Greek reflections on the nature of music
Выбери формат для чтения
Загружаем конспект в формате pdf
Это займет всего пару минут! А пока ты можешь прочитать работу в формате Word 👇
This page intentionally left blank
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
In this book, Flora R. Levin explores how and why music was so
important to the ancient Greeks. She examines the distinctions
that they drew between the theory of music as an art ruled by
number and the theory wherein number is held to be ruled by the
art of music. These perspectives generated more expansive theories, particularly the idea that the cosmos is a mirror-image of
music’s structural elements and, conversely, that music by virtue
of its cosmic elements – time, motion, and the continuum – is
itself a mirror-image of the cosmos. These opposing perspectives
gave rise to two opposing schools of thought, the Pythagorean
and the Aristoxenian. Levin argues that the clash between these
two schools could never be reconciled because the inherent conflict arises from two different worlds of mathematics. Her book
shows how the Greeks’ appreciation of the profundity of music’s
interconnections with philosophy, mathematics, and logic led to
groundbreaking intellectual achievements that no civilization has
ever matched.
Flora R. Levin is an independent scholar of the classical world. She
is the author of two monographs on Nicomachus of Gerasa and
has contributed to TAPA, Hermes, and The New Grove Dictionary
of Music.
Greek Reflections on
the Nature of Music
Flora R. Levin
Independent scholar
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo
Cambridge University Press
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521518901
© Flora R. Levin 2009
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the
provision of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part
may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published in print format 2009
ISBN-13
978-0-511-54001-1
eBook (EBL)
ISBN-13
978-0-521-51890-1
hardback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy
of urls for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication,
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
To Sam
Contents
Figures
Preface
Introduction
Abbreviations
Texts
page viii
ix
xiii
xix
xxi
1 All Deep Things Are Song
1
2 We Are All Aristoxenians
48
3 The Discrete and the Continuous
88
4 Magnitudes and Multitudes
121
5 The Topology of Melody
154
6 Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
204
7 Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
241
8 The Infinite and the Infinitesimal
296
ΣФPAΓIΣ
303
Bibliography
Index
305
317
vii
Figures
1. The Immutable or Changeless (Ametabolon) System
page 52
2. Names of Ratios
67
3. Circle of Fifths
73
4. Paradigmatic System with Octave Species
76
5. Greater Perfect System: Lesser Perfect System
132
6. The Greater Perfect System Projected on the Zodiac
157
7. Six Meson Tetrachords Distributed Over Thirty Equal Parts
202
8. The Family of Ptolemaïs of Cyrene (?)
246
9. The Seven Tonoi of Ptolemy
269
10. The Harmonic Series
viii
287
Preface
This book owes its inception to the teachings of Dr. Seymour Bernstein:
distinguished pianist, composer, author, lecturer, and master teacher.
Dr. Bernstein is known and appreciated for the masterclasses in the art
of the piano, which he conducts throughout the United States, Canada,
Europe, and Asia. I count myself fortunate to have been granted admission to a number of these classes in New York City.
I was impressed early on in these classes by the way in which
Dr. Bernstein approached the practical knowledge that must be acquired
and implemented in the performance of music on the piano. Even more
impressive to me was Dr. Bernstein’s ability to demonstrate the transformation that must be worked on musical sound by the art of musicians.
For his treatment of this transformation was, as I understood it, philosophy in action. It was to resurrect the dream of Socrates that urged the
practice and composition of music as an imperative of philosophy. And
since Socrates regarded philosophy as “the greatest music,” he felt that
by spending his life working on all aspects of music, he was also practicing philosophy in the highest degrees (Plato Phaedo 61A3–8).
The philosophical component of Dr. Bernstein’s teachings made me
think of music even as the ancient Greeks did: as something that tends
to unity, like the course of human reason, while reaching for diversity, like the manifold forces of nature. The unity of reason organizes
and sets limits to things musical, while the forces of human nature
create things musical and set them free. These are the two principles
that Dr. Bernstein emphasized in his teachings. According to him, they
interpenetrate all musical thought, all musical creation, and all musical
performances. Given these principles, I was prompted to think of music
ix
x
Preface
as something manifold but unified, as something whose foundations
are in the human soul, not in matter; they are, rather, as something
next to which all particulars and partialities are dwarfed by the moving
forces of melody. This is to think of music in the way of nature. This is
to think of music in the way of Aristoxenus of Tarentum, a student of
Aristotle, and the greatest musician of antiquity.
Aristotle’s famous dictum has it that musical sound is a living sound
that originates in the human voice, and that all instruments, being
inanimate objects, are built to imitate the sound of the singing voice
(De anima 420b5–6). This finds strong confirmation in the teaching of
Dr. Bernstein. But, as he demonstrated, the piano, owing to its physical
construction, presents a paradox of philosophical dimensions: How can
the discrete pitches produced by the piano be made to imitate the living
continuity of the singing voice? The sustaining pedal goes far in overcoming this discontinuity of pitch. But something more basic is needed
if true artistry is to be achieved. To this end, Dr. Bernstein guided us to
concepts of musical function and musical space, of melodic tension and
resolution, of melodic motion and stasis – concepts that revolve around
the primary axis of Aristoxenian thought. Dr. Bernstein managed to lift
such concepts as these out of the textbooks and off the musical scores by
demonstrating them in living sound on the piano. He did this, much
as Aristoxenus must have done some twenty-five hundred years ago, by
using music as a symbol of itself. And, in the process, he revealed, as
complete musicians always succeed in doing, the composite nature of
music in all its flowing forms and multiforms.
In Dr. Bernstein’s classes, the truth of Aristoxenus’ teachings was first
revealed to me, namely, that the ultimate factor in making music is the
intellectual process; it is this intellectual process that presides over the
activity of the hands on the keyboard and is their determining principle.
When, therefore, I would hear Dr. Bernstein speak of the logic of a resolution, or the function of a particular note, or the tension between two
notes in a melodic phrase, I knew that he was releasing Aristoxenus’ own
concepts from out of the past and disposing them anew. My gratitude to
Dr. Bernstein is best expressed by the content of this book.
Many years have passed since I first began to think about the
woman scholar, Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, who appears in various contexts
Preface
xi
throughout this work. I wondered first of all who she was and when
she might have lived. Most important, she impressed me, even though
her words as quoted by Porphyry are all too few, as being exceptionally
astute where Aristoxenian theory is concerned. And since Aristoxenus
had few enough partisans in antiquity to champion his views on music
with any depth of understanding, whatever she had to say in his behalf
invited my closest study. I was encouraged in this inquiry by the late,
great, and good scholar, Professor Gilbert Highet, Anthon Professor of
Latin (Columbia University), who observed in what was to be his last
letter to me, “Her name alone intrigues for its history.” Coming as it
did from one whose instinctive recognition of a workable hypothesis
I had long since learned to trust, this observation sparked my imagination and led me to speculate on the kind of woman Ptolemaïs might
have been. I hope that the results of my inquiry are compatible with all
that Professor Highet had intuited from her name. I was also encouraged in this pursuit by the late Professor of Latin and Ancient History,
William C. McDermott (University of Pennsylvania). I regret that my
expression of gratitude to him for guiding me through the intricacies of
Hellenistic history must come too late for him to receive it.
I wish to express my deep appreciation of the late Professor Emeritus
of English, Comparative Literature, and Classical Studies, Albert Cook
(Brown University). His many contributions to the world of scholarship
in such diverse fields as Biblical Studies, History, Poetics, and Philosophy
have inspired and sustained me over the course of many years. Professor
Cook’s writings on Plato are especially compelling to me, not least for
being full of dialectical arguments; but above all, for their acute appraisal
of the poetic and musical aspects of Plato’s style. For Professor Cook,
Plato was the Beethoven of Philosophy. He demonstrated this most vividly in his analysis of Plato’s use of the Greek particles – “the riot of
particles,” as he so aptly called them (in The Stance of Plato) – which
make for the powerfully polyphonic texture of the Platonic dialogues.
Professor Cook’s scholarly originality and versatility, coupled with his
extraordinary breadth of knowledge, have earned my everlasting respect,
admiration, and, most of all, my gratitude for his help.
I am particularly indebted to my musically eloquent friend, Norma
Hurlburt, who placed at my disposal her comprehensive knowledge of
xii
Preface
the piano literature, especially that of Beethoven and Schubert. I owe
her thanks for spending many an hour with me speaking of music – the
art – and music – the epitome of logic. To this, she added many more
hours playing for me things that are more definite to musicians than the
meaning of words. Her ideas, both practical and theoretical, helped to
set this work in motion.
My sincere thanks are extended to Dr. Baylis Thomas, whose stimulating observations, drawn from his well-appointed knowledge of song,
convinced me that music, by its nature, has an inbuilt resistance to
theory. It is this that protects music from being demystified.
My obligations to others for their generous help are many: to
Dr. Alison Thomas for her contributions to this project through her
computer skills, which she so generously placed at my disposal. Her
expertise in this critical area is matched only by her pianistic gifts;
to the Near-Eastern Archaeologist and Historian, Dr. Oscar White
Muscarella, who supplied me with articles and special studies on the
history of, and excavations at, Cyrene; to Professor Emeritus of English
and Comparative Literature, William Sylvester (State University of
New York at Buffalo), with whom I enjoyed many lively discussions
on the acerbic views of the philosopher-poet, Philodemus of Gadara, for
whom the art of music was on a par with the art of cooking; to Professor
Emeritus of Indian History, Stanley Wolpert (University of California,
Los Angeles), who, with his wife, Dorothy, read various sections of this
work and offered valuable insights; to Professor of Classics, Jacob Stern
(Graduate Center, CUNY), for his help in checking the Greek text.
From the methods and experience of these erudite friends and scholars,
I have learned much.
I must also thank for their many kindnesses Sheran Maitland and
Diane Allen. My deep gratitude goes also to Beatrice Rehl, Publication
Director of Humanities at Cambridge University Press, and to Laura
Lawrie, Production Editor for Cambridge University Press.
One final debt, the greatest of all, is acknowledged in the
dedication.
Introduction
The peoples of ancient Greece surrounded themselves with music;
they immersed themselves in music; they were in fact imbued with
music. Scarcely any social or human function, whether public or private, urban or rural, took place without its musical accompaniment.
Marriages, banquets, harvestings, funerals – all had their distinctive
cadences. Boatmen rowed to the song of the aulos (the double-reed
oboe-like wind instrument), gymnasts exercised to music’s pulse, the
spirits of soldiers were sustained by its rhythmic lilt as they marched off
to battle. Instrumental music accompanied libations, sacrifices, supplications, religious processions, and ceremonial rites of all sort. Musical
contests drew throngs of knowing listeners. Singer-composers, who
set great numbers of poetic texts to song, which they then performed
from memory to the accompaniment of wind and stringed instruments,
were esteemed as repositories of knowledge. Solo instrumentalists could
stand as high in the public’s estimation as any athlete returning victorious from the Pan-hellenic games. In Attic tragedy, the recurring motifs
of the choral song not only unified the action on stage, but served also
the same virtuoso function as the divisions in a modern aria da capo.
In Attic comedy, the joy of life was celebrated in the ecstatic outpourings of licentious song, the chorus encircled by dancers whirling in the
drunken revelry of the lascivious kordax (a deliberately vulgar and at
times indecent dance). In sum, music was for the Greeks more, indeed,
much more than a pleasant preoccupation or source of amusement. It
was a significant part of life itself. That this was so is because the ancient
Greek language was itself a form of melodious expression.
xiii
xiv
Introduction
The melodious patterns of the ancient tongue were the products of
the pitch-accents that were integral to the meanings of the words. These
accents and melodious patterns were learned by the Greeks from infancy
on, undoubtedly leading to their heightened perception and retention
of pitch-differences in song and speech. As we learn from the fourthcentury b.c. musician and theorist Aristoxenus of Tarentum, there was a
kind of songful melody in everyday speech (λογῶδές τι μέλος).1 To distort
this pitch-accent was tantamount to committing an egregious grammatical error. A common example of this kinship between pitch-accent
and meaning is one that students meet early on in their study of the
ancient tongue, involving the difference in meaning between the two
otherwise identical words, βίος, βιός (respectively, “life” and “bow”). As
W. B. Stanford has pointed out in his ground-breaking study, The Sound
of Greek,2 “There were thousands of such words in ancient Greek if we
count the verbal inflexions which had different accentuations as well as
the nouns, pronouns, verbs, and adverbs.”
All classical Greek authors were thus composing for the ear as well as
for the mind; the meanings of their words depended in the fullest sense
on the semantic nature of their accompanying pitch-accents. This was
true no matter what the content or subject matter of their writings, be it
poetry, history, or even science and mathematics.3 Most important, the
Greek ear was trained to recognize the most subtle intonations in song
and speech. Their ability in this respect was apparently as remarkable as
that of people today who are possessed of absolute pitch.4 Sound was in
fact everything in antiquity and, not surprisingly, reciting aloud – more
often than not from memory – was the norm rather than the exception.
When it came to sound, therefore, the resources of the Greeks were
incalculable and superb. This bespeaks an acutely sensitive and highly
developed auditory sense on the part of performers as well as auditors.
Evidence that this was in fact so is unambiguous and voluminous.
1
2
3
4
Harm. El. 1. 18 (Da Rios 23. 14).
W. B. Stanford, The Sound of Greek, pp. 30–31.
See Stanford (note 2), pp. 8–9.
Absolute pitch is the miraculous ability to identify any pitch out of a melodic context, to name it, and even to reproduce it without mechanical aid of any sort. The
most famous example of this truly mysterious faculty is, of course, W. A. Mozart.
Introduction
xv
This evidence, in addition to being massive and diverse, suggests
the intriguing possibility that the Greeks may indeed have had absolute pitch. For research in this area has shown quite convincingly that
the acquisition of a tonal language may be one of the unusual conditions leading to the retention of and heightened sensitivity to pitch
distinctions.5 To be sure, nothing can be proven on this point, as the
ancient tonal systems were different from our own standards of pitch.
But, given the possibility, this would account for the Greeks’ ability
to discriminate between the most subtle colorations of pitch imaginable: differences such as quarter-tones, thirds of tones, even the lowering of a note by three-quarters of a tone (eklysis), or the raising of a
note by five quarter-tones (ekbolē). As their writings on music show,
every pitch range of the keys of transposition (tonoi), every mode (tropos), every genus (genos) possessed its own meaningful character (ethos).
Some sequences of notes were even defined by their “colors” or nuances
(chroai). Individual notes as the lichanos (finger-note) were recognized
for their distinctive quality, their “lichanos-ness” (lichanoid ), while
other notes were felt to have masculine or feminine characteristics.6
In short, this type of acute sensitivity to sound bespeaks a whole other
realm of perception.
So deep a penetration of music into almost every aspect of life presupposes a musically gifted public and a long tradition of musical education. The evidence appears in fact to depict a society concerned with
music more than anything else. The truth is, of course, that music
was only one of the myriad products of the Greek genius. What they
achieved in all else – poetry, drama, history, architecture, sculpture –
scaling heights that later civilizations have never surpassed – is familiar
to everyone. What is more, almost everything, music included, seems to
have begun with them.7 Mathematics and science were their inventions,
5
6
7
See Oliver Sacks, Musicophilia: Tales of Music and the Brain, pp. 113–14.
This is discussed by Aristides Quintilianus De mus, III, 21 (WinningtonIngram 122.22 123. 4), in which Aristides assigns male or female notes to the
planets according to their associative qualities.
Thus, Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy, p. 3: “What they [the
Greeks] achieved in art and literature is familiar to everybody, but what they
did in the purely intellectual realm is even more exceptional. They invented
xvi
Introduction
and philosophy, that most eloquent witness to the mind of man, was
their creation. When it came to music, the Greeks showed the same
organic point of view, the same instinct for formulating laws governing
reality that appears in every phase of their culture and art. As we learn
from the evidence presented to us, the Greeks were the first to intuit
music’s essence, and the first to discover the universal laws governing
its structure. They were the first to perceive the elements of music not
as isolated entities detached from one another but as integral parts of an
organic whole from which each part derived its meaning and position.
This book is an inquiry into the diverse ways in which the ancient
Greeks contemplated and dealt with the nature of music. My purpose
is to exhibit music as an integral part of their philosophical, mathematical, and cosmological pursuits. As their writings show, music was not
an isolated art whose sole purpose was to amuse and accompany secular
and religious activities. On the contrary, music was considered by them
to be as necessary as language and as rational as thought itself. As such,
it was regarded as powerfully paideutic, and productive of knowledge
for its own sake. Moreover, it was seen to be a genuine molder of human
character. What they achieved in music and musicology, although
comparable to their accomplishments in literature, art and science, philosophy, history, mathematics, and cosmology, has gained them far less
attention.
Acoustical theory is universally accepted to have begun with
Pythagoras of Samos (6th century b.c.). Deductive reasoning from general principles as applied to music was, as I argue, an innovation of
Aristoxenus of Tarentum (4th century b.c.), the leading figure in this
study. This method, together with Aristoxenus’ original and creative
use of mathematics, founded a centuries-long tradition, the main tenets
of which persist to this day.
Pythagorean harmonics was geometrical, not dynamic, whereas
Aristoxenus’ theory was not geometrical, but dynamic, by being rooted
in the continuity of infinite number. It was this dynamic that made
Aristoxenus’ theory a true Science (Epistēmē) of Melody. By contrasting
mathematics and science and philosophy; they first wrote history as opposed
to mere annals. . . . What occurred was so astonishing that, until very recent
times, men were content to gape and talk about the Greek Genius.”
Introduction
xvii
Aristoxenus’ unified theory with that of other specialists in the field, it
is possible to account for its peculiar meaning in regard to the nature
of music itself. To this end, translations from Ptolemy’s Harmonica,
from Porphyry’s Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics, and from the fragments of The Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music by the littleknown Ptolemaïs of Cyrene have been cast into the form of a dialogue.
