, absent in the nominative, ergative, and (synchronically, though probably not diachronically) allative. Extensions are lexically conditioned and carry no meaning (though they may have their origins in
frozen derivational or inflectional suffixes). The Chechen system of extensions
Inflectional morphology
203
Table 3.4 Chechen noun paradigms (all-Latin no-diacritics transcription; see
http://socrates.berkeley.edu/∼chechen for this transcription)
Singular:
Nom.
Gen.
Dat.
Erg.
All.
Ins.
Lat.
Csn.
Plural:
Nom.
Gen.
Dat.
Erg.
All.
Ins.
Lat.
Csn.
‘window’
‘daughter-in-law’
‘mother’
‘grief’
‘pig’
kor
kuoran
kuorana
kuoruo
kuorie
kuoraca
kuorax
kuoral
nus
nesan
nesana
nesuo
nesie
nesaca
nesax
nesal
naana
neenan
naanna
naanas
neenie
neenaca
neenax
neenal
baala
baalin
baalina
baaluo
baalie
baalica
baaliax
baalial
hwaqa
hwaqin
hwaqina
hwaquo
hwaqie
hwaqica
hwaqiax
hwaqial
kuorash
kuoriin
kuorashna
kuorasha
kuorashka
kuorashca
kuoriax
kuorial
nesarii
nesariin
nesarshna
nesarsha
nesarshka
nesarshca
nesiax
nesial
naanoi
naanoin
naanoshna
naanuosha
naanoshka
naanoshca
naanoix
naanoil
baalanash
baalaniin
baalanashna
baalanasha
baalanashka
baalanashca
baalaniax
baalanial
hwaqarchii
hwaqarchiin
hwaqarchashna
hwaqarchasha
hwaqarchashka
hwaqarchashca
hwaqarchiax
hwaqarchial
is a modest version of the elaborate systems found in Daghestanian languages
(Kibrik (1991)), distant sisters of Chechen.
The notion of declension class, or more generally inflectional class, was
devised traditionally to handle paradigms like the Latin ones, where at first
glance there seem to be different series of endings (-us, -um, -¯, -ō in ‘wolf’;
-a, -am, -ae, -ā in ‘road’; -Ø, -em, -is, -¯, -e in ‘foot’, etc.). In fact, though,
there are two sets of differences, one resulting from the vowels (traditional
‘thematic vowels’) that expand the word stem (-u ∼ -o in ‘wolf’ vs -a ∼ -ā in
‘war’ vs Ø in ‘foot’ vs -u in ‘attack’) and one resulting from differences in the
endings themselves (e.g. nominative singular -s or -Ø or -m; genitive singular
-¯ or -(i)s, nominative plural -i or -ēs); these two kinds of differences can also
occur simultaneously (e.g. nom. sing. in Ø with a-stems, but in -s or -m with
others). The thematic vowels are rather like stem extensions; this means that
the Chechen and Latin case paradigms differ in degree of morphophonemic
transparency (Latin being less transparent) rather than in morphological type.
A full taxonomy of variation in stem and ending adequate to typologize inflectional paradigms would be a three-way distinction of variation for both stems
and endings: lexically conditioned, i.e. lexeme-based, allomorphic variation;
category-based allomorphic variation, i.e. allomorphy dependent on specific
204
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.5 Typology of inflectional classes
Formative:
Stem
Lexeme-based
allomorphy
Category-based
allomorphy
No regular allomorphy
Lexeme-based
allomorphy
Category-based
allomorphy
No regular
allomorphy
Latin nouns
Latin and Polish verbs
[unattested in our
sample]
Polish nouns, Anêm
possession
Newar verbs
Chechen verbs, nouns,
Dumi verbs (1.4)
Belhare verbs
Germanic weak verbs,
Ossetic sg./pl. case
Finnish nouns
Table 3.6 Belhare verb paradigm (selection). The k∼g alternation in
yak- and -ka is morphophonologically conditioned; -ʔ and -yu mark
nonpast (the allomorphy is determined by prosodic structure), -he
past, -ŋ e resultative, and -kone inconsequential
1sg
2sg
3sg
nonpast
past
resultative
inconsequential
yau-ʔ-ŋ a
yau-ka
yak-yu
yag-he-ŋ a
yag-he-ga
yag-he
yau-ŋ e-ŋ a
yau-ŋ e-ga
yau-ŋ e
yak-kone-ŋ a
yak-kone-ga
yak-kone
inflectional categories but general across all lexemes; and no allomorphic
variation.
Lexeme-based allomorphy of stems, or stem classes
Stem classes are present when stems differ (because of ablaut, stem extensions, stress shift, etc.) when inflected for the same category, and the differences are lexically (and not [morpho-]phonologically) conditioned. Examples
are the Chechen and Latin paradigms in tables 3.3 and 3.4 above. In Chechen,
for example, the vowel ablaut in ‘daughter-in-law’, or the choice of stem extensions (-ar-, -an-, etc.) in the plural, is a purely lexical and unpredictable matter.
In Latin, as argued above, the traditional declension classes are in fact lexical
differences of thematic vowel (obscured by regular morphophonology such as
vowel raising in the nominative singular lupus < lup-o-s or monophthongization
in the genitive singular lup¯ < lup-o-i; see section 1.4 above).
c at e g o r y - b a s e d s t e m a l l o m o r p h y In some languages, all stems
have the same allomorphy, selected by specific morphological categories or
paradigms. Belhare verbs all undergo the same stem alternations from person
to person and from tense to tense. The verb yakma ‘to stay overnight, find
shelter’, for example, has the two stem forms yak- and yau-, and table 3.6
Inflectional morphology
205
Table 3.7 Verb paradigms in Latin and Polish
Latin ‘love’
1sg
2sg
3sg
1pl
2pl
3pl
Polish ‘write’
Present
Perfect
Present
Past
amo
amās
amat
amāmus
amātis
amant
amāvi
amāvisti
amāvit
amāvimus
amāvistis
amāverunt
pisze
piszesz
pisze
piszemy
piszecie
pisza
pisaem
pisaeś
pisa
pisaliśmy
pisaliście
pisali
shows how they are distributed over a selection of forms. The primary stem
here is yak-, and the secondary stem -yau is derived from this by imposing a
CVV syllable structure: the original root coda /k/ is vocalized while retaining
its tongue and velum positions (i.e. its point of articulation and nasality/orality),
e.g. yak- ∼ yau- ‘stay overnight’, yaŋ- ∼ yaũ- ‘carry by hand’. Bilabials are
exempted from this and remain unchanged (e.g. lap- ‘catch’). CV roots are
fitted into the CVV shape by epenthesis of /i/ or, after /i/, /u/ (e.g. so- ∼ soi‘wait’, khi- ∼ khiu- ‘quarrel’, etc.). These rules hold across the lexicon; the
stem allomorphy is entirely regular and exclusively depends on the person and
tense choice: the secondary stem occurs before the nonpast allomorphs -t and
-ʔ, and before the resultative (and perfect) markers -ŋe (and -ŋa), among others.
N o s t e m a l l o m o r p h y Stems need not behave differently when
inflected for the same categories. The noun stems of Finnish, for example,
and most noun stems of Polish, behave essentially alike and are essentially
unchanged (except for automatic phonological and morphophonemic alternations) when inflected for case. For Finnish paradigms, see Eliot (1890:26ff.);
Serebrennikov and Kert (1958); Branch (1987).
F o r m at i v e c l a s s e s When inflectional formatives have lexeme-based
allomorphy we have formative classes. For example, the Latin nouns shown
above have different sets of endings.
C at e g o r y - b a s e d f o r m at i v e a l l o m o r p h y The verbs of IndoEuropean languages generally have different person–number agreement suffixes in the present and past tenses, but these differences are the same for all verbs
(with few exceptions). For example, consider the Latin and Polish conjugations
in table 3.7. In Latin and Polish, different agreement classes co-occur with differences in stem classes: while amāre ‘love’, a class i verb in Latin, has the stem
amā- in the perfect (amā-v-i), other classes have different perfect stem forms,
which are most often irregular (e.g. agere ‘to guide’: ēg-; rı̄dēre ‘to laugh’: rı̄s-,
etc.). In Polish most verbs have -e- in most paradigm forms, as in table 3.7, but
206
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.8 Latin noun paradigm (singular only)
Nominative
Accusative
Genitive
Dative
Ablative
‘case’
‘mode’
‘gender’
cāsus
cāsum
cāsūs
cāsu¯
casū
modus
modum
mod¯
modō
modō
genus
genus
generis
gener¯
genere
a smaller (though still large) class of verbs has -i: lubie, lubisz, lubi, etc., ‘love’.
These languages are different from Dolakha Newar (Tibeto-Burman; Nepal;
Genetti (1994)), where tense-based agreement allomorphy combines with
stem alternations that are phonologically defined (similar in spirit to what we
described for Belhare) and do not require the discrimination of arbitrary lexical
classes.
Tense-based regular agreement allomorphy is to a limited degree also characteristic of Germanic languages (cf., e.g., German third person singular lieb-t
‘loves’ in the present vs lieb-t-e ‘loved’ in the past), but stem allomorphy is
restricted to a set of irregular verbs traditionally called ‘strong’ verbs as opposed
to the regular ‘weak’ verbs.
N o f o r m at i v e a l l o m o r p h y Finnish nouns all have the same set of
case suffixes, and likewise for nouns in Hungarian, Turkish, and Basque. All
variation there is phonologically or morphophonologically conditioned, i.e. the
same across the (regular) lexicon.
Where there are inflectional classes, an important consideration is identifying
the inflectional form or forms from which all or most of the others can best be
predicted. This is the reference form(s) or principal part(s) (Wurzel (1987a),
1987b); Carstairs-McCarthy (1991)), and it should be included in dictionaries,
glossaries, and practical descriptions. Latin dictionaries, for example, list the
nominative and genitive forms of nouns, and from these one can infer all other
case forms. Thus, while in all of the following nouns the nominative ends in
-us, they have different case paradigms, and this is predictable from the genitive
form that goes together with the -us nominative in each case: cāsus ‘case’ has
genitive cāsūs, modus ‘mode’ has genitive mod¯, and genus ‘gender’ has genitive
generis; cf. table 3.8. Note that other case combinations, e.g. nominative and
accusative, would not unambiguously identify the paradigms. The nominative
(citation form) plus the genitive (principal part), however, serve to completely
identify the rest of the declension.
Case paradigms are the prototypical declension classes, but a number of languages around the Pacific Rim have declension classes defined by allomorphy
of possessive inflection. Languages in our sample with this kind of declension
Inflectional morphology
207
Table 3.9 Anêm possessed noun paradigm (selection) (Thurston
(1982:37)). -ng-, -g-, and -d- in the last three words are stem
extenders. The final elements are person–number–gender suffixes
1sg
2sg
3sgm
3sgf
‘water’
‘child’
‘leg’
‘mat’
kom-i
kom-ı̂
kom-u
kom-ı̂m
gi-ng-e
gi-ng-ê
gi-ng-o
gi-ng-êm
ti-g-a
ti-g-ı̂r
ti-g-ı̂
ti-g-ı̂
mı̂k-d-at
mı̂k-d-ir
mı̂k-d-it
mı̂k-d-it
classes are Amele (Madang family or perhaps Rai Coast-Mabuso, New Guinea:
Roberts (1987)), Anêm (New Britain family, New Britain: Thurston (1982)),
Äiwo (Reefs-Santa Cruz, southeastern Pacific: Wurm (1981)), Chichimec
(Otomanguean, Mexico: Lastra de Suárez (1981)), Cayuvava (isolate, South
America: Key (1967)), and Limbu (Tibeto-Burman, Himalayas: van Driem
(1987)). Languages with typical alienable/inalienable possession might be
described as having two declension classes defined by possessive inflection,
but the six languages listed here have three or more declension classes, usually
with considerable and complex allomorphy of the possessive affixes or stem
alternations triggered by these. Amele has 31 declension classes of inalienables
(Roberts (1987)) and Anêm about 20 created by a combination of different
person–number suffixes and different stem extensions (Thurston (1982:37–8));
cf. table 3.9 for illustration. This is lexeme-based flexivity of both formatives
and stems, similar in kind to Latin case inflection: both the shape of the stem
(with extensions -ø, -ng, -g, -d) and the shape of the formative depend on the
particular lexical declension class of the root.
4.2
Syncretism
Every one of the Latin nouns in table 3.3 has at least one instance of syncretism,
or falling together of case endings: an example is dative and ablative lupō of
‘wolf’. Chechen has virtually no syncretism in its noun paradigms. Syncretism
is sometimes an accident of sound change, but more often it seems to be driven
by purely morphological considerations. It is not at all obvious that syncretizing cases are semantically or syntactically similar; for some discussion see
Plank (1991:19) or Blake (1994:44ff.). Hjelmslev (1935, 1937) and Jakobson
(1971a [1936], 1971b [1958]) assume that syncretism follows, and reveals,
the basic structural components of case meanings such as markedness of categories (markedness is defined in section 5). An instance of syncretism to which
208
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
functional motivation is often attributed is the nominative–accusative syncretism of neuter nouns in Indo-European languages (as in bellum ‘war’ in
table 3.3). The motivation lies in the fact that neuters are almost all inanimate,
hence presumably more likely to function as objects than as subjects of transitive
verbs (as shown by discourse studies in many languages; see Dubois, Kumpf,
and Ashby (2003)); hence there is little need for these nouns to distinguish
subject and object case forms.
Plank (1991:19–20) suggests ordering the cases of a language so as to put
syncretizing forms adjacent to each other to the extent possible. This procedure yields the following order for Latin: Vocative, Nominative, Accusative,
Ablative, Dative, Genitive.
4.3
Defectivity and suppletion
Some words simply lack certain paradigmatic forms. Latin impetus ‘attack’,
in table 3.3 above, forms only a few of the cases (Rhodes (1987)). Bagvalal
place names, as mentioned in section 4.6 below, lack a nominative case. A more
common kind of defectivation is lack of an entire category, or neutralization
of categories, in the presence of some other: e.g. Swahili verbs lack a contrast
of simple and imperfective aspect in negative forms, though they have it in
affirmative forms (e.g. w-a-soma ‘they read’ with wa-na-soma ‘they are reading’
but only ha-wa-soma ‘they don’t read, they are not reading’). Category-based
defectivity is not random; see Aikhenvald and Dixon (1998) for a preliminary
survey.
Gaps in paradigms are sometimes compensated for by (etymologically) different words. The lacking plural forms of Latin impetus ‘attack’, for example,
are frequently supplied by incursiōnēs ‘attack’. When this is regular and obligatory, the result is known as suppletion. Examples are the Latin past and perfect
stems tul- and lat- which are in paradigmatic opposition to the infinitive stem
fer- ‘carry’; or the English past tense went in opposition to the other tense forms
based on go. Suppletion of formatives (e.g Latin nominative in -s vs -m vs -ø)
is usually called (lexical) allomorphy (cf. above).
4.4
Deponence
A deponent word lacks the usual inflectional forms for a specific paradigm and
instead takes on the forms of another. Deponent verbs in Latin and Greek are
stranded passives, i.e. they have only passive forms, but they are used with active
syntax; an example is Latin eum sequor ‘I follow him’, with sequ-or inflecting
like a passive (cf. ag-or ‘I am being driven’) but with a transitive object eum
‘him’ in the accusative. This is the traditional sense of the term ‘deponent’.
Inflectional morphology
209
Table 3.10 Chechen deictic prefixes
hwadwahwalwa-
toward speaker
away from speaker
up
down
Corbett (2000a) and Baerman (2006) show that the phenomenon is more general and gives other examples: Russian nouns like zhivotnoe ‘animal’, which
is a syntactic noun with the declension of an adjective; Mohawk (Iroquoian)
syntactic nouns with verb morphology such as ra’swà:tha’ ‘fireman’ (lit. ‘he
extinguishes’); in Limbu and Belhare, a small number of syntactically transitive
verbs are inflected as if they were intransitive, and vice versa. The Limbu verb
form mε ʔru ‘s/he is fat’, for example, is a regular transitive verb form indicating
a third person singular actor (zero prefix) and a third person singular undergoer
(-u suffix). But syntactically and semantically, this is an intransitive predicate
(Michailovsky (1985, 1997); also cf. Bickel and Nichols (2001)).
4.5
Eidemic resonance
As pointed out by Hockett (1987), all morphology rests fundamentally on a
basic notion of what he called resonance: parts of words resonate with each
other and can therefore be extracted as meaningful formatives or morphemes.
For example, English cooks and runs resonate in that they contain the similar
sounds /s/ and /z/, associated with the identical meaning component ‘third
singular subject in the present indicative’, and from this we can extract a
morpheme -s. This is the most straightforward example, but in addition the
forms of a paradigm often resonate with each other through alliteration, rhyme,
or other paronomasia without entailing any general and consistent semantics or
morpheme extractability. Rather, the resonances serve to structure paradigms,
compartmentalize the lexicon, and provide psycholinguistic processing cues.
Following Bickel (1995) we call this eidemic resonance. Eidemic resonance
is probably best attested in small closed lexical paradigms such as personal
pronouns (e.g. French singular object pronouns me, te, le, se, which rhyme
and have the same syllable structure), basic kin terms (e.g. mama and
papa, with the same vowels and syllable structure and similar consonants:
Jakobson (1941)), essential deictics (e.g. this, that, there, etc., as the only
English words with initial /ð /), and the like, but also occurs in inflectional
paradigms. In Ingush and the predominant pronunciation of lowlands Chechen,
there is a closed set of deictic prefixes which are in part inflectional (table 3.10).
210
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.11 Warrgamay (Pama-Nyungan, Australia; Dixon
(1980:287, 329))
Role
‘woman’
1sg
1pl
a
s
p
ŋ ulmburu-ŋ gu
ŋ ulmburu
ŋ ulmburu
ŋ aja
ŋ ayba
ŋ anya
ŋ ali
ŋ ali
ŋ ali-nya
Type:
Ergative
3-way
Accusative
All four have pharyngeal segments or pharyngealization (spelled ‘w’ in this
transcription) and /a/ vocalism and are monosyllabic. The local prefixes, which
follow these, are varied in form and number of syllables, lack pharyngealization,
and are an open set.
4.6
Case inventories and case terminology
Case inventories range from two cases to dozens, and are usually displayed in
paradigms (see section 4.1 above for some case paradigms). The various caseinflecting words of a language do not necessarily all have the same inventory of
cases. In many languages of the Pama-Nyungan family of Australia, nouns have
ergative case paradigms while personal pronouns have three-way or accusative
paradigms. The examples from Warrgamay in table 3.11 show the three possibilities in one language. The distribution of alignment across parts of speech is
motivated by expectations of agency on the indexability hierarchy (Silverstein
(1976); DeLancey (1981)). The higher a referent is on this hierarchy, e.g. I in
contrast to stone, the more likely this referent is to be agent. Therefore there is
less need of explicit agency-marking in the form of an ergative case (because
agency is already expected), and at the same time more need of explicit patientmarking in the form of an accusative case (because patienthood is not expected).
And, vice versa, the lower a referent is on the hierarchy, e.g. stone in contrast
to I, the more there is a need for explicit ergative-marking (the unexpected
role) but the less there is for explicit patient-marking (the expected role). As
a result, high-indexable referents tend toward zero vs accusative marking and
low-indexables toward ergative vs zero marking.
Apart from these well-motivated splits in morphological alignment, there are
many instances where different words or word classes have different inventories
or numbers of cases. In Chechen, for instance, nouns distinguish eight basic
cases while attributive adjectives distinguish only nominative vs oblique:
Inflectional morphology
(50)
Nominative
Genitive
Dative
Ergative
etc.
‘good’
dika
dikacha
dikacha
dikacha
211
‘person’
stag
stegan
stegana
steguo
This could also be described as syncretism of all oblique cases in the adjective.
In various Nakh-Daghestanian languages, place names and other local nouns
are often adverbs or oblique case forms in origin, and they tend to have defective
declension and restricted syntactic functions. Daniel (2000) describes Bagvalal
(Nakh-Daghestanian) place names as a word class midway between nouns and
adverbs, with a highly defective declension lacking a nominative.
In Russian, a number of nouns distinguish, in addition to the basic six cases
of Russian, a second prepositional (or locative) case and/or a second genitive (or
partitive) case. It might be said that the vast majority of Russian nouns (including
all derived nouns) syncretize these two but a number of (underived) nouns
distinguish one or the other (or both) of them. A very few nouns distinguish a
separate ‘counting case’ used on nouns quantified by the numerals 2, 3, or 4,
while the vast majority use the genitive for this purpose. (The ‘counting case’
differs from the genitive only in stress placement.) These various minor cases
are found only on nouns; pronouns and adjectives distinguish only the basic six
cases. These Russian examples differ from the others discussed in this section
in that they are almost always judged to be ‘extra’ cases in a few paradigms
rather than defectivity of the others.