This results in an interesting discussion among three experts on the
virtues and limitations of the various theories under examination. Of
the three, it is Ptolemaïs who seems to me to have grasped the uniqueness of Aristoxenus’ Aristotelian type of theoretical logistic. To her
credit, Ptolemaïs demonstrated that the geometrical method of the
Pythagoreans appealed solely to the eyes but that Aristoxenus’ system
was designed solely for the ears.
As I argue, Aristoxenus’ method is in essence a profoundly dialectic one from which he obtained a fixed constant of measurement.8 This
enabled him to deal with problems of attunement that could not be
solved by traditional methods of arithmetic and elementary geometry.
Through this technique, Aristoxenus arrived at the concept of continuity by observing the surrounding dense ( pykna) melodic media. The
deep-lying power of Aristoxenus’ method is that it enriches the study
of interrelations among discrete integers. In so doing, he summoned
to the aid of theorists new relations among continuous magnitudes. In
short, Aristoxenus, I believe, was practicing analytic number theory
centuries before its foundations were laid by such luminaries as Peter
Gustav Lejeune Dirichler, Bernhard Riemann, Georg Cantor, Leopold
Kronecker, and Karl Weierstrass.
8
Cf. F. R. Levin, “Apeiria in Aristoxenian Theory,” Hermes 135 (2007), 406–28.
Abbreviations
AJAH
American Journal of Ancient History
AJPh
American Journal of Philology
Barker, I Barker, A., Greek Musical Writing: I.
The Musician and His Art. Cambridge
University Press 1984.
Barker, II Barker, A., Greek Musical Writings: II
Harmonic and Acoustic Theory. Cambridge
University Press 1989.
Barker, Ptolemy Barker, A., Scientific Method in Ptolemy:
“Harmonics.” Cambridge University
Press 2000.
Bélis, Aristoxène Bélis, A., Aristoxène et Aristote: Le Traite
d’harmonique. Paris 1986.
BSA
Annual of the British School at Athens
CPh
Classical Philology
CQ
Classical Quarterly
JHS
Journal of Hellenic Studies
Laloy, Aristoxène Laloy, L., Aristoxène de Tarente. Disciple
d’Aristote et la Musique de l’Antiquité.
Paris 1904.
Macran Macran, H. S., The Harmonics of Aristoxenus.
Oxford: Clarendon 1902.
Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre Mathiesen, Th. J., Apollo’s Lyre. Greek
Music and Music Theory in Antiquity and
the Middle Ages. University of Nebraska
Press 1999.
xix
xx
Abbreviations
Michaelides Michaelides, S., The Music of Ancient Greece:
An Encyclopedia. London 1978.
PCPS Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological
Society
REG Revue des Études grecques
Solomon, Ptolemy Solomon, J., Ptolemy: Harmonics Translation
and Commentary. Leiden 2000.
White, The Continuous White, M. J., The Continuous and the
and the Discrete Discrete. Ancient Physical Theories from
a Contemporary Perspective. Oxford:
Clarendon 1992.
Texts
Caspar Caspar, M., Ioannis Keppleri Harmonices Mundi
Libri V. Munich 1940.
Cousin Cousin, V., Opera Petri Abaelardi. 2 vols. Paris
1849–59.
Da Rios Da Rios, R., Aristoxeni Elementa Harmonica. Rome
1954.
Deubner Deubner, L., Iamblichi De Vita Pythagorica Liber.
Leipzig 1937.
Düring Düring, I., Die Harmonielehre des Klaudios
Ptolemaios. Göteborg 1930 (Högskolas
Årsskrift, 36/1); rep. 1982.
Düring Düring, I., Porphyrios Kommentar zur Harmonielehre
des Ptolemaios. Göteborg 1932 (Göteborg 1932,
Göteborgs Högskolas Årsskrift); rep. 1978.
Düring Düring, I., Ptolemaios und Porphyrios Über die Musik.
Göteborg 1934 (Göteborgs Högskolas
Årsskrift, 40/1).
Friedlein Friedlein, G., Anicii Manlii Torquatii Severini
Boetii De Institutione Musica Libri Quinque.
Leipzig 1867; rep. 1966
Heath Heath, Sir Th. L. The Thirteen Books of
Euclid’s Elements. 3 vols. Cambridge 1925; rep.
1956.
Heiberg Heiberg, J. L., Claudii Ptolemii Syntaxis
Mathematica. 2 vols. Leipzig 1898–1903.
xxi
xxii
Texts
Hiller Hiller, E., Theonis Smyrnaei Philosophi Platonici
Expositio Rerum Mathematicarum ad Legendum
Platonem Utiliam. Leipzig 1878.
Hoche Hoche, R., Nicomachi Geraseni Pythagorei
Introdoctionis Arithmeticae Libri II. Leipzig
1866.
Jan Jan, K. von, Musici Scriptores Graeci. Leipzig
1895; rep. 1962.
Jonker Jonker, G. H., The Harmonics of Manuel Bryennius.
Groningen 1970.
Kemke Kemke, I., Philodemus De Musica Librorum Quae
Exstant. Leipzig 1884.
Meibom Meibom, M., Antiquae Musicae Auctores Septem.
2 vols. Amsterdam 1652; rep. 1977.
Najock Najock, D., Drei anonyme griechische Traktate
Über die Musik. Eine kommentierte Neuausgabe
des Bellermannschen Anonymus. Göttinger
Musikwissenschaftliche Arbeiten, vol. 2.
Göttingen 1972.
Pearson Pearson, L., Aristoxenus Elementa. The Fragment of
Book II and the Additional Evidence of Aristoxenean
Rhythmic Theory. Oxford: Clarendon 1990.
Pistelli Pistelli, H., Iamblichus In Nicomachi Arithmeticam
Introductionem Liber. Stuttgart 1894; rep.
addendis et corrigendis U. Klein 1975.
Ross Ross, Sir D., Aristotle’s Physics. Oxford: Clarendon
1955.
Vincent Vincent, A. J. H., “Notice sur divers manuscrits
grecs relatifs à la musique, comprenant une
traduction francaise et des commentaires,”
Notices ex extraits des manuscrits de la bibliotheque
du Roi et autres bibliotheques, vol. 16/2. Paris
1847.
Vors. Diels, H., and Kranz W., Die Fragmenta der
Vorsokratiker. Dublin/Zürich 1966.
Wachsmuth Wachsmuth, T. C., and Hense, O., Stobaei Eclogae,
vols. I–III. Leipzig 1884.
Texts
xxiii
Wehrli Wehrli, F., “Aristoxenus,” Die Schule des
Aristoles. Basle 1945.
Willis Willis, J., Martianus Capella. Leipzig 1983.
Winnington-Ingram Winnington-Ingram, R. P., Aristidis
Quintiliani De Musica Libri Tres. Leipzig
1963.
Ziegler-Pohlenz Ziegler, K., and Pohlenz, M., Plutarchi Moralis,
vol. VI, Fasc. 3. Leipzig 1953.
1 All Deep Things Are Song*
This world is not conclusion;
A sequel stands beyond,
Invisible, as music,
But positive, as sound.
Emily Dickinson
It is now above seventeen hundred years since Bacchius
the Elder (as he was then called),1 a Greek writer on music, opened
his Introduction to the Art of Music with the seemingly artless question:
“What is music?”2 The answer given by Bacchius to that question
1
Bacchius Geron, like other ancient musicologists – Cleonides, Gaudentius,
Alypius, Aristides Quintilianus, et alii – is today an unknown and obscure
figure, leaving no posterity. Yet, he mattered once, so much so, it seems, as
to have had his work on music studied by no less a figure than the Emperor
Constantine the Great (285–337 a.d.). A curious epigram attached by one
Dionysius (himself unknown), to several manuscripts containing Bacchius’
treatise on music makes for this interesting possibility. It states: “Bacchius
the Elder compiled the keys, modes, melodies and consonances of the art of
music. Writing in agreement with him, Dionysius explains that the almighty
emperor Constantine was a learned devotee of the arts. For, being a discoverer
and dispenser of all the learned disciplines, it is befitting that he was in no wise
a stranger to this one.” Everything that can be known of Bacchius is reviewed
and assessed by Thomas J. Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 583–93.
2 Bacchius’ Introduction to the Art of Music (Eisagōgē Technēs Mousikēs) was first published in 1623 by Frederic Morellus and, in the same year, by Marin Mersenne.
*
Thomas Carlyle
1
2
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
illustrates wonderfully the ancient Greeks’ passion for logic: “It is a
conceptual knowledge of melody and all that pertains to melody.”3
There is in Bacchius’ answer a dynamic reciprocity: melody provides
the conditions for music’s existence, while music at the same time subsists by virtue of melody. After detailing all the elements that pertain to
melody – pitch, interval, consonance, dissonance, scales, modes, modulation, keys, rhythm, and much more – Bacchius arrived at not one but
two different definitions of melody. The first is deliberately circular: “It
is the fall and rise generated by melodious notes.”4 Such a definition is
tantamount to asserting that something is a melody because its constituents are melodious. If Bacchius’ definition is in fact tautological, it
seems to be so consciously, in order that it be correct on purely musical grounds. It arises from Bacchius’ belief that nothing in the world
outside of melody can be invoked or enlisted to define anything that
The treatise is written in a question and answer format like that of the Ps.Aristotle Problems (Book 11 On the Voice and Book 19 On Harmonia) and The
Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music by the remarkable Ptolemaïs of
Cyrene, of whose work only fragments remain. See Chapters 6 and 7. Bacchius’
treatise belongs to the school of Aristoxenus, “The Musician,” as he was known
in antiquity, who, unlike Bacchius, did leave a considerable posterity. The
Greek text from which these translations are drawn is that of K. von Jan, Musici
Scriptores Graeci, pp. 292–316 (hereafter referred to as Jan). On its English translation, see Chapter 2, note 2. Another has been promised by Jon Solomon, one
of the few scholars who has examined the work, in his “EKBOLE and EKLUSIS
in the Musical Treatise of Bacchius,” Symbolae Osloenses 55 (1980), 122, n. 1. The
question that opens the treatise appears at I . 1 ( Jan, 292. 3).
3 I. 1 (Jan, 292. 3–4). There is an unmistakably Platonic cast to Bacchius’ definition of music. His term eidēsis (which I have rendered as “conceptual knowledge”) links “knowing” (eidōs) with “seeing” (eidon) and, as such, has a strong
relationship with Plato’s eidōs-eidē, the terms canonized by Plato as “Form” and
“Forms” and abstracted by him into “Ideas.” In Plato, the eidē are the cause
of true knowledge (epistēmē), inasmuch as they are the eternal realities that
transcend the merely sensible phenomena (aisthēta). The eidē are therefore the
condition of all true philosophical discourses. See Phaedo 65D–E; Parmenides
135B–C). Bacchius’ definition thus recognizes the mental activity (eidēsis) of
the knowing mind by which the melodic concept of Form (eidōs) is grasped.
4 I. 19 (Jan, 297. 22–23). The words for “fall” and “rise” are in Aristoxenian
terms anesis and epitasis, which have the literal meanings, “resolution” and
“tension,” respectively. These words are discussed below, n. 41.
All Deep Things Are Song
3
lies within the precincts of melody. Bacchius’ approach to the nature
of melody adumbrates almost eerily what Ludwig Wittgenstein was to
observe centuries later:5 “Die Melodie ist eine Art Tautologie, sie ist in
sich selbst abgeschlossen; sie befriedigt sich selbst. [Melody is a form of
tautology, it is complete in itself; it satisfies itself.]”
Like Bacchius, Wittgenstein evidently contemplated music not in
any sense as a language, but as an activity of some sort. And Bacchius,
like Wittgenstein, seems to have treated music as an activity whose subject matter is not in any sense factual, but whose processes and results are
somehow equivalent. Accordingly, where Bacchius found logic in melody, Wittgenstein found melody in logic:6 “Die musicalischen Themen
sind gewissen Sinne Sätze. Die Kenntnis des Wesen der Logik wird
deshalb zur Kenntnis des Wesens der Musik führen. [Musical themes
are in a certain sense propositions. Knowledge of the nature of logic will
for this reason lead to knowledge of the nature of music.]”
In Wittgenstein’s view, a melody, like a logical proposition, must make
sense strictly according to its own terms in order to attain to the condition of music. The implication is that the condition of music, in order to
be true to itself, must inhere in the logical constants of melody.
Like a mathematical proposition that uses numerical signs and symbols to designate an intricate truth, a melody employs certain logical
constants, which are preserved by notational signs and symbols, in order
to make musical sense. The proposition that 7 + 5 = 12 is necessarily
true for a mathematician, whether the symbols stand for apples, peaches,
trees, or anything else; it holds true because it defines an unchanging
relation, one that holds independently of the objects involved or of the
mind that contemplates them. Thus, to ascertain that the mathematical
proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is correct, we do not have to study the universe;
we have merely to check the meaning of the numerical symbols. They
assert that 7 + 5 has the same meaning as 12, and this amounts to a
mathematical truth – a truth that, by its very nature, is a tautology.
So, too, the pitches C–C¹, for example, define a melodic constant, one
that stands for nothing in the world save itself. This holds true whether
these pitches be struck on a piano, bowed on a violin string, or blown
5
6
Notebooks, 1914–16, p. 40, 4.3.15.
Notebooks, 1914–16, p. 40, 7.2.15.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
4
on an ancient Greek aulos. The melodic constant defined by the pitches
C–C¹ is an unchanging relation – that of an octave. C–C¹ means “octave”
to a musician and, as such, is a form of tautology.7
In the case of mathematics, we perceive the unchanging relation in
an arithmetic proposition such as that given earlier, not in virtue of the
symbols as phenomenal entities in themselves but by their intervention
as symbols standing for phenomenal entities; in the case of music, we
perceive the unchanging relation not by the intervention of the symbols
representing something else but as phenomenal entities in themselves.8
In other words, the octave C–C¹, whether written in alphabetic notation
(as here) or as notes on a staff, is the octave C–C¹ at that specific pitch
range. Numbers, unlike the musical notes that make up a melody, are
needed not only to compose mathematical propositions, but also, if they
are to have a specific meaning, to stand for or apply to common objects
in the world. It is only when numbers are abstracted from the objects
of the world or understood independently of the world that they begin
to assume the characteristics of musical notes. Like a musical note, the
number 2, say, is not the same as or identical with anything in the world.
It is 2 and, as such, is not identical with a duo of musicians; rather, the
duo of musicians is an instance of the number, 2; and the number, 2, is
an instance of itself. The note C, is in this sense an instance of itself.9
Given such an instance, the subject matter of music, like that of pure
7
The convention for indicating pitch adopted here is that of Carl E. Seashore,
Psychology of Music, p. 73. This tautological type of formulation is seen by many
as a logical trick that is a favorite device of mathematicians. For example, Susan
Langer, Philosophy in a New Key, p. 237: “Musical form, they reply, is its own
content; it means itself. This evasion was suggested by [Eduard] Hanslick
when he said, ‘The theme of a musical composition is its essential content.’”
8 Thus Langer, op. cit., p. 19: “Mathematical constructions are only symbols; they
have meanings in terms of relationships, not of substance; something in reality
answers to them, but they are not supposed to be items in that reality. To the
true mathematician, numbers do not ‘inhere in’ denumerable things, nor do
circular objects ‘contain’ degrees. Numbers and degrees and all their ilk only
mean the real properties of real objects.”
9 This is another way of saying that music is non-representational. Because it
exhibits its own pure form as its own essence, it is altogether untranslatable
into any other medium save itself. It is in this sense wholly tautological, as
Wittgenstein observed (see note 5). Cf. Peter Kivy, Music Alone, pp. 66–67.
All Deep Things Are Song
5
mathematics, belongs to a realm of idealized abstractions in which the
composer of music or the mathematician performs specific operations
with an extrawordly creative freedom.
It was perhaps his intuition of this curious affiliation between
music and mathematics that led Pythagoras of Samos (sixth century
b.c.), the most influential mathematician of antiquity, to make music
a matter for serious philosophical reflection. As reported by Athenaeus
of Naucratis (160–230 a.d.), an authority on the musical lore of
antiquity:10 “Pythagoras, who occupied so very great a position in philosophy, stands out among the many for having taken up music not as
an avocation; indeed, he explains the very being of the whole universe as
bound together by music.” Pythagoras’ intuition along these lines was
to produce one of the most momentous discoveries of all time: musical
sound is ruled by number. This meant nothing less than that the whole
universe, as being bound together by music, must itself be ruled by
number.11
10
Athenaeus of Naucratis in Egypt wrote a monumental work entitled
Deipnosophistai (Sophists at Dinner) sometime after the death of the Emperor
Commodus (180–92 a.d.). The work consisted originally of fifteen volumes.
Much is lost, but what remains of Books IV and XIV in particular is valuable
for preserving information on music and musical practices from much earlier sources such as Pindar (c. 522–c. 446 b.c.), Bacchylides (c. 520–c. 450
b.c.), Damon, the teacher of Socrates (5th century b.c.), Hesiod (c. 700 b.c.),
Aristotle (384–322 b.c.), Aristoxenus of Tarentum (b.c. 375 b.c.; his date of
death is unknown), the leading musician and musical theorist of antiquity. The
passage quoted here is from Book XIV, 632b.
11 The literature on Pythagoras and his discovery of the mathematical ratios underlying the production of musical pitches is vast enough to make up an entire
library. Some of the comprehensive studies are: P.-H. Michel, De Pythagore à
Euclide; P. Kucharski, Étude sur la doctrine pythagoricienne de la tétrade; E. Frank,
Plato und die sogennanten Pythagoreer; A. E. Chaignet, Pythagore et la philosophie
pythagoricienne; A. Delatte, Études sur la littérature pythagoricienne; H. Thesleff,
An Introduction to the Pythagorean Writings of the Hellenistic Period; H. Thesleff,
The Pythagorean Texts of the Hellenistic Period; W. Burkert, Lore and Science in
Ancient Pythagoreanism; W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 1:
The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans; J. A. Philip, Pythagoras and Early
Pythagoreanism; K. S. Guthrie, The Pythagorean Sourcebook and Library; J. Godwin,
The Harmony of the Spheres: A Sourcebook of the Pythagorean Tradition. Pythagoras’
reputation is summed up accordingly by G. E. Owen, The Universe of the Mind,
6
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
On the basis of the truths arrived at by mathematical means,
Pythagoras and his followers could think of music’s elements as concrete
realities linked by number to nature’s own divine proportions. At the
same time, they could think of music itself as the expression in sound
of those same proportions by which nature asserts her divine symmetry.