Standard schemas exist for names of cases in elaborate case systems; see
Melčuk (1986); Hjelmslev (1935); Blake (1994); and grammars of various
Nakh-Daghestanian and Uralic languages. In such languages the local cases
tend to fall into neat series based on topography and directionality vs rest:
inessive (‘in’), illative (‘into’), elative (‘out of’); adessive (‘on, at’), allative
(‘onto’), ablative (‘away from’); superessive (‘on top of’), superlative (‘onto
the top of’), superelative (‘off the top of’); etc. There is less uniformity of
opinion and practice concerning terminology for the more grammatical cases
and in smaller case systems. Cases are usually named for what is taken to be
their primary function. Nominative is the classical term for the basic case or
citation form (cf. Latin nomināre ‘to name’), and the term is still used in this
sense in most Greek-derived and Russian-derived grammatical and linguistic
traditions, while many western linguists use it only for S = A subject cases and
use absolutive for S=P cases. Accusative and ergative are standard for P and
A cases respectively. Dative is commonly used for a case that marks indirect
objects and often some subject-like experiencers. The term is also sometimes
used for primary objects, which comprise the P of monotransitives and the
212
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.12 Russian noun paradigm
‘lake’
Nominative
Genitive
Dative
Accusative
Instrumental
Prepositional
‘book’
Singular
Plural
Singular
Plural
ozero
ozera
ozeru
ozero
ozerom
ozere
ozera
ozer
ozeram
ozera
ozerami
ozerax
kniga
knigi
knige
knigu
knigoj
knige
knigi
knig
knigam
knigi
knigami
knigax
Goal argument of ditransitives (see vol. i, chapter 4), while accusative is the
traditional label for direct objects, which comprise the P of monotransitives and
the Theme of ditransitives. Genitive is most common for the default adnominal
case, though possessive is also found.
5
Markedness and obligatoriness
Morphological forms are defined through oppositions: we know that the form
rivers is marked by a suffix -s ‘plural’ because we know that rivers, like hundreds of other such nouns, stands in opposition to river, without an -s suffix.
It is a frequent characteristic of such oppositions that, as in this example, one
member is zero-marked, i.e. has no overt marker of its own. Another frequent
example for zero-marking is the nominative or absolutive case of nouns. More
unusual are paradigms with zeros in other places, e.g. the genitive plural of many
Russian nouns (table 3.12; zero-marked forms are boldfaced). Zero-marking is
sometimes context-specific: the Belhare locative case is regularly marked by
the suffix -(C)e, e.g. mi-e ‘at, to, on, in the fire’, but a few location-denoting
nouns such as place names or words like khim ‘house, home’ or gaũ ‘village’
have zero-marked locatives if (and only if) they function as the goal argument
of a verb of directed motion.
(51)
Belhare
a. Dhankuta-Ø khar-e-ŋ a
Dh.-loc
go-past-[1sg]excl
‘I went to Dhankuta’
b. Dhankuta-e yag-he-ŋ a.
Dh.-loc
stay-past-[1sg]excl
‘I stayed in Dhankuta’
Inflectional morphology
213
In (51a), the place name Dhankuta has a zero locative ending because it serves as
the goal argument of the verb. In (51b), locative case must be overtly marked, in
contrast, because the place name is in an adjunct rather than argument function.
In the terminology first established by the Prague School of linguistics, a
member of a paradigm is unmarked (German merkmallos) if it does not have
a semantic or syntactic value of its own on a par with the other members of
the paradigm and acquires a value only through opposition with other forms.18
Zero-marked nouns in English, for example, have a singular value only through
opposition with nouns marked as [+plural]. Where the opposition is neutralized,
as in generic statements, the zero-marked form can be used with a non-singular
value. This is why The kangaroo is native to Australia has the same truth value
as Kangaroos are native to Australia. Unmarkedness tends to go together with
zero marking (cf. Haiman (1985:147–51)), but the correlation is not universal:
even though the genitive plural forms ozer ‘of the lakes’ and knig ‘of the
books’ in table 3.12 are zero-marked, there is no context of neutralization and
indeed no reason to assume that they are functionally unmarked members of the
paradigm.
Languages differ greatly in the number of contexts in which an opposition is
obligatory and in which, as a corollary, the use of unmarked forms implies the
opposite value of marked forms. While English obligatorily requires number
marking for all but the generic statement context and reference to amorphous
masses (e.g. sugar, water, mud), many languages draw the line between animate
or human referents and the rest, requiring number marking only for nouns
referring to animate beings. When referring to a group of girls, for example,
one must say in Belhare kaepma-chi ‘girl-pl’; use of kaepma would entail, as
in English, reference to one single girl. By contrast a word like phuŋ ‘flower’
can have either singular or plural value, and, although grammatical, phuŋ-chi
‘flower-pl’ is a rare form. Some languages go further than this, and do not
require number marking in any context. This is typical for languages with
numeral classifiers and many others. In Yucatec (Mayan, Mexico; Lucy (1992)),
for example, a word like pèek’ ‘pig(s)’ or máak ‘man, men’ can have either
singular or plural value. The use of an explicit plural suffix (-ób) is reserved
for emphasis, contrast, or clarification. Optional number marking of this kind
is common in languages all around the Pacific Rim.
When analysing a language, it is very important to take note of differences between contexts requiring obligatory marking and contexts allowing
optional marking because it is these contexts that determine the actual value
of an unmarked (and often also formally zero-marked) form in discourse. If
18
Such oppositions are called privative and are contrasted with equipollent oppositions where both
members are equally specified. See Baltaxe (1978) and Anderson (1989) for historiographic and
theoretical surveys.
214
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
the context requires an obligatory opposition, the unmarked form will have
the opposite value to the marked form (e.g. a singular value in opposition
to a marked plural form). If the opposition is optional, no such implication
arises, and the unmarked form can have either value (e.g., a singular or plural
value).
6
Layered (hierarchical) versus templatic morphology
Strings of inflectional formatives often have a layered, or hierarchical, or nested
structure which can be represented as a branching tree or bracketed structure.
Such a string is said to be configurational, i.e., it has a regular constituent
structure. In a hierarchical string, dependencies between formatives are chiefly
between adjacent ones, the choice of an allomorph can depend on a more inner
formative but usually not on a more outward one, there is a single root or
head, and in general the position of each formative depends on its function (or
the function of its agreement trigger). An example is the following set from
Quechuan (Stump (1996:236) citing Muysken (1986)):
(52)
Quechuan (S. America; Muysken (1986:636))
a. riku-na-chi-ku-n-ku
see-recip-caus-refl-3-pl
‘Theyi caused them to see each otheri ’
b. riku-chi-na-ku-n-ku
see-caus-recip-refl-3-pl
‘Theyi caused each otheri to see them’
c. riku-na-ku-chi-n-ku
see-recip-refl-caus-3-pl
‘They caused themi to see each otheri ’
The relative ordering of the reciprocal, reflexive, and causative formatives determines their relative scope:
(52 )
a . [[riku-na]-chi]-ku-nku
‘[[see each other]-cause]-themselves’
b . [[riku-chi]-na]-ku-nku
‘[[see cause]-each other]-themselves’
c . [[riku-na]-ku]-chi-nku
‘[[see each other]-themselves]-cause’
Some of the clearest examples of layered structure come from multiple case
marking (see section 8.2 below, where these examples are discussed further):
Inflectional morphology
(53)
215
Huallaga Quechua (Quechuan, Peru; Weber (1989))
haacha-wan-naw mutu-n machiita-wan
axe-com-sim
chop-3 machete-com
‘He chops with a machete as though it were an axe’
The ordering of the comitative (‘com’) and similarity (‘sim’) cases on ‘axe’
reflects their relative scope:
(53 )
[[haacha-wan]-naw]
‘[[axe with] as though]’
A more complex example comes from Kayardild:
(54)
Kayardild (Tangkic, Australia; Dench and Evans (1988:34–5))
maku-ntha yalawu-jarra-ntha yakura-naa-ntha
woman-obl catch-past-obl
fish-abl(prior)-obl
dangka-karra-nguni-naa-ntha
mijil-nguni-naa-nth.
man-gen-instr-abl(prior)-obl net-instr-abl(prior)-obl
‘The woman must have caught fish with the man’s net’
The case suffixes on ‘man’ in this example are assigned for the following
reasons: the genitive reflects the noun’s own function as possessor (of the net);
the instrumental is in agreement with ‘net’, which ‘man’ modifies; the ablative
is in agreement with the verbal tense and indicates prior time reference; and the
oblique is in agreement with the case of the entire clause. Thus the word has
the following bracketed structure:
(54 )
[[[dangka-karra-] nguni-] naa-] ntha
[[[man-gen-] instr-] abl(prior)-] obl
Dench and Evans (1988) show that, in several of the many Australian languages
exhibiting multiple case marking, local processes of metathesis, haplology,
syncope, etc. superficially obscure the neat nested structure of the case strings,
but these processes operate on, and thus require, the original nested assignment
of the case suffixes.
Hierarchical morphology in verb agreement systems is illustrated by Abkhaz.
The structure of Abkhaz prefix strings is shown in (55) and table 3.13. The
prefix strings include three different positions for agreement with the direct
object (‘P’) or intransitive subject (‘S’), indirect object (‘IO’), and transitive
subject (‘A’). The agreement morphemes used in the three different positions
are essentially identical (except for minor allomorphy). In using essentially
the same set of agreement morphemes and assigning different functions to
different positions, Abkhaz agreement morphology is reminiscent of English
clause relations, where nps are assigned different grammatical functions by
different positions in the clause (and minor case on pronouns). Abkhaz could
216
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.13 Abkhaz verb agreement
1sg
2sgm
2sgf
3sghuman
3sgm
3sgf
3sgnonhuman
1pl
2pl
3pl
s(ə)- ∼ z(ə)w(ə)b(ə)d(ə)- (only in S/P slot)
y(ə)l(ə)- (only in IO and A slots)
y(ə)- ∼ (n)a◦ (a)- ∼ a◦ - ∼ aaš◦ (ə)- ž◦ (ə)y(ə)- ∼ r- ∼ d(ə)-
thus be said to have word-internal configurationality, with relative positioning
in the prefix layers determining function:
(55)
Structure of Abkhaz prefix strings (tam = tense–aspect–mood):
s/p-io-preverb-a-stem-tam-final
The S, P, IO, and A slots are filled with markers from a general person and
number paradigm, as given in table 3.13 (adapted from Hewitt (1979)). In the
following examples, the function of b(ə)- ‘you (fem. sg.)’ is determined by its
position:
(56)
Abkhaz (Northwest Caucasian; Hewitt (1979))
a. bzə̀ya bə -z-bò-yt’
well 2sg.f-1sg-see-fin
‘I love you’ (p. 105)
b. b-ca-r,
də -b-bò-n.