This being the case, the universal order of things could be said to have
its counterpart in the underlying structures of harmonic theory. The
notion that music owes its life to mathematics, and that the universe,
by the same agency, owes its soul to harmonia – the attunement of opposites – took hold of human imagination from its first utterance and has
transfixed it for the millennia.12
It was during that brilliantly fecund period when Aeschylus was
producing his dramas and Pindar his Odes that Pythagoras made the
discovery about music, a discovery that reverberates to this day. As far
as we can ascertain, no Greek-speaking person had ever committed
the story of the discovery to writing before Nicomachus of Gerasa, the
“Pythagorean,” so-called, a once famous mathematician living at the
turn of the century, 100 a.d.13 According to Nicomachus, Pythagoras
had long been pondering the problem of how to translate the musical
sounds he produced on the strings of his lyre into some sort of concrete
form that his eye could see and his mind could contemplate. While
deliberating about this problem, he happened to be walking by a smithy
12
13
p. 26: “Born about 573 b.c.e. on Samos, according to legend Pythagoras
became the ideal of mathematics, a philosopher and a prophet, apotheosized in
his own lifetime by his own society.”
The moment Pythagoras discovered that the lengths of a vibrating string
sounding a fundamental pitch, its fifth, its fourth, and its octave, are in the
ratios 2: 3: 4, he heard the harmonia of the universe and defined the ordering
of its elements (stoicheia) in numerical terms. From now on, nature and all its
properties were to be found in the science of number. Cf. H. E. Huntley, The
Divine Proportion, pp. 51–56. It is thus to Pythagoras that we owe the first conception of the universe as a harmony patterned on music. For because sounds
were shown to be the embodiment of numbers, it was conceivable that mundum
regunt numeri, that the world was in fact ruled by number.
Nicomachus tells the story of Pythagoras’ discovery in his Harmonikon
Enchiridion (Manual of Harmonics), Ch. 6 ( Jan, 245.19–248). The Manual,
together with ten Excerpta from a lost work of Nicomachus, is translated by
Levin, The Manual of Harmonics of Nicomachus the Pythagorean.
All Deep Things Are Song
7
where, by sheer good fortune, he heard the smith’s hammers beating
out on the anvil a whole medley of pitches. These registered on his ear
as the same consonances that he could produce on his lyre-strings – the
octave, the fifth, and the fourth – as well as the dissonance separating
the fourth from the fifth – the whole-tone.
Intuiting that the size of the sounding body had something to do
with the differences between the pitches he heard, Pythagoras ran into
the smithy, conducted a series of experiments, which he repeated at
home, and came upon the elegantly simple truth about musical sound:
the pitch of a musical sound from a plucked string depends upon the
length of the string. This led him to discover that the octave, the fifth
and the fourth, as well as the whole-tone, are to each other as the ratios
of the whole numbers. These, the harmonic ratios, as they came to be
called, are all comprehended in a single construct: 6:8 :: 9:12. This
means that the octave may be represented by 12:6 or 2:1; the fifth by
12:8 or 3:2; the fourth by 12:9 or 4:3. Moreover, the fifth may also be
represented by 9:6 = 3:2, and the fourth by 8:6 = 4:3. The whole-tone,
being the difference between the fifth and the fourth, is represented by
9:8, a ratio that cannot on division yield a pair of whole numbers. That
is, dividing 9:8 gives 3:2√2, an irrational or alogos number.
In the deceptively simple construct – 6:8 :: 9:12 – there are contained
all the primary constituents of music’s elemental structure and, inferentially, the harmonic symmetry of the universe. What is more, there
is embodied in this set of ratios the original Pythagorean tetraktys, the
ensemble of the four primary numbers – 1, 2, 3, 4 – that became the
corner-stone of the Pythagorean philosophy of number. From the intrinsic properties of this – the tetraktys of the decad – the sum of whose
terms equals the number 10, there were harvested in turn the theory of
irrationals, the theory of means and proportions, the study of incommensurables, cosmology, astronomy, and the science of acoustics.14 Because
14
The original Pythagorean tetraktys or quaternary represented the number 10 in
the shape of a perfect triangle composed of four points on each side. It showed
at a glance how the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4 add up to ten. The number 10 was thus
regarded as sacred, since it comprehended the equivalent in each of its terms to
the universal components of the point (= 1), the line (= 2), the triangle (= 3),
the pyramid (= 4). What is more, it contained in its terms the basic elements
8
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
“truth is truth to the end of reckoning,” the harmonic properties of these
numbers are as true today as they were for Pythagoras when he first discovered them. But a by-product of Pythagoras’ discovery turns out to be
the most stubborn problem in the science of acoustics: the incommensurability of the whole-tone. Interestingly enough, the same irrational
number that appears on the division of the whole-tone was found by
Pythagoras to obtain between the side of a square and its diagonal. In the
one case, that of the whole-tone in the ratio 9:8, the division for obtaining a semi-tone, or one half of a whole-tone, produces the square root
of 2. In the case of the geometric square, the Pythagorean theorem demonstrates that if the length of the side is 1 inch, the number of inches in
the diagonal is also the square root of 2. As George Owen explains, this
discovery was greeted with little joy by the Pythagoreans:15
Having founded their order on the purity of number, the Pythagoreans were
dismayed to discover the existence of the irrational number. Such numbers
may well have played an important role in their mystery rites. Soon after the
death of Pythagoras, Hippasus [an acoustical expert from Metapontum] . . .
communicated his [Pythagoras’] views and some of the Pythagorean doctrines
to outsiders. For this he and his followers were expelled from the society.
The problem of irrationality for mathematicians was eventually resolved
by a feat of intellectual genius: the reduction of arithmetic to logic.16
15
16
of music: 2:1 (octave), 3:2 (fifth), 4:3 (fourth), 4:1 (double octave). Cf. Owen
(above, n. 11), pp. 27–28. The literature on the tetraktys is vast. For pertinent references, see F. R. Levin, The Harmonics of Nicomachus and the Pythagorean
Tradition, p. 65, n. 62.
Owen (note 11), p. 32. Just as no fraction will express exactly the length of
the diagonal of a square, so too, no fraction will express exactly the size of the
musical interval that registers on the ear as a semi-tone. The division of both
the diagonal and the whole-tone yield the same irrational. As Bertrand Russell,
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, p. 67 observed: “This seems like a challenge thrown out by nature to arithmetic. However the mathematician may
boast (as Pythagoras did) about the power of numbers, nature seems able to
baffle him by exhibiting lengths which no numbers can estimate in terms of
the unit.”
The fundamental thesis to which Bertrand Russell devoted his Principles of
Mathematics (1903) is that all the constants that occur in pure mathematics are
All Deep Things Are Song
9
For musicians, the incommensurability of the whole-tone was resolved
by an intellectual feat of no less brilliance: the well-tempered system of
tuning.17
Because of the deep and far-reaching implications that Pythagoras’
discovery had for such fundamental branches of knowledge as mathematics, cosmology, and astronomy – implications that extended far
beyond its immediate utility in converting the sensory distinctions
of pitch and interval into objective numerical form – it was treated
by the ancients as a divine revelation. The story of Pythagoras’ experiments with stretched strings and various other instruments such as
panpipes, monochords, auloi, and triangular harps, and the dazzling
discovery to which these experiments led, having once been told by
Nicomachus, was passed along through the centuries in an unbroken
tradition from one (now) obscure writer to another: from the musical
theorist Gaudentius, surnamed “The Philosopher” (2nd or 3rd century
a.d.), to the Neo-Platonist, Iamblichus (c. 250–c. 325 a.d.), to the bio
grapher of ancient philosophers, Diogenes Laertius (3rd century a.d.),
to the Roman grammarian, Censorinus (3rd century a.d.), thence to
17
logical constants; that, hence, the truths of mathematics can be derived from
logical truths. As Russell argued, in order to deal with the two great sources
of irrational numbers – the diagonal of the square and the circumference of the
circle – the logical notion of spatial continuity had to have been introduced as
an axiom ad hoc (pp. 438–39). In thus generalizing the notion of spatial continuity to the utmost, Russell created a set of new deductive systems, in which
traditional arithmetic – which had laid bare the irrationality of the diagonal
of a square and the circumference of the circle – was at once dissolved and
enlarged. He observes in Mathematics and Logic, p. 196: “. . . we have, in effect,
created a set of new deductive systems, in which traditional arithmetic is at
once dissolved and enlarged . . .”
It will be argued below (pp. 202ff.) that Aristoxenus, the major source of such
logically-minded musical theorists as Bacchius the Elder and others, attacked
the problem of the irrationality of musical space in much the same way as
that described by Russell; that is, he began by introducing the logical notion
of spatial continuity as a necessary axiom ad hoc. This led him to dissolve and
enlarge what had been for him traditional mathematics – Pythagorean harmonics. Logic and the establishment of logical constants led him finally to the
monumental accomplishment for which he is credited in these pages: equal
temperament.
10
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Chalcidius, honored for his commentary on Plato’s Timaeus (4th century
a.d.), to the illustrious polymath, Macrobius, known for his commentary on Cicero’s Somnium Scipionis (4th–5th century a.d.), to Fulgentius
(c. 467–532 a.d.), famed for his writings on mythology. Finally, the
tale of Pythagoras’ discovery was deposited with the towering scholar,
Boethius (480–524 a.d.), who honored Nicomachus by translating his
account into Latin. Thereafter, it was preserved for posterity by one of
the most important links between the scholarship of antiquity and that
of the Middle Ages, Isidore of Seville (570–636 a.d.),18 reappearing
with various embellishments in the account of the Patriarch, André de
Crète, surnamed Hagiopolites (died 8th century a.d.).19
Pythagoras’ revelation of the affinity between music, mathematics,
and philosophy has lost none of its majesty in these many retellings;
if anything, it has gained power and importance through the numerous scientific investigations it set into motion long after its institution
in the scientific literature.20 Indeed, according to general opinion, no
18
19
20
Another tradition, existing quite apart from the Pythagorean, connects the
legendary discovery of the concordant intervals produced on the anvil with
the smith’s hammers to the Idean Dactyls, so-called, the dwarfish craftsmen of
ancient Phrygian chronicles – ancient Nibelungen, as it were – the servants of
the Asian Goddess, Rhea Kybele. This tradition is discussed by Eric Werner,
The Sacred Bridge, pp. 376–77. Still another tradition is to be found in Genesis
4.21, where the discovery of music and the harp is attributed to Jubal, the
descendant of Cain. The inference is that the connection between music and
number had been arrived at independently of Pythagoras and quite possibly
long before him. This is argued by Otto Neugebauer, The Exact Sciences in
Antiquity, pp. 35–36.
The account of the Hagiopolites differs interestingly from that of Nicomachus.
For whereas Nicomachus portrays Pythagoras as experimenting with various
kinds of instruments, finally settling on the monochord as the most convenient for his purposes, the Hagiopolites describes Pythagoras as building a
four-stringed lute-type instrument, an instrument which he named Mousikē.
This account is to be found in one place only, that of A. J. H. Vincent, in the
sixteenth volume of a very rare and beautiful book entitled Notice sur divers
manuscrits grec relatif à la musique, pp. 266–68.
Thus, Sir Thomas Heath. Aristarchus, pp. 46–47: “The epoch-making discovery that musical tones depend on numerical proportions, the octave representing the proportion of 2:1, the fifth 3:2, and the fourth 4:3, may with sufficient
certainty be attributed to Pythagoras himself, as may the first exposition of
All Deep Things Are Song
11
discovery of comparable magnitude was made until the seventeenth
century, when Marin Mersenne, the French mathematician, philosopher, and scientist, first explained in his Harmonie Universelle the
relations obtaining between tension and the frequency of vibration
of a stretched string, relations subsequently codified in “Mersenne’s
Laws.”21 The discovery of these relations was made independently by
Galileo Galilei (1564–1642), the son of the musician, Vincenzo Galilei;
and subsequent investigations conducted by Isaac Newton (1642–
1727), Leonard Euler (1707–83), and Daniel Bernoulli (1700–82)
revealed that the harmonic ratios were not confined to string lengths,
but belonged to the musical intervals produced by all instruments.
Hermann Helmholtz (1821–94), a man who not only unified the practice and teaching of such sciences as medicine, physiology, physics,
and anatomy, but who also related them lastingly to the art of music,
was uniquely qualified to speak of Pythagoras’ discoveries; he assessed
them in these terms:22
This relation of whole numbers to musical consonances was from all time
looked upon as a wonderful mystery of deep significance. The Pythagoreans
themselves made use of it in their speculations on the harmony of the
spheres. From that time it remained partly the goal and partly the starting point of the strangest and most venturesome, fantastic or philosophic
speculations, till in modern times the majority of investigators adapted
the theory of means, and of proportion in general applied to commensurable
quantities, i.e. quantities the ratio between which can be expressed as a ratio
of whole numbers. The all-pervading character of number being thus shown,
what wonder that the Pythagoreans came to declare that number is the essence
of all things? The connection so discovered between number and music would
also lead not unnaturally to the idea of the ‘harmony of the heavenly bodies.’”
Cf. O’Meara, Pythagoras Revived. pp. 14ff.
21 As Mersenne demonstrated, the peculiar relation obtaining between tension
and frequency of vibration is such that the latter – the frequency of vibration –
is the square root of the former – the amount of tension. The details are to be
found in M. Mersenne, First Book of String Instruments, Prop. VII, Sixth Rule,
p. 177. “Mersenne’s Laws” are discussed by Alexander Wood, The Physics of
Music, pp. 90–92 and related by him to the construction of the modern pianoforte. Cf. Levin, “Plēgē and Tasis,” 206, n.2.
22 H. Helmholtz, On the Sensation of Tone, p. 15.
12
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the notion accepted by Euler himself, that the human mind had a peculiar
pleasure in simple ratios, because it could better understand them and their
bearings.
Musicians have always seen powerful connections between the
working dynamics of their art and the combinatorial logic of mathe
matics and, to this day, will invoke purely mathematical concepts to
explain various aspects of their discipline. Statements such as: “music
is the organization of a certain finite number of variables”; or, “sound
is heard number; number is latent sound”;23 or, “a fugal theme, like
a mathematical equation, is subject to inversions, augmentation, and
diminution,” all reflect this sensibility. Such statements seem to gratify the need for certainty that musicians crave in discussing their art.
Mathematicians, by contrast, whose working facts are nothing if not
certain, see their discipline as no less aesthetic in its technical processes
than is the art of music in the abstract. They testify to their sensibility
on this point by assigning to the working dynamics of their discipline
such musical characteristics as cadences, modulations, phrases, and
tempos. Morris Kline speaks of the mathematician’s aesthetic sensibility in these terms:24
In the domain of algebra, calculus, and advanced analysis especially, the
first-rate mathematician depends on the kind of inspiration that we usually associate with the composer of music. The composer feels that he has
a theme, a phrase which, when properly developed and embroidered, will
produce beautiful music. Experience and a knowledge of music aid him in
developing it. Similarly, the mathematician divines that he has a conclusion
which will follow from the axioms.
More recently, Edward Rothstein defined the link between music
and mathematics as “something that mathematics and music share with
our notions of the universe and our notion of the mind and soul – and
23
24
Thus, Edward Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, p. 23: “In this way, sounds and
numbers have become intimately related. And their connection is not arbitrary.
It is not a metaphor: if we interpret the words properly, sound is simply heard
number, number is latent sound.”
Morris Kline, Mathematics in Western Culture, pp. 457–58.
All Deep Things Are Song
13
our notion of beauty as well.” To this determinedly Pythagorean view of
things, he adds the following:25
Both music and mathematics create order, worlds in which processes occur,
relationships are established, and elements are regulated. These worlds possess structures that might be mapped into our own: they might be similar
in the strongest sense the mystics allow.
Miraculously, the dialectical steps by which the Pythagoreans converted music – the most unfathomable and inscrutable of the arts –
into a branch of mathematical science were in turn diverted by them to
transform astronomy – the most conspicuous and mathematical of the
sciences – into the unheard archetype of music. Their point of departure
was motion. Thus, they argued, if motion, as of vibrating strings, air
columns, and percussion instruments, is the cause of pitch variation,
and the primary exemplar of motion is present in the rotations of the
celestial bodies through space, it should follow that these macro-cosmic
motions of the planets must themselves produce pitches.26 Moreover,
that the pitches presumed to be generated in this way are musical may
be attributable to the continuous, uniform, and regular motion that the
planets execute in their orbits. And because the relative pitch of any
musical sound is a function of the velocity of the moving object, the
pitches emitted by the planets in their courses through the ether should
necessarily vary with their individual speeds. As Nicomachus explained
25
26
Rothstein (note. 23), p. 30. Along these lines Rothstein quotes to excellent effect
the words of the nineteenth-century mathematician, James Joseph Sylvester,
from a paper on Isaac Newton: “May not music be described as the Mathematics
of sense, Mathematics as Music of the reason?” (Rothstein, p. 31).
In the third chapter of his Manual (Jan, 241–42), Nicomachus provides what
may be the most ancient version of this distinctly Pythagorean-Platonic concept. He began, as did Plato, by enlisting only those propositions whose truth
can be verified by mathematics. From that point on, he saw to it that his concept of celestial motion should rest upon the same mathematical bases as those
underlying acoustical motion. To this end, he followed the Pythagoreans and
Plato in lifting what appears to be a purely poetic notion into the precincts of
science. See Burkert (above, note 11), pp. 352–55; Barker, II, p. 251, n. 17 and
n. 20. Nicomachus’ description of the heavenly order is analyzed in Levin (note
13), pp. 47–57.
14
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
in his account of the Pythagoreans’ cosmic view, the variation in pitch
imputed to the planets is a function of their mass, speed, and orbital
position.27
With this line of reasoning, the conditions were set for so thorough
a union of harmonics and astronomy that henceforth the mathematical laws underlying the one could be held to account for the harmonic
perfection seen in the other. There was required only the addition of
a single proposition to complete an incorruptible circle of necessity
wherein harmonics and astronomy would find their common bond in
number: the harmonic sectioning of the heavens. This was done by the
planets, whose orbital distances from one another conformed to the concordant distribution of pitches in a well-attuned musical scale. It could
now be assumed that the harmonious properties of music, discoverable
in the mutual relations of number, are implicit in the planetary order.
Accordingly, by virtue of their being distant from one another in the
same relative degrees as the notes of a well-attuned scale – these degrees
of difference dictated by the mathematical ratios determining the concordant intervals making up the octave, the perfect consonance – the
planets could be shown to trace harmonic boundaries in the heavens.
And, conversely, the structural elements of music could be said to imitate the heavenly paradigm in all its particulars.28
The task of reconciling this conception of a harmonic universe with
the astronomical phenomena produced diverse theories and rationalizations, all assembled under the traditional title “Harmony of the
Spheres,” the ultimate expression of which is found in Plato’s Timaeus.
For Plato, the intrinsic meaning of music lay, therefore, in the concept
27
Manual, Chapter 3 ( Jan, 241. 12–15). As Barker, II, p. 251, n.18 sees it,
“. . . the sense is not that the planets differ from one another in the positions of
their orbits in space (i.e., in the distances of their orbits from the earth), but
that their orbits have different ranges of variation.”
28 This concept of a universe animated by the same physical laws that underlie the
tuning of the lyre and invested with the composite symmetry and serene regularity of a musical attunement (harmonia) could free man, in a metaphoric leap, from
the prosaic notion that life is altogether incongruous and man himself totally
insignificant. The notion of musical instruments as expressions of the universe
was gloriously rendered by Robert Fludd (1574–1637), whose cosmic lute, once
seen, is never to be forgotten. See Jocelyn Godwin, Robert Fludd, pp. 45ff.
All Deep Things Are Song
15
of harmonia, the attunement, or proper “fitting together,” of opposites.29
That the movements in space by the heavenly bodies were, like the wellattuned pitches of a melodious movement, harmonious in their combined perfection of uniform, circular, and constantly regular courses, is
an assumption that dominated astronomy from the time of Plato down
to that of Kepler.30 The various theories that derived from this assumption, whether heliocentric, like those of Aristarchus and Copernicus,
or geocentric, like that of Ptolemy, found their explicit formulation
29
30
In the Timaeus 35B–36B, Plato, without having to appeal to the empirical
evidence of music itself, gave music universal significance as the embodiment
of the World-Soul. He accomplished this by application of the harmonic,
geometric, and arithmetic progressions of mathematical science; by these
means, he fixed the boundaries of the physical universe in such a way that
they conformed to a (modern) diatonic scale. He began with the two geometric progressions: 1, 2, 4, 8 and 1, 3, 9, 27, each of which has in common the
number 1, the ratio between their terms being 2:1 and 3:1, respectively. By
inserting the harmonic and the arithmetic means between each of the terms
in the two series, Plato completed the full diatonic scale. Expressed in algebraic terms, to find the harmonic mean, b, within the terms a, b, c, the formula is applied:
; for the arithmetic mean:
. See Levin,
Manual, pp. 114–20. Jamie James, The Music of the Spheres, p. 44, has this to
say of Plato’s construction: “The eight pages (in translation) of the Timaeus that
Plato devotes to the creation of the cosmos have generated thousands of pages of
commentary, yet no one has ever quite managed to clarify Plato’s ambiguities
successfully. What the dialogue does communicate, unambiguously, is Pythagoras’
final triumph. The cosmogonic vision of the Timaeus is the mystical Pythagorean
equivalence of music, the cosmos, and mathematics brought out of the esoteric
closet and thrown open for inspection by all thinking persons.” Cf. L. Spitzer,
Classical and Christian Ideas of World Harmony, pp. 10–17.
The diverse features of this conception that were henceforth to influence astronomical thought for centuries converged with reality in the celestial physics
of Johannes Kepler (1571–1630), who could not but stand in awe of his own
discovery (Harmonikēs Mundi, proemium, Book 5, 179; Caspar, p. 289. 13–19):
“At last, I say, I brought to light, and beyond what I could ever hope for,
I discovered the ultimate truth: that the entire nature of harmonic science in all
its magnitude and with all its parts explained by me in my third book is to be
found in the heavenly motions; but not in the way I had supposed – this part
of my discovery being not the least of my joy – but in another utterly different
way, also both most excellent and utterly perfect.”
16
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
in the models provided by geometry. For by assigning to each planet
a path that conformed to its visible course in space, geometry assisted
astronomy to determine whether its hypotheses were consistent with
the observed phenomena. These latter, being points in space – discrete
and enumerative – embroidering the heavens with their uniform, continuous, and regular courses of a certain magnitude, were thereupon
accounted as the visual embodiment of number in motion and governed
therefore by the uniform and immutable laws of mathematics.31
If the harmonious perfection perceived in the motion of the heavenly bodies could be rendered knowable through the mediation of
number, then the motion that is antistrophal to it and productive
of the audible phenomena should be approachable by similar means.
Implicit in this assumption is the notion on which the Pythagoreans
based their theory of sound. This theory held that the actual, physical, and observable motion in air of vibrating bodies – a motion that
produces sound – is subject to the same laws that govern the actual,
physical, and observable motion of the heavenly bodies. For, as had
already been shown by the Pythagoreans, in the absence of this actual
and observable motion, sound could no more be said to exist than
the heavenly bodies could be conceived to pursue their perdurative
courses. This physical motion that produces sound was explained by
them to be caused by a percussion of some sort – the striking of something against the outside air, whether from the vibrations of a plucked
string, or from the infusion of breath into the mouthpiece of a wind
instrument. These percussions, being conducted through the medium
of air, were found to generate all the varieties of sound that the ear can
31
The laws of planetary motion that Kepler discovered are these three: (1) the
planets trace elliptical (not circular) orbits; (2) the focus of each ellipse is
the sun; (3) the squares of the period of revolution of any two planets are in the
same ratio as the cubes of their mean distances from the sun. Kepler says this
of his discovery (Harmonikēs Mundi, Book 5, 202; Caspar, p. 317. 6–10): “So
far, therefore, it has been proved, by means of numbers taken on the one hand
from astronomy, on the other from harmonics, that there obtain between these
twelve terms or motion of the six planets circling the sun up, down, and in
all directions harmonic relationships (proportiones Harmonices), or relationships
extremely close to being harmonic within an imperceptible part of the smallest
consonance.”
All Deep Things Are Song
17
apprehend. As Plato explained it, the faster the vibratory motion, the
higher the pitch produced and, conversely, the slower the motion, the
lower the pitch produced.32
With musical pitch regarded as inseparable from the motion that is
its cause, its identification with speed and so with quantity and number
could be specified. If quantity could be predicated of pitch, and if pitch
could then be represented by number, the differences between all the
high and the low pitches of melody could be systematically formulated
on the logical bases of numbers in their mutual relations. This meant
that the harmonious property underlying all utterance that is recognizably musical could now be rendered knowable through the mediation of
number. On this approach, the musical universe could be contemplated
as the embodiment in sound of numbers in their mutual relations, and
therein subject, like the visible phenomena, to the uniform and immutable laws of mathematics. The assumption of motion as the principle
of audible phenomena, and the adduction of number as the primary
element of musical pitch, thus supplied the Urstoff of the Pythagorean
doctrine of harmonics. But, according to Plato, it took a Creator to
infuse into the universal soul all the attributes of a mathematically true
attunement and thereby to have the universal voice be “propertied with
all the tuned spheres.” Plato called this Creator the Demiurgus (literally, “one who works for the people”) and represented his artistry as that
of a Master-Musician. The affinity between music and mathematics that
prompted Plato’s identification of the World-Soul and music’s harmonically structured foundation has been felt ever since by astronomers,
mathematicians, and philosophers of all epochs. And, like the “floor
of heaven” itself, poetry is “thick inlaid with patines” of its variegated
implications.
By the sheer force of his intellect, Pythagoras had revealed to the
coming ages worlds within worlds of unchanging and harmonious
order, where reason governs everything and nothing can do or suffer
32
In Timaeus 67B–C1, Plato explained that the kind of physical motion produced
in the air by percussion accounts for the differences in sound: “The rapidity
of the motion is what causes highness of pitch. The slower the motion, the
lower the pitch. Motion that is uniform produces a sound that is even and
smooth; the opposite is what causes a sound that is harsh.”
18
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
wrong. It is here that mathematics and philosophy meet, each bound
to the other by the power of harmonia, the attunement of opposing
natures. Had Pythagoras ever committed any of these thoughts to writing, he would quite possibly have expressed himself as Plato did in the
Phaedo, where he has Socrates being advised in a recurring dream to live
a Pythagorean life:33 “Compose and practice music . . . for philosophy is
music in the highest.”
Not surprisingly then, the works of numerous writers on music have
been and are to this day almost completely dominated by the influence of
Pythagorean thought. Indeed, one might say that when it comes to music,
Pythagoras seems always to be presiding over the discussion, dictating the
reasoning, and even reinforcing the musical analyses. Book titles bearing the
Pythagorean imprimatur have continued to appear since Johannes Kepler
first spoke of De harmonikes mundi, this being the fifth book of his classic
work, The Harmony of the World.34 Today, we have such representative works
as Cosmic Music: Musical Keys to the Interpretation of Reality, edited by Joscelyn
Godwin and, by the same author, The Harmony of the Spheres: A Sourcebook of
the Pythagorean Tradition in Music. Similarly titled is The Music of the Spheres:
Music, Science and the Natural Order of the Universe by Jamie James. Other
works that are deeply imbued with Pythagorean thought and philosophy
are The Concept of Music by Robin Maconie; Emblems of Mind: The Inner Life
of Music and Mathematics by Edward Rothstein; and Music, the Brain, and
Ecstasy: How Music Captures Our Imagination by Robert Jourdain.
33
Plato Phaedo 61A2–4. In commenting on this passage, Albert Cook, The Stance of
Plato, p. 1, speaks of Plato as “the Webern and the Beethoven of philosophy, an
essentialist who is at the same time powerfully polyphonic.” To this perception he
adds, “In trying to account for the unified utterance of a whole dialogue of Plato,
and still more of the body of his writings, we have to try to be anthropologists, literary critics, and responsible philosophers all at once, at the risk of putting asunder what it was his unique achievement to put in perilous equipoise together.”
34 On the plan of the Harmonikēs Mundi Libri V, see the analysis of J. V. Field,
Kepler’s Geometrical Cosmology, pp. 96–99. She thus observes (p. 99): “The position of the musical book immediately after the geometrical ones was probably
designed to emphasize that the ‘musical’ ratios, long seen as arithmetical in origin, had now been given a basis in geometry.” As for the title, the form used by
Kepler, Harmonikēs, is a transliteration of the Greek genitive, the nominative of
which is Harmonikē. Cf. Bruce Stephenson, The Music of the Heavens, p. 4, n. 1.
All Deep Things Are Song
19
In Plato’s explanation and development of the Pythagorean doctrine, there stands as a first cause, a Demiurgus or Creator, who alone
knows the secret of universal harmony. This is Number in all its musical manifestations. The notion of number in music and music in number is expressed in the celebrated dictum of J. S. Bach’s contemporary,
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz:35
Musica est exercitium arithmeticae occultum
nescientis se numerare animi.
Music is a hidden exercise in arithmetic of a mind that doesn’t know itself
to be dealing with numbers.
The mind, according to Leibniz, when dealing with music, is unconsciously engaging in some sort of arithmetic operation. And this is evidently true of the listener’s mind as well as that of the composer. The
inference is that when we are presented with music, it is essentially
number to which we are responding. But Schopenhauer, who ranked
music as philosophy in the highest, recast Leibniz’ dictum so as to alter
its meaning at this deepest level:36
Musica est exercitium metaphysices occultum
nescientis se philosophari animi.
Music is a hidden exercise in metaphysics of a mind that does not know
itself to be dealing with philosophy.
In other words, to take Leibniz’ definition of music literally would be
to consider not the innermost, but only the outward or exterior significance of music. As Schopenhauer says:37
Therefore, from our standpoint, where the aesthetic effect is the thing we
have in mind, we must attribute to music a far more serious and profound
significance that refers to the innermost being of the world and of our own
35
This is quoted by Arthur Schopenhauer from Leibniz’ Letters, ep. 154 (Kortholt)
in The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, p. 256, n. 46.
36 Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 264.
37 Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 256.
20
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
self. In this regard, the numerical ratios into which it can be resolved are
related not as the thing signified, but only as the sign.
Schopenhauer was surely of a mind with Bacchius the Elder, that
all but forgotten musical theorist whose words open this essay. For had
Bacchius believed that it is to the numbers ruling musical pitch differences that we unconsciously respond on music’s presentation, he would
have defined music in this way: “It is a conceptual knowledge of number and all that pertains to number.” But Bacchius scrupulously and
deliberately avoided any mention of number in his definition of music.
In fact, number is not mentioned by him even once in the whole course
of his treatise on music. When he did have occasion to use numerical
terms, it was solely for such enumerative purposes as given in these
examples:38
How many species of musical notes are there? Three. How many inflections
of melody do we say there are? Four. How many modulations do we say that
there are? Seven.
The numbers 3, 4, and 7, respectively, as used here by Bacchius,
are not identical with the musical notes, melodic inflections, or the
modulations that they signify. These numbers are merely what each
of these collections (notes, inflections, modulations) have in common
and what distinguishes them from other such collections. The number 7, for example, is what characterizes the collection of modulations
because, according to Bacchius, there are seven distinct modulations in
his (ancient Greek) music.39 In each of these cases, Bacchius has used
38
39
Introduction to the Art of Music, I. 43 ( Jan, 302. 7); I. 45, ( Jan, 302. 16); I. 50
(Jan 304. 6).
Modulation (metabolē) is, and always has been, one of the most important
resources of musical expression. It does for music what metaphor (metaphora)
does for language: it effects a change of profound dimensions. In the one case,
that of language, the change occurs when there is transferred to one word the
sense of another. To take one of Aristotle’s examples in Poetics 21. 1457b25:
“Old age is the evening of life.” In the other case, that of music, the change
occurs when there is transferred to one pitch the function (dynamis) of another.
For example, the note C that has the function of tonic (I) in the key of C
can be made to bear the function of subdominant (IV) in the key of G. The
All Deep Things Are Song
21
numbers to enumerate members of a designated class. But our know
ledge of modulation, to take one of his examples, and what it does in
music or what it means for music cannot be derived from the number 7;
nor, for that matter, can the numbers 3 and 4 enable us to understand
what is meant by species (eidē ) or inflections ( pathē ) of melody. The fact
is that knowledge in regard to all such collections and all else pertaining to the composition of music cannot be gained from numbers. The
reason for this is that number is not the defining property of music.
The virtue of Bacchius’ definition of music – “It is a conceptual
knowledge of melody and all that pertains to melody” – lies in its recognition of melody as the defining property of music – a property by
whose possession music is distinguished from all else in the natural
universe. In his recognition of the status of melody, Bacchius could offer
what Bertrand Russell would regard as a definition by intension, that
is, a definition that specifies a defining property of the thing defined.
Indeed, Russell considered this kind of definition more fundamental
logically than any definitions that enumerate the components or elements of a thing. According to Russell then, definitions of the latter
type, so-called definitions by extension, can always be reduced to definitions by intension. It is for this reason that Russell considered intensional definitions to be the ultimate source of knowledge. Because we
cannot enumerate all fractions, say, or all of any other infinite collections, be they notes, intervals, or numbers, “our knowledge,” Russell
says, “in regard to all such collections can only be derived from a definition by intension.”40
Proceeding logically from his intensional definition of music,
Bacchius thereupon offered a deliberately tautological definition of
40
subject of modulation/metaphor bristles with complexities, but this much can
be said here: metaphor can only work within the framework of a standardized
rule-governed language; modulation, to work at all, requires a standardized
equally-tempered attunement. See below, pp. 323–24. The seven types of
modulation listed by Bacchius are: by system, by genus, by key, by character (ēthos), by rhythm, by rhythmic tempo, by arrangement of the rhythmic
composition. Here, as elsewhere, Bacchius is following a tradition set down
centuries earlier by Aristoxenus. Cf. Solomon (note. 2), 122, n. 2. On modulation, see Barker, II, p. 424.
Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, p. 13.
22
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
elody: “It [melody] is the fall and rise generated by melodious notes.”41
m
Then, after examining in detail the seemingly limitless melodic permutations and combinations yielded by the fall and rise of melodious notes,
Bacchius saw fit to add a second definition of melody, one which conforms
interestingly to what Russell terms “extensional.”42 Bacchius’ definition in
this instance is extensional in that it enumerates the constituents of a class,
the class in this case being that of the melodic elements. Thus Bacchius:43
“What is melody? It is that which is composed of notes and intervals and
units of time.”
As Bacchius seems to have intuited, notes, intervals, and units of
time themselves form an infinite collection of terms and cannot therefore be satisfactorily defined solely by enumeration or, as Russell has
it, by “extension.” Moreover, such collections of notes, intervals, and
units of time, having a given number of terms themselves, presumably form infinite collections. That being so, it may be presumed that
in music it is possible for there to be produced an infinite number of
melodies. Bacchius evidently wished to define melody in such a way
then, that the production of an infinite number of melodies might
not only be thought a possibility, but indeed a probability, given the
infinite number of terms involved in its creation. Therefore, Bacchius
approached music, as he had to, in terms of an infinite number of
melodic elements. At the same time, he had to define such a collection
by intension, that is, by a property common to all its members. This
property is melodiousness (emmelēs). Bacchius is wonderfully clear on
this point:44
41
42
43
44
I. 19 (Jan, 297, 19–20). The technical terms for “rise” and “fall” come from
Aristoxenus’ epitasis (tension) and anesis (resolution) and are defined as such by
Bacchius at I. 45 (Jan, 302. 18–21): “[Anesis] is the motion of melody from the
higher note to the lower.” Epitasis is the motion of melody from the lower note
to the higher.”