2sg.f-go-if 3sg.hum-2sg.f-see-fin
‘If you had gone, you would have seen him’ (p. 173)
In (56a), bə- is in the S/P position of a transitive verb form, so that it is in object
(P) function. In the form bcar ‘if you had gone’ in (56b) b- is again in the
S/P position, but since the verb is intransitive, it is assigned the S function. In
the transitive form dəbbòn ‘you would have seen him/her’, b- follows another
agreement marker and this shows that it is in the A slot, therefore in transitive
subject function.
Layered morphology contrasts typologically with what is called templatic
morphology (Simpson and Withgott (1986); see also Spencer (1991:208ff.);
Inkelas (1993); Stump (1996); Hyman (2003)). In templatic morphology the
structure of the string of formatives is flat and departs in a number of ways from
layered structure: there can be more than one root or head, dependencies can
obtain between non-adjacent formatives, allomorphy of more inward formatives
pf2
N- ‘3nsg’
N- ∼ miN- ‘neg’
pf1
mi- ‘3nsg’
-yuk ‘definitive’
-yakt ∼-ya(u) ‘ipfv’
sf1
sf3
-chi ‘du’
-i ‘1/2pl’
sf2
-(h)e ∼ -att ‘past’
-t ∼ -yuk ‘npt’
-a ‘subjunctive’
-n(i) ‘neg’
sf4
-ŋ (a) ‘excl’
-k(a(k)) ‘2’
sf5
Table 3.14 Belhare intransitive verb agreement of selected tense/aspect/mood forms (pf = prefix position, sf = suffix
position, = verb stem, N = nasal morphophoneme)
218
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
can be sensitive to more outward formatives, and the position of formatives
in the string can be determined by their formal categories, or by phonological
principles, rather than their syntactic or semantic functions.
Templatic morphology is characteristic, for example, of verb agreement in
Algonquian, Bantu, and Kiranti languages, where it regulates the sequencing of
inflectional formatives. Table 3.14 illustrates the templatic structure of Belhare
(Kiranti) intransitive verbs (see Bickel (1995, 2003), for a complete analysis).
As is typical for templatic morphology, there are many long-distance dependencies across several affix positions. For instance, the allomorphy of the past
tense marker -(h)e ∼ -att in suffix position sf2 is regulated by whether or not
there is a negation marker in sf4 (-n(i)), and these are often not adjacent (e.g.
n-ta-at-chi-n neg-come-pt-dual-neg ‘we two didn’t come’, with an intervening sf3 filler -chi ‘dual’). The appearance of the negative prefix in pf2 (N-)
is contingent on the simultaneous presence of the sf4 negation marker (-n(i)).
(There are transitive negative forms with only the sf4 negation marker, but none
with only the pf2 marker.)
In templatic morphology there is often a tendency for different affix positions
to be characterized by the same categories: e.g. in table 3.14, all fillers of the sf1
and sf2 slots are tense, aspect, mood markers, and all fillers of the sf5 position
are person markers. However, positions are not always homogeneous. The pf2
position, for instance, includes both person and negation markers. The rationale
for assigning morphemes to templatic position is purely formal: fillers of the
same position cannot co-occur in the same string. Therefore, a third person
nonsingular negative form, as in (57a), requires the use of the pf1 filler mi‘3nsg’. Although they are semantically compatible, the markers N- ‘3nsg’ (as
in 57b) and N- ‘neg’ (as in 57c) cannot co-occur and are therefore assigned the
same affix slot (the negative allomorph miN- only occurs in infinitives):
(57)
Belhare
a. mi-n-ta-at-ni
3nsg-neg-come-past-neg
‘they didn’t come’
b. n-ta-he
3nsg-come-past
‘they came’
c. n-ta-at-ni
neg-come-past-neg
‘s/he didn’t come’
The ordering does not reflect any syntactic functions, as it does in the hierarchical morphology of Abkhaz, but is purely morphological (and arbitrary).
Inflectional morphology
219
Occasionally, templatic ordering leads in some languages to functionally
indeterminate structures, as in Maithili, where the ordering of non-nominative,
honorificity-indicating agreement suffixes is rigidly fixed and allows for a variety of interpretations:
(58)
Maithili (Y. P. Yādava (p.c.))
dekhau-l-i-au-nh
show-pt-1nom-2nonhon-3hon
‘I showed him/her to you’
‘I showed you to him/her’
‘I showed his/her X to you’
The sequence -i-au-nh is the only one that is possible in Maithili with three
simultaneous agreement markers, and this is largely due to prosodic constraints
requiring verbal desinences to consist of an end-stressed light-heavy syllable
sequence (Bickel, Bisang, and Yadava (1999)). It is probably not uncommon
for templatic morphology to be determined or at least historically motivated by
prosodic and other phonological principles, but research on this area has just
begun; see, e.g., Hyman (2003) on the sonority hierarchy as a driving source
for suffix ordering in Bantu.
However, templatic versus layered properties are likely to hold of individual formatives rather than of the entire string. Judging from examples in
the literature, templatic properties seem to be typical of formative strings that
include inflectional elements, are head-marking or detached, and are in Prae
or Wackernagel position, though sometimes (as in the Belhare example mentioned above) they are in Post position. Layered properties are most common
in suffixed formatives (though in Abkhaz, above, a prefix string is layered)
and in dependent-marking morphology, with Australian multiple case marking
surely the most extreme example. We tentatively raise these generalizations as
hypotheses.
Regardless of whether formatives follow the principles of templatic or layered arrangement, they tend to abide by universal semantic ordering principles,
which interact with whatever other syntactic, morphological, or phonological
principles determine formative order in the given language:
(59)
Universal affix ordering in layered morphology
a. verbs: voice/aspect > modality > status/tense >
evidentials/illocutionary force
(Foley and Van Valin (1984); Van Valin and LaPolla (1997);
Bybee (1985))
b. nouns: number > case
(Greenberg (1963))
220
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
These principles are often seen as absolute universals, but there are exceptions,
and their status rather seems to be one of default principles that apply only in the
absence of overriding constraints (chiefly phonological or prosodic constraints).
7
Two examples of common inflectional categories: person
and number
Categories that are commonly inflectional and treated in other chapters of this
work include gender, deixis, tense, aspect, mood, illocutionary force, and voice
oppositions of various kinds. Nominalization, causative, reflexive, reciprocal,
middle, and negation are categories which, if not always strictly inflectional, at
least frequently have their overt marking worked into inflectional paradigms.
Two common inflectional categories treated elsewhere in this chapter are agreement and case (section 8). The rest of this section briefly describes two major
inflectional categories that are covered only partially or not at all elsewhere in
this chapter or this work.
7.1
Person
Person concerns the grammaticalization of conceptual distinctions between
participants involved in speech activities. From a pragmatic point of view, many
such distinctions play a role in communication, e.g., the difference between
those persons who actually attend a speech act and those who are merely referred
to, between those to whom an utterance is targeted and those who happen to
hear it as bystanders, etc. (see Levinson (1988) for an analysis of such notions).
Grammars typically conflate such distinctions and reduce the system to three
terms grammaticalizing the roles of speaker (first person), addressee (second
person), and other (third person), respectively. While this triad is the most
common system worldwide, other ways of dividing up the conceptual space
of person are also found, and we briefly discuss them in the following. Note,
however, that person systems other than the standard triad often apply to verbs
only, or pronouns only; it is not uncommon to find splits here across parts of
speech.
7.1.1
Exclusive versus inclusive
Many languages distinguish between an exclusive and inclusive conception of
the first person, and in many cases these are subcategories of plural (or dual)
number marking. An example is found in So, a language spoken in the Uganda–
Kenya border area. Exclusive here refers to the speaker and his or her group, but
excluding the addressee(s). The inclusive forms, by contrast, explicitly include
the addressee(s) along with the speaker and his or her group in the notion of
‘we’.
Inflectional morphology
221
Table 3.15 So pronouns (Kuliak, E. Africa;
Serzisko (1993))
Singular
Plural
1
aya
2
3
piya
ica
exclusive: inia
inclusive: isia
pitia
itia
Table 3.16 Belhare intransitive verb agreement
( = stem, N = nasal morphophoneme)
excl
incl
2
3
Singular
Dual
Plural
-ŋ a
-chi-ŋ a
-chi
-chi-ga
N--chi
-i-ŋ a
-i
-i-ga
N-
-ga
-
Some languages treat the exclusive versus inclusive distinction on a par
with the basic second versus third distinction rather than as a subcategory of
plural first persons. In such a system, exclusive and inclusive have singular
values, just as the other persons do. Table 3.16 is an example from Belhare
intransitive verb agreement (cf. Table 3.14 for the templatic arrangement of
affixes, and table 3.6 for a sample paradigm in the singular). For the exclusive (‘speaker(s) but not addressee’) this works without complications, since
restricting the reference to one person simply means reference to the speaker.
The inclusive, by contrast, does not allow a true singular value because it comprises both the speaker and the addressee and thus requires at least two referents.
While Belhare sidesteps this issue by not having an overt inclusive marker at
all, many languages of Siberia, North America, and Northern Australia use
a different kind of number system to accommodate the inclusive as a basic
person category: instead of distinguishing singular versus non-singular, these
languages distinguish minimal versus augmented number (McKay quoted by
Dixon (1980:351–6)). Table 3.17 illustrates this in a Siouan language of North
America. Minimal means singular for exclusive (ha- ‘I’), second person (ra‘you [sg.]’), and third person, but for the inclusive person minimal entails dual
number reference, i.e. h˜- ‘thou and I’. Augmented is plural for all persons (h˜-wi ‘you and I’, ha- -wi ‘we, excluding you’). In Northern Australian languages,
a third term, unit augmented, is sometimes distinguished. This translates as
222
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.17 Hocak (a.k.a. Winnebago; Siouan) subject agreement
(root xé ∼ xa ‘bury’: Lipkind (1945))
excl
incl
2
3
Minimal (-ø)
Augmented (-wi)
ha-xé
h˜-xé
ra-xé
xé
ha-xa-wı́
h˜-xa-wı́
ra-xa-wi
xa-wı́
‘I bury him’
‘thou and I bury him’
‘thou buriest him’
‘he buries him’
‘we (they and I) bury him’
‘we (you and I) bury him’
‘you bury him’
‘they bury him’
Table 3.18 Rembarrnga pronouns (N. Australia: Dixon
(1980:351–6) after McKay
excl
incl
2
3 masc
3 fem.