Russell (above, note 40), p. 12. As Russell points out (p. 13): “The vital difference between the two [definitions] consists in the fact that there is only one
class having a given set of members, whereas there are always many different
characteristics by which a given class may be defined.”
II. 78 (Jan, 309. 13–14).
II. 69 (Jan, 307. 5–10).
All Deep Things Are Song
23
What sort of notes are melodious? Those which people use when singing and
when they play something on musical instruments. For without this [emmelēs]
being present, it is impossible for any of the musical elements to be defined.
To Bacchius then, music and its defining property – melodiousness –
are for all practical purposes interchangeable. Or, to put it another way,
music in the absence of melodiousness is no longer music. A melodious
sequence, being “that which is composed of notes and intervals and
units of time” (see note 43), is more, therefore, indeed, much more,
than the sum of its parts.
Melody was, accordingly, music’s proper subject matter for Bacchius.
Without attempting to compare melody to anything in the world –
to language, for example, or to mathematics, or to architecture, or to
painting – Bacchius concentrated solely on identifying those melodic
attributes that make music possible. In this effort, his intention was
not merely to show what makes for the nature and differences between
musical notes and intervals and units of time, but, more specifically, to
demonstrate that musical notes, intervals, and units of time are in reality original and immutable qualities of the melodies that exhibit them.
This approach to the question of music’s essential nature stems from the
recognition that, ultimately, music speaks for itself and will not endure
translation into any other medium of expression.45
The question posed by Bacchius – “What is music?” – is, of course, one
that has been asked ever since Homer first set Western civilization into
motion with the quintessential word of music that opens the Iliad: aeide
(“Sing”). It was, in fact, in song that the Homeric bards had already been
keeping civilization alive for many generations in their singing “the deeds
of gods and men.” Indeed, song, as the ancient Greeks had long known, is
something that requires exacting thought, consummate skill, keen perception and, above all, paideia: cultivation, in the highest sense of the word.46
45
See note 9. It is Aristoxenus’ recognition of this fact that makes him so worthy
of modern attention.
46 The Greeks created the ideal of paideia. Indeed, as Russell might have said, paideia is the defining property of Hellenism. Yet the word paideia, like aretē, has
no sufficient equivalent in English. Cf. Werner Jaeger, Paideia, Vol. I, pp. 4ff.
Paideia has to do with the training of man to fulfill the ideal of humanity as
it ought to be. As Jaeger, Paideia, Introduction, p. xxiv says: “It starts from
24
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
By Homer’s time,47 song, accompanied on the phorminx,48 the stringed
instrument of the bards, was a well-evolved art. Phemius, for example, the
bard of the Odyssey, despite his denial of formal training, had to admit that
his repertory of songs was virtually inexhaustible:49 “I am self-taught, and a
god has planted all sorts of songs in my mind.”
Many of Phemius’ songs were the product of his own genius or, as he
put it, were given him by a god. Others of his songs came down to him
from countless generations of singers, and the audiences for whom he
sang were familiar with them all. If one of them made Penelope weep, it
may easily be imagined that the melody sung by Phemius was as much
a cause of her tears as were the words of his song. As Homer describes
the episode:50
Then with tears did she [Penelope] address the bard: ‘Phemius, you know
many other enchantments for mortals – the deeds of men and gods that
singers celebrate; sing one of them as you sit by these men [the suitors of
Penelope] and let them drink their wine in silence; but stop singing this
sorrowful song which wears away my own heart within my breast.
47
48
49
50
the ideal, not from the individual.” As such, it “is the universally valid model
of humanity which all individuals are bound to imitate.” The role played by
music in this enterprise is described by Athenaeus Deipnosophists XIV. 628C:
“Music plays a part in the exercise and the sharpening of the mind; for that
reason, every one of the Greeks and those foreigners whom we happen to know
make use of it.”
Since the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries of our era, Homer’s time and
place in history have been, and probably always will be, a matter of scholarly
debate. Some scholars believe in the multiple authorship of the two epics, the
Iliad and the Odyssey, while others go so far as to deny the existence of Homer
altogether. The view accepted here is that Homer lived and worked at or near
Chios before 800 b.c., that his is one of the greatest minds Greece was able to
produce even before its own history commenced, and that Homer is the single
author of the Iliad and the Odyssey.
According to Martha Maas and Jane McIntosh Snyder, Stringed Instruments of
Ancient Greece, p. 4, phorminx is the Homeric term for lyre, but its linguistic origin remains a mystery. “We are left with the conclusion that the word phorminx
was borrowed by the Greeks from some other, possibly non-Indo-European
language.” Cf. Anderson. Music and Musicians in Ancient Greece, pp. 36–37.
Odyssey 22. 347–48.
Odyssey 1. 336–42.
All Deep Things Are Song
25
These words say much: that Homer must have known as well as any
great composer of lieder has known ever since – a single line of melody
produced by a “clear-toned” voice, like that of Circe (or Dawn Upshaw,
Cecilia Bartoli, or Frederica von Stade), can be as emotionally searing, if
not even more so, than the words of a poem.51 According to Bacchius, it is
in the interior precincts of melody that music finds its best definition.
Unlike Bacchius’ definition of music, which ultimately turns on its
own ground of determination, modern definitions of music are grounded
in the sensibility it induces in human beings. These definitions focus
on how the listener is affected by the music, so that what the listener
feels is transferred to the object itself: music. The subjective significance of this feeling, once transferred to the music that induced it, has
produced many different definitions of music. Of these, the most commonly accepted holds that “Music is the language of feeling.” Because
it is a definition associated directly with the cognitive faculty – the
mind, where music begins – while linked at the same time to human
emotions – where music finds its target – it is accounted by many to be
appropriate at all levels. Thus, for example, the composer and writer on
music Robin Maconie gives it the following endorsement:52
Music is a field of human expression which has successfully resisted analysis in terms of conventional theory. . . . From one vantage point music can
be perceived as operating in the same auditory domain as speech, being
processed by the same sensory mechanisms, capable of arousing a predictable response, and available for inspection in written form. From such a
viewpoint music is therefore arguably language-like.
51
52
The question as to whether the beauty of melody always takes precedence over
the associated text, or whether the words of the text add expressive content
to the music has been debated forever, it seems. See, for example, Wayne D.
Bowman, Philosophical Perspectives on Music, pp. 141–52. On the use of language
to describe music, see Peter Kivy, Music Alone, pp. 97–101. The music most
admired by Plato, for example, has been best described by Sir Walter Scott in
Quentin Durward. Speaking of the Lady with the Lute, Scott wrote: “The words
had neither so much sense, wit, or fancy as to withdraw the attention from the
music, nor the music so much of art as to drown out all feeling of the words.
The one seemed fitted to the other.”
Robin Maconie, The Concept of Music, p. 3.
26
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Deryck Cooke, music critic and musicologist, goes even further: for
him music is not merely language-like; it is in fact a language:53
We may say then that, whatever else the mysterious art known as music may
eventually be found to express, it is primarily a language of the emotions,
through which we directly experience the fundamental urges that move mankind, without the need of falsifying ideas and images – words or pictures.
With that in mind, Cooke levels this rather biting criticism against the
experts who, he believes, should know what music in fact is:54
But we musicians, instead of trying to understand this language, preach
the virtues of refusing to consider it a language at all; when we should be
attempting, as literary critics do, to expound and interpret the great master
pieces of our art for the benefit of humanity at large, we concern ourselves
more and more with parochial affairs – technical analyses and musicological
minutiae – and pride ourselves on our detached, dehumanized approach.
In order “to bring music back from the intellectual-aesthetic limbo in
which it is now lost, and to reclaim it for humanity at large,”55 Cooke
assigned himself the task of “actually deciphering its language.” His
method was “to isolate the various means of expression available to the
composer – the various procedures in the dimension of pitch, time, and
volume – and to discover what emotional effects these procedures can
produce.”56
According to Cooke,57 musical works are built up out of tensions
within the three dimensions of pitch, time, and volume. Tempo, he
says, expresses different levels of animation, volume expresses various
degrees of emphasis given to specific feelings, and intervallic tensions
between pitches – these termed by Aristoxenians like Bacchius, epitasis
53
54
55
56
57
Deryck Cooke, The Language of Music, p. 272. Cooke’s phrase, “falsifying ideas
and images – words or pictures,” is strangely ambiguous here. He apparently
means that words, images, or ideas need not be imported, since they tend to
falsify the emotional content of music.
Cooke, op. cit., Preface, p. x.
Cooke, op. cit., Preface, p. xi.
Cooke, ibid.
Cooke, op. cit., pp. 35ff.
All Deep Things Are Song
27
(rise) and anesis (fall) – have their equivalents of pleasure-pain within
the major-minor modal structures of melodic motifs. Given these three
properties, melodic motifs can, in Cooke’s view, induce in the listener
certain emotional responses that are not only elemental – joy or sorrow –
but are also predictable. These elemental responses are triggered, he
argues, by sixteen basic terms in music’s “vocabulary” to each of which
he assigns an objective utility within their respective contexts. Thus,
he says, the ascending major triad expresses an assertive emotion of joy,
the ascending minor triad, an assertion of sorrow: a descending major
sequence from dominant to tonic conveys relief, consolation, and reassurance; a descending minor sequence from dominant to tonic expresses
an acceptance of, or yielding to, grief or to the despair connected with
death. A rise from the lower dominant over the tonic to the minor
third, followed by a resolution to the tonic “conveys the feeling of a
passionate outburst of painful emotions”; major sevenths are generally
“optimistic” intervals, while minor sixths are laden with anguish.
Assuming that specific meanings inhere in such melodic elements
as major and minor intervals and other such distributions, Cooke proceeds to adduce from a wide range of musical literature numerous
examples of these types of melodic sequences in action. The climax of
Beethoven’s Leonore Overture No. 3 denotes, he says, excited affirmation
in an outgoing feeling of pleasure; while the closing pages of Mahler’s
First Symphony arouse an incoming feeling of pleasure.58 An outgoing
feeling of pain is elicited, he says, by “O heilige Schmach” from Act 2
of The Valkyrie, whereas an incoming feeling of pain is conveyed in the
opening of the finale of Tschaikovsky’s Pathétique Symphony. The first
theme of the third movement of Brahms’ First Piano Concerto ascends
with the notes 5 – 1 – 2 – 3 – 5 – 1 (which can be better heard as A1 –
D – E – F – A – D1) and conveys courage and heroism, the minor phrase
5 – 1 – 3 awakening this distinctive reaction in the listener. To cite one
more example, the progression 1 – 2 – 3 – 2 – 1 in the minor mode is
used, Cooke claims, to express gloom, doom, and a sense of inescapable
fear, especially when it is repeated over and over. These and many more
58
Cooke, op. cit, pp. 104–5 explains “outgoing” and “incoming” as follows:
“The expressive quality of rising pitch is above all an ‘outgoing’ of emotion.
The expressive quality of falling pitch is of an ‘incoming’ of emotion.”
28
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
examples allow Cooke to affirm such confidence in his analytic method
that he can say:59
Such [examples show] clearly that music has its own method of coherent
emotional expression, quite different from that of speech-language. This
method is nothing more mysterious than the presentation of some general
but clearly-defined attitude towards existence by the disposition of various
terms of emotional expression in a significant order.
Cooke’s attempt to translate subjective feelings into objective form,
indeed, to rationalize what is the ecstatic experience of music, raises an
age-old problem: Is there justification for the belief that any number of
people can hear the same melodies and react to them in the same way?
If there is justification in ascribing the same responses from different
listeners to any given melody, then Cooke must be concerned, as indeed
he is, with those features that those melodies have in common for all
listeners. To be sure, Cooke concedes that one listener’s reaction to a
melody may differ greatly from that of another, and he even quotes the
composer Paul Hindemith to that effect:60
One given piece of music may cause remarkably diverse reactions in different listeners. As an illustration of this statement, I like to mention the second movement of Beethoven’s Seventh Symphony, which I have found leads
some people into a pseudo feeling of profound melancholy, while another
group takes it for a kind of scurrilous scherzo, and a third for a subdued
kind of pastorale. Each group is justified in judging as it does.
A clear and unambiguous observation, this, but for Cooke, how
utterly wrong! As he sees it, neither Hindemith, nor anyone else in his
right musical mind, is entitled to this conclusion, namely, that each listener is justified in judging as he does. In fact, Cooke’s whole book may
be read as an attempt to refute Hindemith on this critical point. The
conclusion to which all his arguments lead is this: listeners’ reactions to
59
60
Cooke, op. cit., p. 212. However, cf. Jourdain, Music, the Brain, and Ecstasy,
p. 60; “When it comes to the production of melodies, we are still at the
hunting-and-gathering stage.”
Cooke, op. cit., p. 21.
All Deep Things Are Song
29
music differ in direct proportion to their own understanding of music
and their own capacity to feel music’s emotional content. As he says:61
The fact is that people can only react to emotions expressed in a work of art
according to their own capacity to feel those emotions.
He therefore asks:62
Could it not be that some listeners are incapable of understanding the feeling of music properly?
His answer is unequivocally, “Yes”:63
The answer is, of course, yes; and this explains why “tests,” in which the
reactions of a random collection of individuals are classified and analyzed,
prove nothing. Sympathetic understanding is a prerequisite.
In the end, Cooke has to dismiss as “plainly unmusical” all those
people who would react to a given piece of music in ways that are at
odds with his own feelings:64
Such people, whom one knows to exist, are just plainly unmusical: suppose
that such a listener’s “memory-image” has no connection with the emotions
expressed by the music at all. If someone were to declare the Eroica Funeral
March to be a sanguine piece, we should unhesitatingly accuse him of being
emotionally undeveloped.
As Cooke has it then, those listeners who could even think of the
Eroica Funeral March as sanguine or could judge the second movement
of Beethoven’s Seventh Symphony to be a “scurrilous scherzo” must be
deemed totally unqualified to offer any opinion at all on any piece of
music presented to them:65
61
62
63
64
65
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid., n. 2
Cooke, op. cit., p. 22.
Cooke, op. cit., p. 23.
30
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
One is bound to regard anyone who reacts in this way as either superficial,
unmusical, or unsympathetic to Beethoven.
At issue is this: Are there, in fact, natural indications in melodic
utterances, or in music generally, that evoke or stimulate the same
emotions in the same way in all possible human minds? Cooke would
(and, in effect, does) answer “Yes.” Hindemith’s answer, on the other
hand, is an emphatic “No.” In truth, however, even if each could find
no flaw in the other’s argument or reasoning, neither would ever succeed in winning over the other to his own point of view. For the
dispute in which they are engaged has been going on for as long as
music has existed; it is a dispute in which only the more obstinate
participant can presume to have won. When a man of Cooke’s critical judgment undertakes to refute the conclusions of composers like
Hindemith, he does so in the belief that there is in the human mind
an order of absolute truth – truth that is wholly distinct from metaphysical conjectures. Indeed, for Cooke, music presents a case in which
exact and precise truth can actually be arrived at. Moreover, his critical attitude toward music is wholly unaffected by the possibility that
an exact truth may not be identical with its perceived object; that the
known object – music – and the mind’s knowledge of it may be two
very different realities.
If Cooke tends to be dogmatic in his assertion that there are between
musical truths and the knowing mind a perfect parity, Hindemith is
no less so in his negation of any such possibility. Hindemith, as it happens, receives strong approbation on this point from the formidable Igor
Stravinsky:66
66
Igor Stravinsky, An Autobiography, p. 83. Stravinsky’s position is an example of
musical formalism at its most rigid. As Bowman (n. 51), p. 193, points out,
“musical formalism represents a beneficial reaction against the metaphysical
excesses of idealistic theory. . . . [but] Its interest in system and structure may
devalue personal expression and activity. . . . Its interest in ‘objectivity’ may
devalue parameters and experiences that tend to be more personal and subjective.” On p. 94, Bowman cites Stravinsky’s pronouncement as an example
of the formalist’s argument that “states its positive thesis in negative terms.”
Cooke’s thesis is an example of a formalistic approach stated in positive terms,
but Bowman does not include it in his discussion.
All Deep Things Are Song
31
I consider that music, by its very nature, is essentially powerless to express
anything at all, whether a feeling, an attitude of mind, a psychological
mood, a phenomenon of nature, etc. . . . Expression has never been an inherent property of music. That is by no means the purpose of its existence. If,
as is nearly always the case, music appears to express something, this is only
an illusion and not a reality. It is simply an additional attribute which, by
tacit and inveterate agreement, we have lent it, thrust upon it, as a label,
a convention – in short, an aspect which, unconsciously or by force of habit,
we have often come to confuse with its essential being.
The most significant thing in Stravinsky’s statement is his refusal to say
what music’s essential being is. This is not mere musical affectation on his
part; it indicates, rather, an abiding philosophical position: that we cannot, or must not, seek to know music’s essence as we do other things and
their laws. All we can do in the face of music is to cast upon it figurative
or metaphoric language, and not, as in Cooke’s attempt, the language of
literal fact and denotation. Thus, whereas Cooke was intent on assigning
aesthetic meanings to specific melodic figures, Hindemith and Stravinsky
were bent on divesting music of any sort of representational capacity. In
this respect, Stravinsky and Hindemith (as well as most musicians) share
the position of Bacchius, and the Aristoxenian school for which he was a
keen spokesman. This position derives from the fact that music operates
between the hearing ear (akoz) and the thing heard (akoumenon), without
the intervention or mediation of any other element, any tertium quid, as it
were. It is this fact of sensation that sets music apart from the visual arts,
for example. For the eye, as Plato points out, in order to see the visual
object in all its colors and forms must have a tertium quid: light:67
But there is this need in the case of sight and its objects. You may have the
power of vision in your eyes and try to use it, and colour may be there in the
objects; but sight will see nothing and the colours will remain invisible in
the absence of a third thing peculiarly constituted to serve this purpose.