Minimal
Unit augmented (-pparraʔ)
Augmented (-ə)
ŋənə
yəkkə
kə
nawə
ŋ atə
yarr-pparraʔ
ŋ akorr-parraʔ
nakorr-parraʔ
parr-pparraʔ
parr-pparraʔ
yarr-ə
ŋ akorr-ə
nakorr-ə
parr-ə
parr-ə
trial for the inclusive and dual for the other persons, as in Rembarrnga (see
table 3.18).
The inclusive minimal form yəkkə refers to a simple set of speaker and
addressee and thus has a dual referent; the unit-augmented form ŋakorrparraʔ
adds to this one more referent and therefore has a trial referent (I, you, and one
other person); the augmented ŋakorrə finally adds further referents, and thus
has a plural value (I, you, and several others). For all other persons, the minimal
has a singular value (thus, ŋənə ‘I’, nawə ‘he’, etc.), the unit-augmented forms
have a dual value (thus, yarrpparraʔ ‘the two of us, without you’, parrpparraʔ
‘the two of them’, etc.), and the augmented forms have a plural value (yarrə
‘we, without you’, parrə ‘they’).
The diagnostic feature of augmented number systems is an additional dual or
trial number found only with first person inclusive forms (e.g. Hocak h˜- ‘1 dual
inclusive’, but no form glossed ‘1 dual exclusive’). When the description leads
one to positing such an additional number, a reanalysis in terms of augmentation
is usually called for (cf. Dixon (1980)).
It is important to note that in all of these systems in which inclusive and exclusive are independent person categories there really is no generalized first person
singular concept, no term corresponding to English I or So aya. Reference to
speaker alone is always achieved indirectly by minimizing or singularizing the
Inflectional morphology
223
category of the exclusive person. Only in languages where inclusive/exclusive is
a subtype of first person plural (as in So), and of course in languages like English
which lack any inclusive/exclusive distinction, is there a true generalized first
person singular pronoun.
7.1.2
Conjunct/disjunct systems
While the distinction between first and second person as indices to the speaker
and addressee, respectively, is the most common type worldwide, typological
research has established that this is not the only one possible. A few languages
in Asia and South America have grammaticalized a completely different categorization, at least in verb agreement. One person, usually labelled ‘conjunct’,19
refers to the speaker in statements and to the addressee in questions (excluding
rhetorical questions, which are really statements in function). Thus, the conjunct person form wonā in Newar, the Tibeto-Burman language of the Nepalese
capital Kathmandu, can mean ‘I went’ or ‘did you go?’. This is in opposition
to what is called a disjunct form, wona, which is used for all other situations,
i.e. meaning ‘you went’ or ‘s/he went’ or ‘did s/he go?’ or, where this makes
sense in context, ‘did I go?’. What is at the functional core of the conjunct
person category is the indexing of what Bickel (2001) calls the informant, i.e.
the person who the speaker supposes or claims to be the immediate supplier
of the information. In statements, this is the speaker himself or herself, but
in questions this role of informant is attributed to the addressee. The disjunct
person indexes any participant who is not the informant in the speech situation.
Conjunct/disjunct systems are sometimes geared toward agents in the sense
of volitional instigators of situations. In Newar (A. Hale (1980); Hargreaves
(1991)) and some other Tibeto-Burman languages, conjunct person marking
generally applies only to such referents and therefore only to volitional or
controlled verbs.20 In other languages, however, the distinction applies to other
arguments as well, and one occasionally finds it applied to both actors and
undergoers marked differently. The South American language Awa Pit, for
instance, has agreement differentiation in conjunct marking:
19
20
The term is from A. Hale’s (1980) pioneering description of the phenomenon in Newar. The
less than ideally transparent terminology derives from the use of conjunct forms in reported
speech where the form marks coreference (referential ‘conjunction’) of the subject with the
speaker referent reported in the matrix clause (i.e. it has the same effect as a logophoric marker).
Alternative terms found in the literature are locutor, egophoric, subjective, and congruent; cf.
Curnow (2002).
In Tibetan, this has to do with the historical source of the distinction, which is an epistemological
category focussed on agency. See DeLancey (1990, 1992) and Bickel (2000b) for discussion
of this; and Dickinson (2000) for a study of epistemological categories and conjunct person in
Tsafiki (Barbacoan, Ecuador).
224
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
(60)
Awa Pit (Barbacoan; Ecuador and Columbia; Curnow (2002))
a. k-in-ka=na,
na=na
Santos=ta
dawn-when=top 1sg[nom]=top S.=acc
izh-ta-w
see-past-conjunct.subject
‘At dawn I saw Santos’
b. shi ayuk=ta=ma libro ta-ta-w?
what inside=loc=q book put-past=conjunct.subject
‘Under what did you put the book?’
c. Juan=na
(na=wa) izh-t-i-s
j.=top
1sg=acc see-past-conjunct.undergoer
‘Juan saw me’
d. nu=wa=na
m-in=ma pyan-t-i-s?
2sg=acc=top who=q hit-past-conjunct.undergoer
‘Who hit you?’
e. p-ina
alu
ki-mat-i-zi
very
rain
do-pfv-past-disjunct
‘It rained heavily’
In (60a) and (60b), the verb is marked for a conjunct person subject: in (60a), a
statement, it indexes the speaker; in (60b), a question, it indexes the addressee.
The examples in (60c) and (60d) illustrate the conjunct person in undergoer
function, again indexing the speaker in a statement (60c) and the addressee in a
question (60d). Example (60e) illustrates disjunct marking, which signals that
the conjunct person is neither subject nor personally affected by the situation.
7.1.3
Person and the indexability hierarchy
In most languages, the person triad and the conjunct/disjunct opposition are
not disjointed sets of terms but form a tightly structured hierarchy which is
responsible for various morphosyntactic effects. At the core of the hierarchy
is the distinction between speech-act participants and third person referents,
but the hierarchy is often elaborated in distinguishing, among third persons,
between human and non-human referents, or between animate and inanimate
referents. Sometimes other parameters, such as anaphoricity or definiteness,
gender, kinship, number, possession, size, and discreteness or segmentability, affect the structure of the hierarchy as well. The hierarchy has many
effects ranging from number differentiation to splits in case-marking patterns,
and we will review some of them below. We refer to the hierarchy as the
indexability hierarchy (Bickel (1999)) since its basic variable is the ease with
who a referent can be identified – or ‘indexed’ – from within the speech-act
situation. Identification is easiest for speaker and addressee, who are necessarily
Inflectional morphology
225
co-present, and it is easier for human referents than for other animates because
humans tend to be topics in ordinary discourse and are therefore cognitively
more accessible. Singular and individualized referents are generally easier to
point at unambiguously than groups or masses, so that in many languages they
figure higher on the indexability hierarchy. Alternative terms like animacy,
agency, generic topicality, egocentricity, or empathy hierarchy that have been
proposed in the literature (cf., among many others, Comrie (1981a); DeLancey
(1981); Givón (1994))21 capture some, but not other aspects of the hierarchy. Note, however, that there is considerable (but at present ill-understood)
cross-linguistic variation in the details of how the hierarchy is set up among
third person referents, and different parameters may prove relevant in different
languages.
While such details vary, one way of distinguishing among non-speech-act
participants is particularly noteworthy from a typological point of view: some
languages expand the indexability hierarchy beyond the traditional person triad
by adding a fourth (or obviative) and sometimes even a fifth (or further obviative) person.22 Such extensions are best known from Algonquian languages but
they are also attested in a few other North American languages. Depending
on a number of syntax and discourse factors, nps in these languages appear
in discourse as either third or fourth (or fifth) person. In Cree, fourth person
(also called obviative) is marked by the suffix -a; third person (also called
proximative) is zero-marked. This difference has a reflex on verb agreement.
Agreement in Cree and other Algonquian languages is in person–number but it
does not indicate role. To indicate the roles, verbs are marked as what is called
‘direct’ or ‘inverse’: a direct marker signals that the A argument is higher on the
indexability hierarchy than the P argument, while an inverse marker establishes
the reverse role assignment, with a person lower on the hierarchy acting on a
person higher. This mechanism applies equally to positions in the hierarchy.
Thus, if a third person acts on a fourth person (downwards, as it were), the verb
will be marked as direct. If a fourth person acts on a third person (upwards,
as it were), the verb will be marked as inverse. The same logic applies when,
for example, a first and a third person are involved. Again, if the action goes
‘down’ the hierarchy (first acting on third), the marking is direct. If the action
goes ‘up’ the hierarchy (third acting on first), the verb is marked as inverse. The
following examples illustrate this.
21
22
The hierarchy was first extensively discussed by Silverstein (1976), but there are many precursors, to say nothing of the very fact that person categories are referred to by the numbers 1, 2,
3 in both the Graeco-Roman and the Indic linguistic traditions (although in different order: for
the Indian grammarians, the speaker was ‘3’).
Note that the label ‘fourth person’ is sometimes used in a different sense. In descriptions of
Eskimoan languages, for example, it is the traditional label for reflexives.
226
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
(61)
Plains Cree (Algonquian; N. America; Dahlstrom (1986))
a. e -wa pam-a -ya hk-ik
b. e -wa pam-iko-ya hk-ik
det-see-dir-1pl.excl-3pl (conj)
det-see-inv-1pl.excl-3pl (conj)
‘They (3) see usexcl (1)’
‘Weexcl (1) see them (3)’
d. e -wa pam-iko-t
c. e -wa pam-a -t
det-see-dir-3[sg][-4sg] (conj)
det-see-inv-3[sg][-4sg] (conj)
‘He (3) sees him (4)’
‘He (4) sees him (3)’
In (61a), the direct marker -a signals that a first person acts on a third person.
In (61b) this is reversed, and it is the third person that acts on the the first. This
is exactly parallel to (61c) and (61d), respectively, but here the relationship is
between a third and a fourth (obviative) person (zero-marked here): in (61c)
this relationship is direct, so that the third (proximate) person acts on the fourth;
in (61d) the relationship is inverse, so that the fourth person acts on the third.
Determining which referent is third and which one is fourth (obviative)
depends by and large on topicality or other prominence in discourse. But there
are also purely syntactic factors involved: a possessor, for instance, is always
higher on the hierarchy than its possessed object (Wolfart (1978)). Algonquian
languages differ in how syntactic and discourse factors compete in determining
person assignment (Rhodes (1990); Mithun (1999:76f.)).
Scenarios involving speech-act participants only (‘I saw you’, ‘you saw me’)
often enjoy a special status on the hierarchy. Sometimes speech-act participants are ranked: in Plains Cree, for instance, the second person takes preference over the first in triggering person marking (in independent mood forms).
But the inverse/direct marking does not apply in I/you and you/me scenarios,
and instead there are portmanteau morphemes signalling ‘1>2’ (-iti) or ‘2>1’
(-i) (where ‘>’ indicates a transitive relationship with the first term as subject and the second as object).23 Portmanteau morphemes for these person sets
are a widespread phenomenon worldwide (as noted by, among others, Hagège
(1982:107); Heath (1991, 1998); Bickel (2000b); Jacquesson (2001)). Kiranti
and many other Tibeto-Burman languages, for instance, have dedicated agreement markers for the ‘1>2’ relation (e.g. Belhare nise-na (see-1>2) ‘I saw
you’). Some languages, such as the Indo-Aryan language Maithili, neutralize
scenarios here and have only one form covering both ‘1>2’ and ‘2>1’ relations (e.g. dekhl-i ‘I saw youhon. ’ or ‘Youhon. saw me’: Bickel et al. (1999)).
The reason for blurring the nature of the relationship or coding it by a portmanteau morpheme is probably, as Heath (1991:86) suggests, that such scenarios
are ‘doubly dangerous’ since ‘they not only combine the most pragmatically
23
Alternatively, one could analyse -iti and -i as markers of inverse and direct relations, specialized
for scenarios involving only speech-act participants (Dahlstrom (1986)). For discussion, see
Bickel (1995).
Inflectional morphology
227
Table 3.19 Old Church Slavic number paradigm (Huntley
(1993:140))
‘woman’
Singular
Dual
Plural
Vocative
Nominative
Accusative
Genitive
Dative
Instrumental
Locative
ženo
žena
ženo
ženy
ženě
ženojo
ženě
ženě
ženě
ženu
ženama
ženama
ženu
ženy
ženy
ženŭ
ženamŭ
ženami
ženaxŭ
sensitive pronominals’ but ‘also combine them into a syntagmatic structure and
thereby necessarily focus on the speaker–addressee relationship’.
Another type of person that is often specially marked is generic or nonspecific
person. English uses second person pronouns in this function, e.g. You win a few,
you lose a few. Some languages have a dedicated generic person form which
is grammatically third person in verb agreement, e.g. German man, French
on, Hausa a(n) (Newman (2000:486)), or the Slave (Athabaskan) prefix ts’(Rice (2000:187)). In other languages it is the first person inclusive category
that is used for generic reference. For instance, the Belhare form hiu-t-i ‘cannpt-1pl[incl]’ can either specifically mean ‘us’ including the addressee(s)
(‘we can (do it)’), or it can be meant in the generic sense of ‘one can (do
it)’.
7.2
Number
Number is, minimally, an opposition of singular to plural.24 Less common
numbers are dual (two individuals), trial (three individuals), and paucal (a
few individuals). Old Church Slavic makes a singular/dual/plural opposition in
nouns, pronouns, adjectives, and verbs (see table 3.19).
In a number of languages, verbs make an aspectual or aspect-like distinction
of single versus multiple action, often in addition to singular versus nonsingular
agreement. An example from Chechen is in table 3.20 (semelfactive = single
action; pluractional = multiple action).
Number-like categories include distributives (which imply a plurality of separate individuals) and collectives (which imply a number of individuals viewed
as a set).
24
See Corbett (2000b) for an exhaustive treatment of number.
228
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.20 The Chechen verb ‘drive’. 1x = once, Nx = many times
Singular
Plural
Semelfactive
Pluractional
loallu ‘one drives one 1x’
loaxku ‘one drives many 1x’
loellu ‘one drives one Nx’
loexku ‘one drives many Nx’
Number often shares formatives or at least paradigms and position slots with
person, and number agreement is systematically marked in the great majority
of languages having person agreement on the verb. On other parts of speech,
number is more likely to be optional or missing entirely. It is fairly common
for number not to be marked overtly on nouns. It may be marked instead on an
article or plural word (illustrated for Yapese in (42) above), and many languages
have number marking on verbs although the nouns with which the verbs agree
in number have no overt number marking themselves; an example of such a
language is Lakhota (Siouan, North America). In a number of languages, verbs
make more number distinctions than do nouns (e.g. verbs in Yimas distinguish
singular/dual/paucal/plural while nouns distinguish only singular/dual/plural).
Where present in a language, number marking is likely to be optional on nouns,
especially those in the lower reaches of the indexability hierarchy; or it may be
available only to animate or human nouns or other high-indexability nouns (see
section 5 above). Personal pronouns are more likely than nouns to make number
distinctions, and pronominal formatives more likely to distinguish number than
independent pronouns. These and other patterns of optionality and limitation
in number categories are briefly reviewed in Nichols (1992:144ff.).
An unusual marking of number is number toggling (or ‘inverse number marking’) in the Kiowa-Tanoan languages (Wonderly Gibson, and Kirte (1954);
Watkins and McKenzie (1984:78ff.); Weigel (1993)), in which nouns have
inherent number, every noun being either singular or plural, and the suffix -go
(and its allomorphs) toggles singular to plural and vice versa.
Number intersects with person in various ways, and this has impacts on the
referential value of number categories. One instance of this is the effect of
exclusive versus inclusive distinctions on number, which in some cases yields,
as we saw in section 7.1.1, a distinction between minimal and augmented rather
than between singular and plural. Another effect is that nonsingular in the first
person usually means ‘the speaker and his/her group’ rather than a multitude of
simultaneous speakers (Jespersen (1924b/1969: 192)). Some languages allow
this use of nonsingular forms with other nouns as well. Belhare ama-chi, for
instance, does not refer to several mothers but rather to ‘my mother and her
people’ (e.g. sisters, friends, etc., depending on the situation). This type of
nonsingular number, known as associative number, is a distinct category of its
Inflectional morphology
229
own in a few languages (Moravcsik (1994); Corbett and Mithun (1996)): in
Hungarian, it is marked by the suffix -ék (Jánosék ‘John and his associates)’,
distinct from the ordinary plural -ok (Jánosok ‘several Johns’). Similar contrasts
are found in Pomoan and Eskimo languages. Associative numbers are usually
confined to names, kin terms, titles, and occupations and do not usually extend to
common nouns. However, with inanimate nouns, a similar notion is sometimes
expressed by echo words, in which a word is repeated with some mutation.
In many Eurasian languages, this involves replacing the initial consonant, cf.
Nepali raksi-saksi ‘raksi (a distilled alcoholic beverage) and things that go with
it (snacks, etc.) or are similar in kind (beer, etc.)’ with default mutation to /s/, or
Turkish çocuk-mocuk ‘children and all that goes with them (toys, games, etc.)’
with default mutation to /m/. Most South Asian languages extend echo-wordformation to other parts of speech, e.g., Hindi nahā-vahā ‘bathe and do whatever
goes with this (dry, get dressed again, etc.)’ or jaldi-valdi ‘fast, etc.’. In these
cases, the semantic effect is sometimes more generally one of inspecificity than
of association. See Abbi (1994:27–33) for a discussion of semantic variation
in South Asian echo words.
8
Morphology in syntax
8.1
Agreement
Agreement is the phenomenon by which a word carries morphological features
that originate somewhere else. For instance, a verb agrees in person with its
subject or a modifying adjective agrees in case with the head noun. There
are two fundamentally different types, based on where the features originate:
head-driven and dependent-driven agreement. Head-driven agreement consists
in percolating features from the phrasal head to its dependents, e.g. from the
noun heading a noun phrase to some or all of its dependents. The result of
this is dependent marking in the sense defined in section 2. Consider (1) in
the introductory section, from German, or the example from Hindi in (62).
In this language, agreement targets not only adjectives but also the adnominal
postposition kā ‘of’:
(62)
Hindi (Indo-European; South Asia)
a. lar.k-õ=k-ā
chot-ā
boy-pl.obl=of-masc.sg small-masc.sg
‘the small room of the boys’
b. lar.k-õ=k-e
chot-e
boy-pl.obl=of-masc.pl small-masc.pl
‘the small rooms of the boys’
kamr-ā
room(masc)-sg.nom
kamr-e
room(masc)-pl.nom
230
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
If the head noun is nominative masculine singular, adjective and postposition
end in -ā (62a); if the head noun is nominative masculine plural, adjective and
postposition end in -e (62b).
Head-driven agreement usually involves gender, number, and/or case and
chiefly affects nps. On the vp and clause level, head-driven agreement is sometimes found in the form of transitivity or tense agreement. Transitivity agreement
is illustrated by the Australian language Yidi, where it is required across the
verbs in a complex predicate vp:
(63)
Yidi (Pama-Nyungan, NE Australia; Dixon (1977:252))
guwal
dyara -l gali-ŋ al-nyu,
bulmba.
name[abs] put-past go-appl:com-past place[abs]
‘[He] gave names to all the places as he went along’ (p. 522)
In this example, the intrinsically intransitive verb gali- ‘go’ receives a comitative
applicative marker that increases its valence and thus allows the verb to match
the valence of the head verb dyara- ‘put’.
Tense agreement is illustrated by the Uto-Aztecan language Luiseño:
(64)
Luiseño (Uto-Aztecan, S. California; Steele (1990))
noo=n=il
čaqalaqi-qus. hengeemal-i
1sg=1sg=past tickle-past boy-acc
‘I was tickling the boy’ (p. 3)
Both the auxiliary (=nil) in the Wackernagel clitic position and the lexical verb
(čaqalaqiqus.) are marked as past tense, and they must agree in this marking.