In taking the position that music does not denote feelings, Hindemith
and Stravinsky were expressing the view that music, in its uttermost
67
Plato Republic 507D11–14 (Cornford).
32
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
depths, cannot be put into thoughts, cannot be cast into words, and
cannot be portrayed in images. For music, as musicians think of it,
comprehends no duality; it is not a copy of anything in the sensible universe. As Wittgenstein said in his capacity of a musician, music is one
with itself; it is complete in itself; it satisfies itself (see note 5). On these
grounds, music can be placed on the same footing and accepted as parallel with that which Plato called Idea.68 On this construal, music exists
beyond the reach of science and beyond the power of representation. It
is not a copy of the Platonic idea, but rather, that of the musician’s own
will, the objectification of which is the music itself. If music is in this
sense a copy only of itself, then it must exist outside the world of phenomena and out of time, annulling both but penetrating to the innermost nature of each with a distinctness surpassing that of perception
itself. For all these reasons, Schopenhauer set music apart and above all
the other arts, ranking it with the Platonic Ideas, as an objectification
of the will:69
Hence all of them [the other arts] objectify the will only indirectly, in other
words, by means of the Ideas. As our world is nothing but the phenomena
or appearance of the Ideas in plurality through entrance into the principium
individuationis (the form of knowledge possible to the individual as such),
music, since it passes over Ideas, is also quite independent of the phenomenal world, positively ignores it, and, to a certain extent, could still exist
even if there were no world at all, which cannot be said of the other arts.
Thus music is as immediate an objectification and copy of the whole will as
the world itself is, indeed as the ideas are, the multiplied phenomenon of
which constitutes the world of individual things. Therefore music is by no
68
69
See note 3 on Bacchius’ application of the term eidēsis to melody.
Schopenhauer (note 35), p. 257. Commenting on Schopenhauer’s insight,
Bowman (note 51), p. 72, has this to add: “What art does, in Schopenhauer’s
view, is give us insights into the nature of the phenomenal world. Music,
however, is unlike the other arts. It is a copy of the Will itself, a face-to-face
encounter with the innermost nature of existence. Music thus has the power
to communicate the incommunicable, to penetrate the rational veil of representation and appearances – to give us insight into truths more profound than
reason can ever grasp.”
All Deep Things Are Song
33
means like the other arts, namely a copy of the Ideas, but a copy of the will
itself, the objectivity of which are the Ideas.
It was for such reasons that Felix Mendelssohn left in a letter this celebrated comment for us to ponder:70
People often complain that music is too ambiguous, that what they should
be thinking as they hear it is unclear, whereas everyone understands words.
With me it is exactly the reverse, and not only with regard to an entire
speech, but also with individual words. These, too, seem to me so ambiguous, so vague, so easily misunderstood in comparison to genuine music,
which fills the soul with a thousand things better than words. The thoughts
which are expressed to me by music that I love are not too indefinite to be
put into words, but on the contrary, too definite.
Music thus reveals itself literally in itself, not as another object of
sense which it resembles. It is not a melody that one hears, for example,
as that which opens the second movement of Brahms’ Double Concerto,
Op. 102; what one hears is the melody that opens the second movement. Because such aesthetic considerations as these were self-evident
to experts like Hindemith and Stravinsky, they evinced frustration (as
exampled above) and signs of exasperation at having to speak about
music as though it needed any explanation at all. If the tone of their
words is acerbic, it is no less so than that of Philodemus of Gadara
70
This statement comes from a letter of 1842 written by Mendelssohn in reply
to Marc-André Souchay, who had asked Mendelssohn the meaning of certain
of his Songs Without Words. See Composers on Music. ed. Sam Morgenstern,
pp. 139–40. It is appropriately cited by Roger Scruton, The Aesthetics of
Music, p. 165, in connection with the assertion of the Viennese Critic, Eduard
Hanslick in his Vom Musikalisch-Schönen (On the Musically Beautiful) that music
cannot express any emotions at all. Cf. the statement to the same effect by
Stravinsky (see note 66). In urging this opinion, Hanslick managed to set in
motion 150 years of theoretical objections and counterobjections. As Bowman
(note 51), p. 141 explains in behalf of Hanslick: “Although musical experience
may of course be feelingful, such feeling is neither the source of musical beauty,
nor is it music’s content.”
34
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
(first century b.c.),71 but for an altogether different reason: music had
no “essential being” for Philodemus. As he argued, if music had any
function at all, it was strictly for amusement: its business was solely
to titillate the ear, without ever engaging the mind. That being the
case, Philodemus considered music to be an irrational (alogos) kind of
art without any intellectual content. Thus, the moment he began to
consider the question of objective meaning in music, such as Cooke
claimed to decipher (see note 57), he was able to settle the case once
and for all, and he made a thorough job of it. With two axioms in place,
he disposed of the question altogether. His first axiom was: no two (or
more) people will be moved in the same way by the same composition;
his second axiom: the expressive content of music is an illusion of the
mind, and nothing more.
71
Philodemus, a poet and philosopher living during the time of Cicero (106–43
b.c.), is noted for his criticisms of the theory of musical ethos and its educational value that was first expounded by the teacher of Pericles, Damon (fifth
century b.c.) and closely adhered to by Plato in the Republic (398E–399C4).
This Damonian theory, which Plato so vigorously promulgated, held that music
has intrinsic properties to affect the listener for good or ill. The most influential work on this whole subject continues to be that of H. Abert, Die Lehre vom
Ethos in der griechischen Musik (on Philodemus, see pp. 27–37). Disputing this
Damonian theory, Philodemus argued, often with excessive vituperation, that
melody has no independent meaning at all. His arguments to this effect are
examined by L. P. Wilkinson, “Philodemus on Ethos in Music,” CQ 32 (1938).
174–81. Cf. Bowman (note 51), pp. 138–39. The range of Philodemus’ writings, which now are largely lost, was extensive: rhetoric, aesthetics, logic, ethics,
and theology. Through his writings, he influenced the most learned men of his
day. Several charred rolls of papyri were discovered in the eighteenth century at
Herculaneum among the ruins of what had been an elegant villa belonging to
Philodemus’ friend, Piso Caesonius. Among them was Philodemus’ treatise On
Music in four volumes, of which only fragments of Books I and II remain and
some large sections of Book III and almost all of Book IV. The text is provided
by Johannes Kemke, Philodemi de musica librorum quae exstant (Leipzig, 1884).
On the numerous studies on Philodemus, see Warren D. Anderson, Ethos and
Education in Greek Music, p. 278, n. 13. These studies have been importantly
supplemented by Annemarie Jeanette Neubecker, Die Bewertung der Musik bei
Stoikern und Epicureern and, by the same author, Philodemus’ text and German
translation and commentary in Philodemus, über die Musik IV Buch. His work on
music has not as yet been translated into English.
All Deep Things Are Song
35
Philodemus thus ridicules the whole idea that music can affect the
listener for good or ill, and he does so on grounds that are not unlike the
views expressed (see note 54):72
. . . not all people will be moved in the same way by the same melody, any
more than a melody can make a soul gentle that is moved by frenzy and
set it at rest; nor can a melody alter or turn the soul from one passion to
another, or augment or diminish its natural disposition.
Speaking now as if he were a Stravinsky, Philodemus has this to say
about melody:73
Some [like Diogenes] allege that one type of melody is stately, noble, sincere, and pure; while another kind is unmanly, vulgar, and illiberal; others
term one kind of melody austere and imperious, but another kind gentle
and persuasive. Both parties impute to melody things that do not inhere
in it at all.
Then, as if in direct response to Cooke who, it will be remembered,
urged musicians to treat music not only as a language, but also to work
at deciphering its (for him) explicit meaning and content, Philodemus
impugns any such enterprise on the following grounds:74
72
73
74
De musica I. col. IX. 65, frag. 3 (Kemke, 12. 4–14). Commenting on statements such as this by Philodemus, Wilkinson (note 71), 174, says: “As is well
established, Philodemus was not an original thinker, though he has a tone in
controversy which is all his own. He may be relying here on Epicurus’ lost
work [On music, for which see Diogenes Laertius X, 28]; very probably also on
his master, Zeno of Sidon.”
De musica IV, col. II (Kemke, 64. 19–30). As Wilkinson points out (ibid.): “His
[sc. Philodemus’] chief butt, the Stoic Diogenes of Seleucia, lived a century
before him.”
De musica IV, col. II (Kemke, 64.2–65. 16). Abert (note 71) p. 28, observes of
Philodemus’ tone: “We have a polemic before us, which is distinguished not by
a systematic structure and concise composition of thoughts, but by the acerbity
of his manner and, in part, by a plainly vulgar invective. It pleases the author
to treat his opponents either in sympathetic tones as comic fools or as plainly
insane.”
36
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
And, accordingly, the musician who is seeking after the kind of understanding by which he will be able to distinguish exactly what sorts of perceptions
are involved, is seeking after an exact knowledge of things that have no
reality; and what he teaches on this subject is vacuous; since no melody, qua
melody, which is irrational (alogon), arouses the soul from a state of immobility and stillness and leads it towards its own characteristically natural
state, any more than melody calms and sets at rest to its former state a soul
that is driven to frenzy.
In making the point that meaning in music is dependent ultimately
on the listener’s own contributed feelings, Hindemith, it must be
admitted, sounds alarmingly like Philodemus. Here is Hindemith:75
If music did not instigate us to supply memories out of our own mental
storage rooms, it would remain meaningless; it would merely have a certain
tickling effect on our ears. . . . If music we hear is of a certain kind that does
not easily lend itself or does not lend itself at all to this connection, we still
do our best to find in our memory some feeling that would correspond with
the audible impressions we have.
Writing as though he had consulted with Hindemith just yesterday,
Philodemus counters with an even sharper distinction between what
the ear perceives and what the listener makes of this common aural
experience:76
75
76
See Morgenstern (note 70), p. 482.
De musica IV, col. IB (Kemke, 63, 44–64, 3). This is all part of Philodemus’
polemic against the view held by Plato that music can affect the listener for
good or ill. As Neubecker observes in her commentary on this passage in
Philodemus, über die Musik, p. 127, while Philodemus will allow that “in the
general province of sense-perception, occasionally various predispositions can
exert their influence; but in the case of hearing, this holds true: since all people under various predispositions, make the same aural observations, they all
feel the same sensations of pleasure or displeasure (Philodemus of course offers
no reason for taking these assertions as self-evident); all dissimilar judgments
of individual tonal genre, rhythms or melodies depend solely, according to
Philodemus, on accustomed beliefs.” Bowman (note 51), p. 138 says appropriately: “Epicureans tend to equate perception with sensation, a belief that made
them rather dubious about music’s potential cognitive or moral significance.”
All Deep Things Are Song
37
While people who are similarly endowed in their power of perception agree
not in the fact that a certain object is poor, but arrive at the same judgment if the question arises as to whether that object gives them dissatisfaction or pleasure. Indeed, given these matters, it is possible that our
perceptions correspond to certain variations in our predispositions; but, on
the whole, when it comes to our sense of hearing, there is no difference
between us. On the contrary, all ears get the same impression from the same
melodies, and they derive virtually the same pleasures from them, so that
even when the question concerns the Enharmonic and the Chromatic [genera], the difference between them is not perceived on the basis of aesthetic
perception – which is irrational – but on the basis of aural opinions.
To Philodemus, who offered even fewer concessions than did
Hindemith, the sense of hearing is itself an act of judgment: noting by
ear the differences between the Enharmonic and Chromatic genera, for
example.77 As Philodemus saw it, the ears of all listeners transmit the
same information. That being so, no disagreement should arise among
any two or more people as to the characteristic features of Enharmonic
or Chromatic melodies. Aesthetic feeling, however, because it is in
Philodemus’ estimation irrational, cannot come into play in this kind
of discrimination; it is the ear alone which records melodic information,
and it is the ear alone which derives pleasure from, or as Hindemith has
it, is “tickled” by certain melodic proceedings. But, even as Philodemus
stipulated earlier (see note 72), once these melodic proceedings, or configurations, occur in a living musical context, they will affect no two
people in the same way. In sum then, for Philodemus (and apparently
to some extent for Stravinsky and Hindemith also) there is not any
objective property in music that guarantees the validity and pleasure of
the aesthetic experience; rather, the nature of the aesthetic experience
is presupposed in the subjective stance of the listener. If, therefore, the
supposed character of a major third (joy) or a minor third (sorrow), for
77
The three genera of ancient Greek music expressed in alphabetic notation are:
Diatonic: E F G A; Chromatic: E F Gb A; Enharmonic (+ = quarter-tone): E E+
F A. These sequences can be transposed into any pitch range (topos) whatever,
without alteration of their generic form, e.g.: Diatonic: A B♭ C D; Chromatic:
A B♭ C♭ D; Enharmonic: A A+ B♭ D.
38
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
example,78 is wholly and solely a product of our subjective state, there
can be nothing that answers to it in the nature of melodies themselves;
consequently, to prosecute Philodemus’ argument to its conclusion, our
knowledge of melodies is without an object. This means that items like
major and minor thirds must be taken as mere acoustical data. Whether
they be implicated in a melodic context or abstracted for theoretical
or acoustical study, they can have no meaning or emotional content in
themselves, no more, certainly, than that of a single note or an isolated
sound. Thus, music, even when it exhibited laws such as those defining the Enharmonic or the Chromatic genera (with their characteristic major and minor thirds, respectively), constituted for Philodemus
a domain whose ordinances are not inscribed in the essence of real or
actual things. On his conception, music was a world without intrinsic necessity or intelligibility. His final conclusion had therefore to be:
music is a subject unfit for rational knowledge.
Philodemus’ observations were not a condemnation; they reflect,
rather, a critic’s lack of interest in the effect of music, especially if it had
for him no apparent didactic purpose. For Philodemus and others like
him, music was a kind of learning that cannot be readily grasped by the
intellect and, on that basis, is ipso facto inferior to purely intellectual
pursuits. Its deficiency must therefore consist in the fact that it is a nonscientific mode of discourse, for no object of musical representation can
be an object of knowledge in the strict sense of the word. If, therefore,
one were to ascribe beauty to the major third, for example, Philodemus
would regard this not as a cognitive judgment, but simply an opinion
(doxa). And this, he argues, is not a logical or rational determination, but
78
Thus Cooke (note 53), p. 55, on the major third: “It would seem, then, that
our major third has established itself naturally as an expression of pleasure
or happiness.” And on the minor third, he says (p. 57): “Being lower than
the major third, it has a ‘depressed’ sound, and the fact that it does not form
part of the basic harmonic series makes it an ‘unnatural depression’ of the
‘naturally happy’ state of things (according to Western ideas). Interestingly,
it is the Enharmonic Genus (note 77) in which prominence is granted to the
major third (or ditone) that Aristoxenus considered kallistē (most beautiful).
See his Harmonic Elements (hereafter, Harm. El.) I. 23 (Da Rios, 29. 14–16).
Cf. Barker, II, p. 141, n. 89.
All Deep Things Are Song
39
an irrationally based aesthetic opinion, signifying that its determining
ground cannot be other than subjective.79
By contrast, in a theory that gives precedence to the intellect, as is
the case with Cooke, it is clearly the objective property of a beautiful
construct like the major third, for example, that makes for its peculiar
power. This property is actualized in melody only. It has nothing to do
with sensuous responses to the beauties of nature, say, or to the ecstasy
of love, or to the pain of grief. Indeed, as anyone listening to Beethoven’s
Ode to Joy from the Choral Symphony (itself an ode to the major third),
can testify, this is a property that denotes an intellectual type of cognition, one which produces a powerfully disinterested type of pleasure.
It is a state of pleasure that demands much more than a sensible intuition
of the melodic property in question, however; it is one that calls instead
for an aesthetic knowledge that is no less complex than pure intellectual
knowledge. If this type of knowledge is therefore on a par with intellectual knowledge, as theorists like Bacchius believed, it must be because
it has an object that is identical with that of intellectual knowledge,
namely, the substantial reality of something that is animated by its own
perfection. This is the perfection or fulfillment – what Aristotle termed
entelecheia and Wittgenstein called abgeschlossen – which guarantees the
total completion of what had hitherto existed only potentially in the
79
As Philodemus argues throughout his polemic, the only conveyor of rational
thought is language. Thus Abert (note 71), p. 28: “The basic elements of music,
Rhythm and Melody, are, as he [sc. Philodemus] says, purely of an external, formal nature, and consequently, in and of themselves indifferent throughout. But
since the influence of one psyche on another is possible only through the spoken word as the conveyor of rational thought, it follows that music can never
be capable of that.” That being the case, music, in Philodemus’ view, while a
source of pleasure, has as little to do with the human psyche as the art of cooking. Cf. Wilkinson (note 71), 179: “The pleasure is [only of the ear], a direct
titillation of the ear in which the mind has no share, analogous to the taste of
pleasant food and drink.” Philodemus’ most extreme positions on music were
adopted and amplified by the Skeptic, Sextus Empiricus (c. 200 a.d.), who
argued that the only true existent things are feelings. He says, therefore, in his
Against the Musicians that sound, not being a feeling, but only productive of
feeling, is not an existent thing. For additional discussion, see Bowman (n. 51),
pp. 139–40; Barker, I, p. 462, n. 19.
40
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
mind of the composer. Bacchius identifies this suprasensible reality as
melody, the “characteristic property of music.”80
The question is, if, as Bacchius and Wittgenstein seemed to believe,
the subject matter of music – the direct object of a musically aesthetic
knowledge – is not in any sense factual, how can music be called a
language?81 Cooke would undoubtedly have objected strenuously to
such a question. Indeed, as he insisted, how can music not be thought of
as a language? Seen from Cooke’s point of view, music is not the same
as sound; but it communicates something unmistakeably real through
sound. And if it makes sense, music is felt to have meaning.82 Given
these types of judgments, music seems to specify itself according to a
certain system or logical principle analogous to that of language. For
language, like music, is not the same as sound itself; yet it, too, communicates something unmistakably real through sound. And if it makes
sense, language is certainly felt to have meaning. Above all, music and
language, it is universally agreed, both originate in the human mind.