Dependent-driven agreement is the mirror image of head-driven agreement,
with features copied from a dependent usually to the head. Classic examples
are the registration of possessors on the head noun in an np (as in the Hungarian
and Abkhaz examples, (26) and (29) in section 2 above), or the registration of
arguments on a verb. The following Belhare examples illustrate both:
(65)
Belhare
a. ŋ ka-ha a-tak
1sg-gen 1sg.poss-friend
‘my friend’
b. un-chik-ŋ a ŋ ka
ma-ŋ -ni-at-ni
3-nsg-erg 1sg[abs] 1sg.p-3nsg.a-see-past-neg
‘They didn’t see me’
In (65a), the head tak ‘friend’ of the np registers the person and number of its
possessive dependent. In (65b), the verb ni- ‘see, know’ agrees with both the
A-argument unchikŋa ‘they’ and the P-argument ŋka ‘me’. Dependent-driven
agreement typically targets the head only. But occasional examples of multiple
Inflectional morphology
231
targets are attested. Consider the following examples from Archi (agreement
formatives are boldfaced):
(66)
Archi (Nakh-Daghestanian, NE Caucasus; Kibrik (1994:349))
a. buwa-mu b-ez
dit abu ◦ alli
abu
father-erg iii-1sg.dat early:iii bread(iii):abs.sg make:iii
‘Father made the bread for me early’
b. nenabu
◦ alli
abu
1incl.erg:iii bread(iii):abs.sg make:iii
‘We made the bread’
In (66a), the absolutive argument ◦ alli ‘bread’ is in gender iii and this feature
is matched by nearly all constituents of the clause, including not only the head
of the clause, i.e. the predicate (abu ‘made.it’) but also other dependents such as
adverbs (ditabu ‘early’) and pronominal arguments (bez ‘me’). Whether or not
a constituent undergoes agreement depends on the availability of morphological
slots on it. Nouns do not have such a slot, which is why buwamu ‘father’ in
(66a) does not show agreement, unlike the pronoun nenabu ‘we(incl.)’ in (66b).
(Note that agreement markers are infixed in most instances.) Another case of
multiple agreement targets is found in Coahuilteco, an extinct language isolate
of southern Texas. In this language, subject agreement is manifested on the
verb and on dependent object nps (including embedded clauses). Thus, both
the verb form and the shape of the accusative suffix (boldface) are determined
by the person of the subject referent:
(67)
Coahuilteco (isolate; N. America; Troike (1981))
a. Dios tupo -n
naxo-xt’e wal wako
God dem-acc.1 1pl.s-annoy caus
‘We annoyed God’
b. Dios tupo -m
xa-ka wa xo e?
God dem-acc.2 2s-love aux q
‘Do you love God?’
c. Dios tupo -t
a-pa-k’tace y
God dem-acc.3 3s-sub-pray:pl
‘that (all) pray to God’
Dependent-driven agreement is by and large limited to features specifying
referents, and this is why cross-reference is often used as an alternative term.
Typical examples involve inflection of nouns or verbs for person, number, and
gender of referents. Nonreferential features like case are rarely affected by
dependent-driven agreement (but see Bickel et al. (1999) for an example from
Maithili). Clause-level categories like mood are equally rare in dependentdriven agreement. However, in some languages, question words sometimes
232
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
trigger interrogative mood marking on the verb. This is obligatory in Greenlandic Eskimo (Sadock (1984)) and Hausa (Newman (2000:493)), and is an
optional possibility in Japanese (Hinds (1984)):
(68)
West Greenlandic Eskimo (Eskimo-Aleut, Greenland; Sadock
(1984:200))
kina maanii-ppa?
who be.here-3sg.interrogative
‘Who is here?’
In these languages, interrogative mood also appears in polar (‘yes/no’) questions, where it is not triggered by question words. The Papuan language Tauya,
by contrast, has a dedicated mood (-ne) for parametric (‘wh’) questions, distinct
from the mood marking polar questions (-nae ∼ -nayae). Thus, the parametric
mood only appears as the result of agreement:
(69)
Tauya (Adelbert Range, Papua New Guinea; McDonald (1990))
we fofe-ʔ e-ne?
who come-3sg.fut-parametric.interrogative
‘Who will come?’
Dependent-driven agreement, especially on the clause level, is often sensitive
to the nature of the relationship between the dependent and the head. One distinction is that between grammatical and pronominal agreement.25 Grammatical
person/number agreement marks a relationship between the verb and argument
nps. This is illustrated by the examples in (65b) through (67) above, or, indeed,
by the subject agreement found in the English translations of these examples.
Pronominal agreement, in contrast, does not mark a relationship between verb
and argument nps; rather, the agreement morphology absorbs argument positions and consequently the agreement-triggering nps can no longer overtly
appear in these positions. Put differently, grammatical agreement points to an
argument while pronominal agreement is the argument. This is the case, for
example, in Irish:
(70)
25
Irish (McCloskey and K. Hale (1984)) (pronominal agreement)
a. chuirfinn
(*mé) isteach ar an phost sin
put:1sg.cond 1sg
in
on art job dem
‘I would apply for that job’
b. churfeadh Eoghan isteach ar an phost sin
put:cond e.
in
on art job dem
‘Owen would apply for that job’
This distinction has a long tradition (but terminology varies). The idea was first introduced by
Du Ponceau (1819) and von Humboldt (1836) and had a veritable renaissance in the mid-1980s
(see, among others, Jelinek (1984); Mithun (1985); Van Valin (1985); Bresnan and Mchombo
(1987)).
Inflectional morphology
233
In (70a), the verb is inflected for first person singular. This inflection absorbs the
subject argument position, and therefore no np (mé ‘I’) can fill this position in
the clause. If the verb is not inflected for person and number, as in (70b), subject
nps (here, Eoghan) can occur overtly. Similar patterns are found all over the
world, e.g. in many languages of the Americas (cf. Popjes and Popjes (1986)
on a Jê language; Abbot (1991) on a Carib language; and Galloway (1993) on
a Salishan language) and in several Semitic languages.
The ban on overt agreement-triggering nps is often not general but concerns
a specific phrase-structural position reserved for true arguments. In Chichewa,
object nps can co-occur with pronominal agreement markers if they are moved
out of their canonical postverbal argument position into topic (or afterthought)
position:
(71)
Chichewa (Bantu, E. Africa; Bresnan and Mchombo (1987:751))
a. ??ndi-kufúná kutı́ [VP mu-wa-páts-é
a-lenje] mphâtso
1sg.s-want
comp
2sg.a-3.pl(ii).p-give-sub ii-hunter gift
‘I want you to give them a gift, the hunters’
b. ndi-kufúná kutı́ [VP mu-wa-páts-é
mphâtso] a-lenje
1sg.s-want comp
2sg.a-3pl(ii).p-give-sub gift
ii-hunter
‘I want you to give them a gift, the hunters’
Example (71a) is unacceptable because the primary object alenje ‘the hunters’
occupies the vp-internal argument position that is already filled by the agreement marker wa-, which denotes a class II (= plural animate) noun in primary object (‘P’) function.26 Moving the np out of the vp into an afterthought
(or fronted topic) position as in (71b) resolves this problem. A similar possibility is given in many Amazonian languages, e.g. in Yagua (Peba-Yagua
family; Everett (1989)) or Maxakalı́ (Jê; Rodrigues (1999)). When nps are
removed from argument positions, their relation to agreement markers is no
longer one of feature-matching. Instead, it is one of anaphoric resumption.
In this respect, pronominal agreement markers resemble cliticized or incorporated pronouns. However, unlike pronouns, pronominal agreement markers are
formatives, not grammatical words. One effect of this is that they have more referential possibilities than pronouns. For instance, they can have indefinite reference (‘someone, something’) without any special marking. Ordinary pronouns
(like he, she, it) usually do not have this option. See Evans (1999) for detailed
discussion.
The diagnostic feature of pronominal agreement is that nps in the same
argument role as the agreement markers are banned from syntactic argument
(actant) positions in the clause. Whether or not overt nps occur at all in the sentence is a different issue. In most languages, nps are completely optional in all
26
The notion ‘primary object’ is discussed in vol. i. chapter 4, section 2.3.
234
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
positions, regardless of whether the language has grammatical agreement (e.g.
Latin, Belhare, or Maithili) or pronominal agreement (e.g. Maxakalı́, Yagua, or
Chichewa).
Note, however, that there are split systems. Agreement systems can be grammatical in some part (say, subject agreement, or object agreement with animate
nps) and pronominal in other parts (e.g. object agreement, or object agreement with inanimate nps). Such splits generally reflect ongoing processes of
grammaticalization: pronominal agreement involves the same kind of anaphoric
links that are found in discourse in general, and, over time, these links can
become strengthened and grammaticalized. This results in grammatical agreement systems. See Givón (1976, 1984) for exemplification and discussion.
Grammatical agreement systems are all based on relating features in the
agreement trigger and features expressed by the agreement morphology. In
most cases, this relation consists in unifying (or merging) the features so as to
create one single referential expression: even though in e.g. he walk-s there are
two different referential indexes, one implied by the np and one implied by the
agreement desinence -s, there is only one single referent expressed. This and
similar agreement systems are what we call integrative agreement systems.
In addition, there also exist a s s o c i at i v e agreement systems (Bickel
(2000a)), which employ different ways of relating features. In associative systems, which are characteristic of many Tibeto-Burman and Australian languages, the features of the agreement trigger enter into a variety of relations with
the features expressed by agreement morphology. A particularly rich example
is found in Lai Chin:
(72)
27
Lai Chin (Tibeto-Burman, W. Burma; Bickel (2000a))
a. a-maʔ
a-ni
3[sg]-dem 3[sg]s-laugh
‘S/he laughs’
(identity)
b. a-háw
daʔ nà-n-raʔ ?
3[sg]-who q 2-pl.s-come
‘Who of you came?’
(part of)
27
c. tsó n piak tu niʔ làw ka-thloʔ
vé
teacher
erg field 1[sg]a[-3sg.p]-work even
‘Even as a teacher I can work the field’
(apposition)
d. ka-lùŋ
na-r`ŋ
1[sg]poss-heart 2[sg]s-suspicious
‘I suspect you’
(other relation)
In keeping with the isolating morphology of this language, words like tsón piak tu niʔ ‘teacher
erg’ are unitary from the point of view of syntax and lexicon but not from the point of view of
phonology. Spaces demarcate phonological, not grammatical, word boundaries.
Inflectional morphology
235
Only in example (72a) do features merge into unified reference to a single
third person. In (72b), the subject argument aháw ‘who’ represents a subset of the referents expressed by the corresponding subject agreement prefix
nàn- ‘you (pl.)’. In (72c), the subject tson piak tu niʔ ‘teacher’ is understood
as a secondary predicate (a copredicate) of the subject (A) prefix ka- ‘I’. The
most complex relation is found in (72d), where the subject np, of which ‘r
`ŋ
‘be suspicious, be green’ is predicated, is kalùŋ ‘my heart’. As a subject, this
np triggers agreement in the corresponding subject agreement slot on the verb.