Therefore, both can legitimately be held to belong to the faculty of
knowledge. Moreover, both bear witness to an immediate interaction of
80
81
82
The only true knowledge of music must therefore be of its eidē, the Forms of
melody, and so the cause of musical epistēmē or knowledge.
Roger Scruton (n. 70), p. 143, has stated the case in this way: “Aesthetic
meaning is real but ineffable. To attempt to make it effable, is to reduce expression to representation, and therefore to lose sight of the essence of art.” As for
music being a form of language, he has this to say (p. 172): “It is doubtful
that music conveys information as language does; but it shares with language
another and equally important feature – the fact of inhabiting the human face
and voice. We hear music as we hear the voice: it is the very soul of another, a
‘coming forth’ of the hidden individual.”
Bowman (n. 51), p. 168 says on this point: “Absolute expressionism’s critical problem is to explain how sound-patterns with no fixed reference achieve
‘meaning’ and become experienced as feeling. Clearly, not all felt response is
musically relevant: a given musical event cannot implicate just any meaning or
feeling.” Like Cooke, Bowman believes, as he goes on to say: “Meanings that
are genuinely musical are the kind found in musically conversant listeners,
people who are fluent in the given style and whose feelings arise directly and
exclusively from the perception of events and processes objectively ‘there,’ in
the music. But how precisely does this happen?”
All Deep Things Are Song
41
this faculty with human feelings of pleasure and delight or, as the case
may be, with displeasure, and even abhorrence.
All things considered, however, it is a curious fact that, as comparisons
between music and language grow more sophisticated, their claims to
the power of proving facts about music in particular seem to diminish proportionately. Cooke was not hampered in the slightest by this
paradox; on the contrary, once he delineated his sixteen general terms of
music’s language, he considered himself eminently justified in inferring
from them the emotional meaning of a particular piece of music. As he
saw it, the fundamental character or, as the ancients termed it, the ethos
of a particular composition must inhere in the basic laws of musical
expression.83 After working through whole series of such laws, Cooke
arrived at last at results which he felt could be utilized to predict what
it is that music is meant to say:84
Perhaps one day, after intensive research into the various aspects of the art –
acoustical, physiological, psychological, and simply musical – it may be
possible, by correlating many findings, to discover exactly what it is that
music expresses, and exactly how it expresses it; but if the attempt is made,
it will have to be guided by the most meticulous regard for absolute truth,
especially in the psychological field, where the final answer is likely to be
found.
In laying down this challenge, Cooke was in quest of a logic whose
common acceptance by musicians would bring forth a new science, one
that would be an objective representation of what the world of music
really is. The cognitive psychologist, John A. Sloboda, rose to Cooke’s
83
84
In his identification of tone-color, pitch-function, intervallic tensions, and other
such elements as “characterizing agents,” Cooke (n. 53), pp. 102ff. moved from
a strictly musical aesthetic into the ancient realm of musical ethos, an expression
for which no modern language possesses an adequate counterpart. For musical
ethos had to do not solely with musical beauty, but much more so with musical
goodness. Its main axiom is: every melody has a certain ethos that is able not
only to represent the movements of the soul, but also to change these movements by being well-ordered (or the opposite). See Plato Republic 401D5-E.
As Cooke puts it (p. 212): “And musical form is simply the means of achieving that
order.”
Cooke (n. 53), p. 273.
42
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
challenge. In his book, The Musical Mind: The Cognitive Psychology of
Music, Sloboda assumed the heavy task of giving a cognitive demonstration of music’s relation to language. Although he may not have found
the final answer that Cooke had sought, he accomplished something
that is in itself a sufficient answer to the question: Is music in fact a
language? For Sloboda, by examining those properties that are common to both music and language, was able, through a fine process of
elimination, to show why analogies between music and language must
ultimately fall apart. He begins by saying:85
My view is that the linguistic analogy in music deserves serious attention;
although I would make three qualifying remarks. Firstly, it would be foolish to claim that music is simply another natural language. There are many
fundamental differences which cannot be overlooked, the most obvious
being that we use language to make assertions or ask questions about the
real world and the objects and relationships in it. If music has any subject
matter at all, then it is certainly not the same as that of normal language.
Secondly, this analogy can clearly be exploited in metaphorical ways, of
which scientists are right to be wary (e.g. ‘music is the language of the emotions’). However, this does not exclude the possibility of a more rigorous
use of the analogy. Indeed, it is arguable that the most productive scientific
analogies are those which fire the imagination as much as they fuel empirical and theoretical endeavors.
According to Sloboda, it is Cooke’s empirical endeavor that best
deals with the question: What is it in music, apart from its ability to
mimic sounds like bird-calls, and so on, that makes it have meaning for
us? He thus recognizes Cooke’s contribution:86
One of the most popular suggestions is that musical sequences somehow
denote, or stand for, certain emotional states. Deryck Cooke (1959) has presented one of the most fully worked out versions of this thesis. . . . I believe
that Cooke has identified a real and important component of musical meaning with his melodic analyses.
85
86
John A. Sloboda, The Musical Mind, p. 12.
Sloboda (n. 85), pp. 60–61.
All Deep Things Are Song
43
Yet, Cooke’s thesis does have its flaws, and Sloboda was not slow in
pointing them out. To begin with, Cooke can all too easily be charged
with selecting those motifs that would best support his theory. More to
the point, his pairing of certain motifs with particular emotions cannot be supported by empirical investigations.87 In addition, Cooke all
too often relies so heavily on the words to which a melody is set that
his own thesis is undermined by his attempt to correlate the two: the
melody and the words that the melody ought to mean.88
The analogies between music and language that merit our most
serious attention are those which focus upon the universal features of
each, features that display something fundamental about man’s intelligence. As Sloboda sees it, it was Noam Chomsky who, in discovering the supreme intelligibility buried within the manifold processes
of language, not only founded the field: the cognitive psychology of
language, but also prompted the formation of a new discipline: psycholinguistics.89 One of the main tenets of Chomsky’s theory is that all natural languages have, at the deepest level, the same structure, and that
this structure reveals something universal about human intelligence.
Sloboda thereupon calls our attention to a striking similarity between
Chomsky’s revelation about language and that of Heinrich Schenker
(1868–1935) about music. For Schenker claimed that all musical masterpieces have, at the deepest level, the same type of structure – a triadic Ursatz – and that this structure reveals something universal about
man’s musical intuition. In Sloboda’s words:90
87
88
89
90
Sloboda (note 85), pp. 62–63.
Thus Scruton (note 70), p. 204: “Cooke’s interest is aroused primarily by wordsettings, since these seem to him to settle unambiguously the question of what
the music ought to mean. And if the setting is successful, it really does mean
what it ought. Cooke’s examples are therefore of striking and powerful works,
in which a verbal message is conveyed with maximum musical force. This
might lead the reader to be sceptical of the claim that Cooke has isolated a genuine vocabulary: a set of phrases and gestures which have a standard meaning
for those who are competent to deploy them, regardless of any accompanying
text.”
Sloboda (note 85), pp. 11ff.
Sloboda (note 85), p. 12.
44
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
There are some striking parallels between Schenker’s views on music and
Chomsky’s on language. For instance, Schenker would wish to claim that, at
a deep level, all good musical compositions have the same type of structure,
and that this structure reveals to us something about the nature of musical
intuition. There is no evidence to suggest that Chomsky knew of Schenker’s
work at the time of formulating his theories of language. It appears, therefore, that similar ways of viewing language and music arose quite independently in two creative intellects steeped in their own subject matter.
The parallels that Sloboda finds between Schenker’s approach to
music and that of Chomsky to language are indeed striking; but even
more striking and, indeed, more revelatory are the differences between
them that emerge from Sloboda’s comparisons. These differences arise
not so much from the ways in which these two creative intellects framed
their respective theories as they do from the different orders of truth
by which the two theories are dictated. What Sloboda’s comparisons
end up showing all too clearly is that music and language are by nature
two distinctly different realities, each one in no sense a plurality of
many unrelated things, but each a true universality of many related
things. As Sloboda explains, on Chomsky’s approach the deep structures
that lie beneath the surface of a sentence can, by the application of certain rules of transformation, actually generate new sentences or surface
structures that bear the same meaning as that embedded in the deep
structures. Chomsky’s method is in this sense a genuinely generative
one. It exposes for talking human beings the most fundamental and
universal of human sciences: grammar.
Schenker, by contrast, closely following the clues given him by
his musical instincts, burrowed step by analytical step, like a musical archaeologist, deep below the surface of melodies down into their
tonal bedrock. There he discovered the primal tonal repositories, the
harmonic armatures, the deep structures that underlie all good melodies. These deep structures are what remain after a successive process
of reductions through middleground structures lays bare the Ursatz.
The original melody is now scrubbed bare, as it were, of all its surface
features. From what remains of the melody – its tonal bedrock – the ear
can be expected to acquire sufficient tonal consciousness to find its way
through the complexities of all the surface structures by which melodies
All Deep Things Are Song
45
explain themselves. It is at this point that Chomsky’s approach and
that of Schenker lead to diametrically opposite results, thus demonstrating explicitly why analogies between music and language must
break down. For although Chomsky’s deep structures can be enlisted to
generate new sentences bearing the same meaning, Schenker’s Ursätze
cannot by any amount of transformations ever succeed in generating
new melodies bearing the same “meaning.” Roger Scruton has put the
case succinctly:91 “The deep grammar proposed by Schenker turns out,
in fact, to be the surface grammar of classical music.” In other words,
the melody is, as Wittgenstein maintained (see note 5), a form of tautology, since its ‘meaning’ is imparted only and solely through the entirety
of its surface details.
Thus, for example, the melody of Beethoven’s Ode to Joy and that of
the opening to the second movement of Brahms’ Double Concerto are
reducible by Schenkerian analysis to the same triadic Ursatz: D F♯ A.
But no one in his right musical mind would mistake the one melody
for the other, despite the fact of their identical deep structures. For
these melodies are, like ideas and concepts, to be found not in their
deep structures, but in the mind. They start in the mind and are as
individual as the individual mind that created them.92 Feeding as they
do on our sensations of pain, pleasure, grief, or joy, melodies such as
these manage somehow to represent qualities and sensibilities better
than the words to grace them can. Sloboda succeeded in showing, then,
that the unmatched power of a melody is but a concrete expression of
its supreme mystery: its meaning is conveyed not by its deep structure, but by the details of its prismatic surface.93 It is in these details
only that the mind can surmise or actually experience what it is that
melodies “mean.” No analytic probe can extract these “meanings”; for
this, there is required a deeply intuitive act, a kind of éclat or, as one
91
92
93
Scruton (n. 70), p. 318.
Maconie (n. 52), p. 11.
Thus Sloboda (n. 85), p. 16: “If the Ursatz determined the significance of music,
then there would be very little for composers to say. Much of the “meaning”
of any given piece of music is given to it through the actual surface details. In
language it is different. The significance of a sentence, in practical discourse,
lies almost entirely in its deep structure.”
46
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
ancient theorist called it, a zopyron, a “flash” of knowledge that defies
all analysis.94 Although Schenker’s Ursätze are open to the charge of
arbitrariness, in postulating them, he did expose for singing human
beings the most fundamental and universal of human attributes: musical intuition.
Whereas the “meaning” of a melody inheres in its consummate
surface, that of a sentence lies in its deep structure. This sentence, for
example, is deeply structured as Noun – Verb – Object: “John phoned
Amy.” Its meaning remains unambiguously the same even when its
surface details change: “John phoned up Amy”; “John phoned Amy
up”; “Amy was phoned by John”; “Amy was phoned up by John.”95
In other words, the deep structure of a sentence such as this carries a
meaning which can be maintained through transformational changes
in the surface structures of actual sentences. But it is ultimately in its
deep structure that the meaning of a sentence lies. With a melody, however, the condition is so profoundly reversed that it abrogates all and
any analogies between speech and song. The melody which Beethoven
set to Schiller’s Ode to Joy, for example, is an edifice built on the structural pillars: D – F♯ – A. These notes constitute Schenker’s Ursatz, the
deep structure, the distilled essence of the work’s tonality. But without
the mind of Beethoven to build upon them the surface details of the
Ode to Joy, they must remain frozen in place, the product of an analysis
from which the unique ‘meaning’ of Beethoven’s melody can never be
extracted.96
94
95
96
The ancient theorist referred to here is Ptolemaïs of Cyrene (for whom, see
Chapters 6 and 7), the type of woman whom Juvenal would have characterized
as Rara avis in terris nigroque simillima cygno (the rarest bird on earth, unique as
a black swan). The phrase occurs in Juvenal Satire 6. 165. This is the only compliment paid to a woman by Juvenal, but he immediately nullifies it by saying
that such a woman would have been so “proud of all her virtues as to be quite
intolerable.” See Gilbert Highet, Juvenal the Satirist, p. 92. Ptolemaïs was, it is
most certain, as rare as a Black Swan, but one who showed no consciousness of
her own uniqueness.
Cf. Sloboda (note 70), p. 14.
For a comprehensive examination of the distinguishing structural features of
melody, see Kivy, Music Alone, pp. 124ff., in a chapter aptly titled “Surface and
Depth.” Here, Kivy shows how resistant Beethoven’s “Ode to Joy” theme is to
All Deep Things Are Song
47
The predilection to see in music a form of language – to make the
objects of musical knowledge conform as closely as possible to those
of linguistic knowledge – has produced endless controversy and has
engendered an ongoing series of unresolvable questions. All too naturally, these questions aggregate on the border-line that divides speech
from song. It is, to be sure, an almost imperceptible line on occasion;
yet the moment one crosses it in either direction, a universe is disclosed
unlike any other, one that is formed on principles peculiar to itself
alone. In failing to distinguish the formative principles upon which
music or, conversely, on which linguistic laws are based, we are destined
to become immersed in irreconcileable difficulties, the most obvious of
which is this: There is nothing in reality to answer to melody. To put
it more precisely, if a melody is not something real in the things of the
world, how can a likeness be found between it and our words for things
of the world? It is a problem as old as language and as immemorial as
music.
“deep structure” analysis. What he has to say applies to all other such masterpieces, p. 135: “The only criterion that will do the job – the one indeed which
we must assume to have been employed, implicitly, to be sure – is simply that
of removing or adding any note whatever until you get what you have already
decided is there.”
2 We Are All Aristoxenians
Caught in that sensual music,
All neglect monuments of
unageing intellect
W. B. Yeats, Sailing to Byzantium
Had he been as little regarded in his own day as he is
today, Bacchius would surely not have had conferred upon him an epithet of good consent, if not affectionate esteem: Geron, the “Old Man.”
In antiquity, certainly, as in some few segments of society now, “The Old
Man,” like Der Alter, was a term reserved for persons of high repute and
venerable wisdom.1 One would like to believe, therefore, that Bacchius
was recognized by the musicians of his day for what he represented
to them: a repository of ancient musical knowledge. Bacchius was, in
fact, a pure logician of music, one who had nothing to do with problems pertaining to mathematics, science, or to any of the other arts. His
subject-matter was music and everything pertaining solely to music.
This “everything,” as he made clear, involved the most vital source of
1
48
As Aristotle points out in Nicomachean Ethics VI. xi. 6, there is a kind of wisdom that comes with the experience of age: “Consequently, we must pay heed
to the unproven assertions and opinions of experienced and elderly people or
of prudent people no less than we do to those that are provable; for it is from
having experience that the eyes of the elderly see things correctly.” In the case
of Bacchius, it was apparently his age and experience that gave him the ability to hear things correctly. Bacchius has been translated into English by Otto
Steinmayer, “Bacchius Geron’s Introduction to the Art of Music,” Journal of Music
Theory 29 (1985), 271–98.
We Are All Aristoxenians
49
musical knowledge: melody.2 In this very special and restricted respect,
Bacchius belonged to a tradition that was founded by Aristoxenus of
Tarentum (375/360–after 320 b.c.), the most original and penetrating
musical theorist of antiquity. It was to Aristoxenus’ method and philosophy that Bacchius paid tribute in his Introduction to the Art of Music,
down to the last detail, now and then adding material that is not to be
found in the extant works of Aristoxenus himself.3 Following the path
charted by Aristoxenus, Bacchius assembled all his musical facts from
one source only: the basic truths of musical experience.
The question was, and continues to be, what are the basic truths of
musical experience and how is musical knowledge to be built up from
them? These are the questions with which Aristoxenus and his followers grappled. They began with the assumption that music is an organic
value worthy of study for its own sake, that its existence relates to nothing beyond itself, and that its meaning is self-evident to the musically
intuitive mind. This strictly musical approach is a notable example of a
potent and vigorous reaction against Pythagorean harmonics, that mathematically grounded doctrine which has dominated musical thinking
since the day Pythagoras discovered those musical ratios that hold true to
2
3
Melody, as Bacchius explains in his Introduction I. 1 (Jan, 292. 9–11), arises
from two sources only: (1) the highs and lows of musical pitches and the spaces
between them, this constituting its nature ( physis); (2) the use to which composers put these elements, this constituting the art of composition (melopoeia).
The point has often been made by scholars that for the ancients melody literally
meant music, as their music was strictly homophonic. Understandably then,
Pratinas of Phlius, a poet-musician of the 6th–5th century b.c., and composer
of dance music (hyporchēmata), wrote, with a music-maker’s enthusiasm: “It is
song that the Pierian muse has enthroned as queen” (Athenaeus Deipnosophists
xiv. 617D). The study of harmonics had nothing to do with “harmony” in the
modern sense of the term, but rather, with the proper “fitting together” (harmonia) of those elements detailed by Bacchius and other theorists. The sense of
harmonia and its etymology are examined fully by Edward Lippman, Musical
Thought in Ancient Greece, pp. 3ff.
Jon Solomon, one of the few modern scholars who have examined Bacchius’
treatise in any depth, discusses its contribution to, and departures from,
Aristoxenian theory in his “EKBOLE and EKLUSIS in the Musical Treatise of
Bacchius,” Symbolae Osloenses 55 (1980), 11–26. Cf. Chapter 1, note 2. As for
melody, it is, as Kivy, Music Alone, p. 82, remarks, “almost music itself.”