However, it is not the third person singular feature of this np (nor the possessor’s
features) that are registered there, but rather the features of the referent with
regard to whom the predication holds, here na- ‘you (sg.)’.
In systems like these, the feature specification in the verb agreement morphology is independent of the specifications in the agreement-triggering nps. The
two feature sets are then related to each other through the agreement relation
itself, and this is done in the various ways indicated in (72) above. Integrative
systems, by contrast, involve one unitary set of features and the agreement
relation merely assures this unity; it does not create it.
8.2
Case spreading and stacking
Cases and adpositions can also appear on words secondarily, i.e. not because
they are directly assigned but because they are assigned to some other word
with which the host stands in some syntactic relationship. There are two types
of secondary case assignment: spreading and stacking. Both contrast with inert
behaviour, where no secondary cases appear. Inert behaviour is the simplest
situation and the most common type cross-linguistically.
Copying and agreement of cases and adpositions can generically be called
spreading. Spreading of cases within the np is common in Utian and IndoEuropean languages:
(73)
Southern Sierra Miwok (Utian, California; Broadbent (1964))
a. cyty-ʔ
naŋ a-ʔ
good-nom man-nom
‘a/the good man’
b. ʔ i-s-ʔ ok
cyl a-s
that-instr-that awl-instr
‘with that awl’
(74)
Latin
a. ascia
nova
axe.nom new.nom
‘a/the new axe’
236
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
b. asciā
novā
axe.abl new.abl
‘with a/the new axe’
In a language with inert cases, case would be marked only once for the np here.
In Belhare, for example, Latin asciā novā ‘with the new axe’ would translate as
uchoũat phendikŋa, where the instrumental case suffix -ŋa appears only once
on the head; in fact spreading would be ungrammatical (*uchoũatna phendikŋa
‘new-instr axe-instr’).
When case is inert, it has scope over the whole phrase. Although the instrumental is not marked on the adjective in a Belhare np, the adjective is still in the
scope of this case marker, and it therefore refers to the quality of the instrument
‘axe’ here. The adjective does not constitute an independent nominative np.
Because of their phrasal scope, inert case markers are sometimes analysed as
cliticized adpositions, on the assumption that phrasal scope means that markers
are attached to the whole np (a phrase) rather than to the head noun (a word).
However, if carried through its logical conclusion, such an analysis would suggest, counterintuitively, that the English plural is a cliticized postposition: it too
has phrasal scope and the plural does not spread onto adjectives (as it does in
German, cf. gross-e Häuser with big-Ø house-s, where gross ‘big’ is marked as
plural in German – cf. gross-es Haus in the singular). Phrasal scope is a result
of morphological inertness; it does not require adpositions, i.e. syntactically
independent words.
Spreading of adpositions is rare. An example is preposition repetition in Old
Russian (Klenin (1989)):
(75)
Old Russian
a. za ego djadeju
za Matfěem”
after his uncle.instr after Matthew.instr
‘after his uncle Matthew’
b. pro kolokol” pro nemec’skyi
about bell.acc about German.acc
‘about (the) German bell’
In (75a), Matfěem” is in apposition to djadeju ‘uncle’, and in (75b) nemec’skyi
‘German’ is an adjective modifying kolokol” ‘bell’ and agreeing with it in
gender and number. In both, the preposition preceding the head noun spreads
to its modifier.
np-internal spreading can be subject to various restrictions. In several Finnic
languages, spreading is limited to only some of the cases and found on only some
adjectives. In Chechen, as shown in section 4.6 above, attributive adjectives
distinguish only nominative versus oblique cases, which is to say that all oblique
cases syncretize in spreading.
Inflectional morphology
237
It is common for case to be inert on continuous nps but spreading on discontinuous nps. In many languages, case agreement is found only when the
phrase is discontinuous, i.e., interrupted by other sentential material that does
not belong to the phrase. This is true of many Australian languages:
(76)
Warlpiri (Pama-Nyungan, C. Australia; Hale et al. (1995:1434))
a. [np [N maliki] [A wiri-ngki]] =ji
yarlku-rnu
dog
big-erg
=[perf-]1sg.p bite-past
‘A big dog bit me’
b. [N maliki-rli] =ji
yarlku-rnu [A wiri-ngki]
dog-erg =[perf-]1sg.p bite-past big-erg
‘A big dog bit me’
In (76a) the np is continuous, so there is no case agreement, but in (76b) case
agreement is a mandatory means for identifying the discontinuous parts of the
np.
Stacking of cases within nps is not uncommon; for surveys, see Plank (1995).
Often one of the cases is due to copying and one to assignment, as in Old
Georgian:
(77)
Old Georgian (Kartvelian; Fähnrich (1991:197))
a. saxl-man israeyl-isa-man
house-erg Israel-gen-erg
‘the house of Israel’
b. arkw dze-ta
israeyl-isa-ta
speak son-obl.pl Israel-gen-obl.pl
‘speak to the sons of Israel’
The genitive case in both examples is assigned by the adnominal construction,
and the ergative in (77a) and the oblique in (77b) are assigned to ‘house’ and
‘son’, respectively, and spread to ‘Israel’. Since stacking is most common in
adnominal constructions, cross-linguistically it is the genitive case – the universal default adnominal case – that is most prone to have another stacked onto
it.
Clause-level stacking of case suffixes is illustrated by Huallaga Quechua
and Kayardild. The Quechuan example involves copredicatives, as is relatively
common; the Kayardild one has ordinary clause members (see the discussion
of it above in section 6).
(78)
Huallaga Quechua (Quechuan, Peru; Weber (1989:221)) (= (53)
above)
Haacha-wan-naw mutu-n machiita-wan
axe-com-sim
chop-3 machete-com
‘He chops with a machete as though it were an axe’
238
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
Table 3.21 Behaviour of words and formatives with regard to
assignment, spreading, and stacking. Blanks mean that we have no
examples of that phenomenon
Assigned (inert):
Spreading:
Stacking
(79)
np
clause
np
clause
np
clause
Syntactic word
Formative
Engl. of, etc.
Engl. to on IO, etc.
Old Russian prep.
IE prep./preverb
adnominal genitive
case on arguments
IE case agreement
IE predicate nominals
Old Georgian, etc.
Kayardild modal case
IE prep./preverb
Kayardild (Tangkic, Australia; Dench and Evans (1988:34–5))28
(= (54) above)
maku-ntha yalawu-jarra-ntha yakura-naa-ntha
woman-obl catch-past-obl
fish-abl(prior)-obl
dangka-karra-nguni-naa-ntha
mijil-nguni-naa-nth
man-gen-instr-abl(prior)-obl net-instr-abl(prior)-obl
‘The woman must have caught fish with the man’s net’
Stacking of syntactic words appears to be less common than stacking of
cases. For example, where two prepositions would be assigned by the syntax in
Russian, the first is deleted. This happens in time expressions, as in (80), where
v ‘in’ would ordinarily be assigned to this kind of time adverbial, and here its
object happens to be a more or less fixed expression starting with a preposition,
bez chetverti . . . ‘a quarter to . . .’.
(80)
Russian
on prishel (*v) bez
chetverti sem’
he came at
without quarter 7
‘he came at a quarter to 7’
Perhaps this is preposition stacking with obligatory syncope.29
Table 3.21 summarizes the behaviour of formatives and words with regard
to assignment, spreading, and stacking.
28
29
For glossing of cases and the interlinear (prior) see ex. (54) above.
At one time, preposition stacking must have been possible in Russian, for there exist compound
prepositions such as iz-za ‘because of’ (lit.: ‘from-behind’), iz-pod ‘of, from’ (lit.: ‘from-under’).
Both govern the genitive (as iz does) and not the instrumental (as za and pod do).
Inflectional morphology
9
239
Conclusions
Morphological typology played a pioneering role in the development of typology in the nineteenth century, but in the second half of the last century, the
traditional approaches came under heavy criticism for conflating parameters
(see the discussion in section 1), and the field was often questioned for its
general usefulness (e.g. by Comrie (1981a)). However, advances in the theoretical understanding of the word – specifically, the systematic breakdown of
this notion into phonological and grammatical words – have now made it possible to put morphological typology on a more precise foundation. In addition,
since the 1990s, there has been a renewed interest in the theory of inflection
classes and this has improved the understanding of one of the most intricate
problems in morphology: allomorphy and the nature of paradigms. Further, the
grand renaissance of grammaticalization studies in the early 1990s has brought
with it much insight into the diachrony of morphology and its functional and
cognitive dimensions.
Together, these three strands of development have led to a rapid and theoretically diverse expansion of the field of morphology. Along with this, morphological typology has begun to survey the languages of the world with new
tools and analytical notions. We hope this chapter has shown that morphological typology can in turn improve descriptive analysis by paying close attention
to all parameters along which inflectional morphology varies.
10
Suggestions for further reading
General surveys of theoretical issues in inflectional morphology are Spencer
(1991) and Carstairs-McCarthy (1992). Spencer (1991) in particular, contains
a helpful discussion of the interaction of syntax and morphology, which has
been one of the traditional controversies of grammatical theory. See also S.
R. Anderson (1992) for a word-based approach. For a basic introduction to
morphology, see Haspelmath (2002); for general reference, consult Spencer
and Zwicky (1998) or Lehmann, Mugdan, and Booij (2000).
Some of the typological distinctions we draw here are treated under various
technical terms in generative frameworks, and are not always easy to recognize:
much discussion of synthesis and notions of wordhood (section 1) is currently
covered by literature on complex predicates, e.g. Alsina, Bresnan, and Sells
(1997) or Ackerman and Webelhuth (1998), and on what is called the principle of lexical integrity (e.g. Mohanan (1995); Bresnan and Mchombo (1995)).
On the phonological word, see in particular Hall and Kleinhenz (1999); on
grammatical word notions, see Di Sciullo and Williams (1987). The properties of layered morphology as distinct from templatic morphology (section
6) are attributed to the Mirror Principle, which states that the sequence of
240
Balthasar Bickel and Johanna Nichols
morphological operations mirrors syntactic tree and scope structure (Baker
(1985)). See Alsina (1999), Rice (2000), and Stump (2001) for some recent
controversial discussion. Pronominal agreement markers (section 8) are typically analysed in terms of movement from syntactic argument positions to their
morphological host. Grammatical agreement is analysed, by contrast, as basegeneration of markers (clitics, affixes) at the host; since such markers co-occur
with nps, the phenomenon is then also referred to as ‘clitic doubling’ in the
literature. See Spencer (1991:384–90) for a useful summary.