50
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the present moment: 6 is to 8 as 9 is to 12.4 The reaction to Pythagorean
doctrine on the part of theorists like Bacchius was not merely a rejection of a mathematically based harmonics but, rather, a positive assertion that the practicing musician’s ideas of melody in action are better,
freer, and more real, because they correspond more systematically to the
actual phenomena of living music than any laws of mathematics can
realize. Paradoxically enough, then, music, out of whose rich veins the
harmonic ratios had been quarried, was never to reveal its true nature in
any of these mathematical extrapolations. This, as Aristoxenus showed,
is because the truths of music’s nature do not correspond with the mathematical extrapolations by which the phenomena of physical nature can
be explained. The truths of music’s innermost nature cannot, therefore,
take the form of such mathematical extrapolations.
Although Aristoxenus’ accomplishments in musical theory and aesthetics were prodigious, his name is almost as unfamiliar today as is
that of Bacchius. Yet, he was the first to intuit music’s essence, the first
to discover the universal laws governing its structure, the first to set
out a genuine musical logic and, as is argued in Chapter 5, the first to
devise and employ a workable musical temperament. He was led to these
discoveries on the strength of two concepts which he derived from the
teachings of Aristotle: musical space is homogeneous; musical functions
are invariable. To support these fundamental assumptions, he relied on
the testimony of the musically educated ear. In showing that the nature
of these musical concepts was dissimilar to the spatio-temporal existing things of actual nature, Aristoxenus revealed a fundamental tension
between the infinity of musical space and the relative notion of the infinitesimal, as correlative to the musical note that is assumed to be finite. It
is these revelations that make his theory so applicable to the concerns of
present-day musicians.
Unlike Pythagoras, Aristoxenus had no adherents approaching the
stature of a Plato, a Euclid, or even a Nicomachus, to promulgate his
doctrine. To be sure, Bacchius transmitted Aristoxenus’ teachings with
clarity and fidelity to the master’s methods. But, like other Aristoxenians,
he was not up to the far greater task of relating Aristoxenus’ theory to
the Aristotelian model on which it was grounded – in particular, to
4
Cf. Mathieson, Chapter 1, pp. 4ff.
We Are All Aristoxenians
51
Aristotle’s version of infinite divisibility and to Aristotle’s method of
approximation in dealing with incommensurable magnitudes. This is
true also of one Cleonides, who is known to us in name only, and even
this has been a matter of scholarly dispute.5 Cleonides was a thoroughgoing Aristoxenian who, like Bacchius, knew how to formulate the
schemata and scale-systems of ancient music in a manner wholly consistent with the teachings of Aristoxenus. He also performed the great
service of transmitting material that is not found in the extant writings
of the master himself.6 But Cleonides was no philosopher. His aims
having been limited by his own capacities, Cleonides succeeded simply
in composing a school-text of an elementary sort; this text has come
down to us complete. Cleonides spoke the language of Aristoxenus, but
he made no attempt to explain the musical significance of the words he
recorded. Thus, Cleonides wrote what he knew, but he seems to have
known little of what lay behind the words that he wrote. A case in point
is that from his Introduction, Chapter 2, in which he speaks of tension
(epitasis) and resolution (anesis), these being the conditions, according
5
Full references on the question of authorship and the value of Cleonides’
treatise are provided by Thomas J. Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 366–90.
Cleonides’ treatise was translated into English by Oliver Strunk, Source
Readings in Music History, pp. 34–46, who characterized Cleonides as “an
abbreviator and popularizer of Aristoxenus” (p. 34). More recently, Cleonides
has been translated into English by Jon Solomon, “Cleonides: EISAGOGE
HARMONIKE; Critical Edition, Translation, and Commentary” (Ph.D. dissertation, University of North Carolina–Chapel Hill, 1980), 162–74. M. L.
West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 5, sums up the status of Cleonides in these succinct terms: “Cleonides’ lucid handbook, formerly misattributed to Euclid, is
the most purely Aristoxenian.”
6 Most interesting by far is what Cleonides contributes to the concept of ethos, or
melodic “character,” since most of Aristoxenus’ own evidence on the subject is
lost. Cleonides’ treatment of ethos in his Introduction to Harmonics 13 (Jan, 206.
3–18) has to do with modulation (metabolē) from one ethos to another. He refers
here to three types of ethos: diastaltic (dignified, manly, and elevated); systaltic
(dejected, depressed, and unmanly); hesychastic (calm, serene, and peaceful). For
full discussion and references, see Jon Solomon, “The Diastaltic Ethos,” Classical
Philology 76 (1981), 93–100; Barker, II, p. 432, n. 150; Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre,
pp. 388–89.
52
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
to Aristoxenus, that make for the difference in highness and lowness of
musical pitch (tasis):7
7
Cleonides’ Introduction to Harmonics 2 ( Jan, 181. 7–11). Everything that
Aristoxenus had to say on the phenomena of tension and resolution confuted
all that Euclid and the Pythagoreans maintained with respect to the behavior
of strings under tension. For whereas Euclid refers the height or the depth of
pitch to a comparable increase or decrease of vibratory motion (for which, see
Chapter 4, pp. 141ff.), Aristoxenus maintained that pitch emerges only on the
completion of motion, while it is the process leading to the pitch that is construed by him as motion. In other words, Aristoxenus’ analysis of tension and
resolution had only to do with the pitches produced by the string under tension or those of the human voice. It was thus that Aristoxenus could conclude
that the voice moves in producing an interval, but that it stops in order to produce a musical note. See C. W. L. Johnson, “The Motion of the Voice, τῆς ϕωνης
κινησις, in the Theory of Ancient Music,” 44–45. On the eighteen functional
notes to which Cleonides referred, see Fig. 1, which depicts the basic scale
system.
Figure 1. The Immutable or Changeless (Ametabolon) System
We Are All Aristoxenians
53
Pitches are also called notes; we call them pitches because of plucked instruments having their strings put under tension, but we call them notes when
they are actualized by the human voice. [For being under tension is a property of both.] Notes are infinite (apeiroi) in respect to pitch; but in respect
to function (dynamis) there are eighteen to each genus.
Cleonides’ derivation of pitch (tasis) from tension (teinein) and his use
of an Aristotelian term (energein) to mean the “actualization” of notes by
the voice raise a number of issues that are pivotal in Aristoxenus’ theory
of melodic motion: the causal relation between tension and pitch; the criterion for distinguishing a musical note in particular from the infinite
possibilities of musical pitch in general; the concept of function (dynamis)
according to which a note is assigned a musically logical status in melodic
utterances.8 Most important, Cleonides has supplied a word – energein – that
does not appear in the extant writings of Aristoxenus, but one that explains
how Aristoxenus construed the production of musical notes by the human
voice, namely, as a process whereby the tensions and resolutions of the moving voice are actualized as discrete notes. Thus, even though energein (and
its related form, energeia) does not appear in Aristoxenus’ extant writings,
everything that he has to say about musical notes and what is realized on
their coming into being is commensurate with the meaning of energeia.
8
The concept of dynamis is of pivotal importance not only in Aristoxenian theory,
but also in all studies that focus on melody; cf. Chapter 1, note 39 on the role of
dynamis in modulation. To modern theorists, who speak of it as tonal function, it
is what distinguishes an abstract scale from a living mode by investing the latter with ‘meaning.’ Knud Jeppesen, Counterpoint, pp. 62–63, refers to it in these
terms: “One could define it as the sum of melodic or harmonic motive-impulses
attached to certain tones and to a certain extent tending toward the principal
tone or final. The way certain tones are emphasized while others are subordinated
chiefly determines the mode.” And when Walter Piston, Harmony, p. 31, speaks of
the “tonal function” of each degree of a scale, he has in mind what Aristoxenus calls
dynamis in Harm. El. 33 (Da Rios, 42. 8–13): “Our theory, taken in its entirety, is
concerned with melody, whether it is sung by the voice or played by instruments.
It is determined according to two things: the ear and the intellect (dianoia). We
judge the magnitude of intervals by ear; but we observe the functions (dynameis)
of these intervals with our intellect.” This, and other such passages, are central to
Aristoxenus’ theory of melodic collocation. Cf. Barker, “Aristoxenus’ Theorems,”
25: “A note’s δύναμις determines what other notes it can follow and precede.”
54
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
For this word, as Aristotle explains it, is associated with the notion of
fulfillment and has especially to do with motion:9 “For actuality (energeia) appears in particular to be a movement.”
Another Aristoxenian theorist is Gaudentius, a writer of uncertain
date and a figure as obscure as Bacchius.10 Gaudentius not only wrote
a treatise entitled Harmonic Introduction (Harmonikē Eisagōgē), but also
won for himself the title “Philosopher” for having done so. He was an
important source for Cassiodorus (b.c. 485 a.d.) who, with Boethius
(c. 480–524 a.d.) was one of the two great intermediaries between the
music of antiquity and that of the Middle Ages. Gaudentius has much
to offer that is of more than passing interest.11 He begins his treatise
engagingly enough with an epigraph:12 “I sing for the educated; you
who are profane do close your doors.”
Gaudentius introduces the subject by stressing what Aristoxenus considered to be a vital prerequisite for the application of his theory: a trained ear.
Thus Gaudentius:13
One might rightfully begin by touching upon the harmonic proportions.
For these are the elements that have to do with notes and intervals and systems, as well as with keys and modulations and melodic composition in all
9
10
Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1047a30–32.
Mathesien, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 498–509, has compiled everything that can be
known of Gaudentius, together with complete references to the editions and
translations (as by Oliver Strunk) to his treatise.
11 This is especially the case in Chapter 8 of his treatise (Jan, 337. 5 – 338. 7), where
he distinguishes between concordancy (symphonia) and discordancy (diaphonia), as
well as between homophonic intervals, or isotones which are of the class of concords, and paraphonic intervals (paraphonoi) which, he says, fall between concords
and discords. The examples that he gives of paraphonic intervals are the tritone
(as between F and B♮) and the ditone (as between G and B♮). Mathiesen, Apollo’s
Lyre, p. 502, observes of Gaudentius’ paraphonic intervals: “This is a remarkable
definition on several counts: first, Gaudentius is clearly referring to intervals of a
tritone and a ditone; and second, such intervals might have been commonly used
in instrumental accompaniments.” For, as Gaudentius said, these intervals (Jan,
338. 4–5) seem to be concords when played (literally, plucked) on strings.
12 In his note to this epigraph, Jan, p. 327, observed that it bears a striking resemblance
to an Orphic hymn quoted by the Bishop of Laodicea, Apollinarius (c. 360 a.d.).
13 Jan, 327. 4–20.
We Are All Aristoxenians
55
the genera of attunement. But he who would pay attention to the proportions
in all these areas must first train his ear by experience to hear notes accurately
and to judge of intervals as to their concordancy and their discordancy, so
that he may make use of the proportion that is compatible with his perception of the unique properties of the notes, applying a full-scale scientific knowledge that has now been augmented by trial and rational thought.
But he who is to hear the proportions without heeding the note or without
training his ear, let him depart, since he has closed the doors on his sense of
hearing. For he will stop up his ears, being unable to apprehend by ear those
things to which the proportions relate. Let us begin then by speaking of
those aspects of sound that are given through empirical training.
From this point on, Gaudentius provides a full-scale and systematic
course in Aristoxenian theory, pausing now and then to explain a
technical term, or to describe in some detail how the ancient notational characters were formed.14 In Chapters 10 and 11, however,
he departs from this program by introducing into the Aristoxenian
context the story of Pythagoras’ discovery of the harmonic ratios,
adding to this material his own numerical interpretations.15 Apart
from this curious digression, Gaudentius adheres to the Aristoxenian
theoretical framework, thus complementing the work of Bacchius
and Cleonides.
14
Thanks to the otherwise unknown Alypius, the Greek musical notation
(parasēmantikē) has been preserved in his treatise, Introduction to Music (Eisagōgē
Mousikē), the text of which appears in Jan, 367–406. Thanks also to the work
of the mid-nineteenth century German scholars, F. Bellermann, C. Fortlage, and
R. Westphal, the Greek signs and symbols have been correlated with those of modern notation, so that all the scales and fragments of Greek melodies can be faithfully transcribed. For a full account of Alypius’ production, the reader is referred to
Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 593–607. The place of the Greek system in the history
of notation can be found in C. F. Abdy Williams, The Story of Notation, pp. 6–42. The
fifteen keys (tonoi) with their ancient notation are presented by Macran, pp. 46–61.
Cf. Fortlage, Das Musikalische System Der Griechen, pp. 27–34.
15 Instead of using the more usual Pythagorean ratios – 6:8 :: 9:12 – to define the
consonant intervals, Gaudentius has as his basis 12:16 :: 18:24. Moreover, he
computes the octave and a fourth (24:9) as a consonant interval, whereas the more
traditional Pythagorean calculation (8:3) confirms the octave and a fourth to be
a discord. See Chapter 4, note 24. Cf. Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 503–4.
56
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
In his monumental Harmonics, Claudius Ptolemy (2nd century a.d.),16
the great astronomer, geographer, mathematician, and musicologist, mentions his predecessors in musical theory but seldom; when he does, it is
more often than not to criticize them. This is certainly the case when it
comes to “the Aristoxenians,” none of whom he speaks of by name. He
tells only of “the Aristoxenians” who, he argues, “are wrong in measuring the concords by the intervals and not by the notes”17 and who “are
wrong in assuming that the concord of the fourth consists of two and a
half tones.”18 In speaking of these Aristoxenians, Ptolemy suggests that
they were both numerous and ubiquitous. But the truth is that, apart
from Aristoxenus himself, those Aristoxenians who left enough writings
for Ptolemy to criticize are all of a later date than that of Ptolemy. This
is certainly true of Aristides Quintilianus, the most eclectic and comprehensive of all the Aristoxenians whose works are extant. As is the
case with Bacchius, Cleonides, and Gaudentius, nothing is known of
Aristides beyond the fact that he wrote on music. His treatise, On Music
(Peri Mousikēs), consists of three volumes and is one of the three most
16
17
18
Ptolemy’s Harmonics has been translated into English by Barker, II, pp. 275–
391, this preceded by a comprehensive introduction in which Ptolemy’s contribution is thoroughly evaluated. A second translation of Ptolemy’s treatise
has recently appeared, that by Jon Solomon, Ptolemy, Harmonics: Translation and
Commentary. To these works must be added that of Andrew Barker, Scientific
Method in Ptolemy: “Harmonics.”
Ptolemy Harm. I. 9 (Düring, 19. 16–17). Whereas Aristoxenus treated pitches
as individual points on a melodic continuum, which he construed to be infinitely divisible, Ptolemy considered the difference between pitches to be
intrinsic to the sounds themselves. Cf. Barker, II, p. 293, n. 81.
Ptolemy Harm. I. 10 (Düring, 21. 19–20). This was a common complaint
leveled by the Pythagoreans against Aristoxenus. For, as they argued, there is,
mathematically speaking, no proportional mean between two distances on the
line that are in the ratio 4:3, the ratio of the fourth. And this means that the
semi-tone or half of a whole tone is not mathematically expressible in whole
numbers. According to Barker, II, p. 295, n. 86, Ptolemy’s point is well-taken:
“Two notes forming, for example, a concord must therefore have distinctive
properties (their ‘quantities’) between which the relation holds. They cannot
be featureless points, and the concordance cannot be a property inhering in
the empty distance between them.” It is on this issue that Aristoxenus and the
mathematicians are worlds apart. See Chapter 4, note 39.
We Are All Aristoxenians
57
influential in the field (the other two being those of Aristoxenus and
Ptolemy). According to Thomas J. Mathiesen, the first scholar to have
translated Aristides’ treatise into English, the style and substance of the
writing suggest that “Aristides Quintilianus was active sometime in the
late third or early fourth century a.d.”19
When it came to the promulgation of his doctrine, Aristoxenus was
at a most serious disadvantage. For, in addition to the unfortunate fact
that his own writings have reached us in an incomplete state,20 there
seems to have been no one among his adherents who was musician
enough to understand the significance of his concepts, or philosopher
enough to grasp the logic of their content. Yet he was for centuries
quoted by some of the most learned and celebrated minds of antiquity, among them: Athenaeus of Naucratis, Plutarch of Chaeronea,
Porphyry of Tyre, Vitruvius Pollio (the Roman architect), Cicero, and
Boethius, to mention only a few.21 He was catechized (as by Bacchius
19
See Thomas J. Mathiesen, Aristides Quintilianus: On Music in Three Books, p. 14.
This work has been deeply analyzed by Barker, “Aristides Quintilianus and
Constructions in Early Music Theory,” CQ, 32 (i.), (1982), 184–97, and translated by him in Barker, II, pp. 399–535.
20 The treatise designated in most of the manuscripts as “The Harmonic
Elements of Aristoxenus” has come down to us in three books. That it has
been compiled from as many as three or even four separate works has been
suggested by scholars on the basis of various (perceived) inconsistencies,
repetitions, and omissions in its treatment of the subject. The first book
defines the scope of harmonics and its subsidiary subjects; the second redefines it, establishing the principles (archai) from which its laws are deduced;
the third comprises theorems and proofs in the manner of Euclid’s Elements,
breaking off abruptly in the course of examining the species of the fourth.
Scholarly opinion on the problem of the work’s compilation from a multiplicity of treatises is discussed by Macran, pp. 89–92. The whole question
is given penetrating analysis by Da Rios in her Prolegomena, pp. cvii–cxvii.
For a detailed chapter by chapter programming of the treatise, see Barker II,
pp. 120–25 and Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 294–344. An argument in favor
of a unified work has been offered by Annie Bélis, Aristoxène de Tarente et
Aristote, pp. 34–36 that is strong enough to make everyone rethink his position on the subject.
21 Everything that was said about Aristoxenus by the ancients, together with all
the fragments from his work that were preserved by them, can be found in the
collection assembled by Fritz Wehrli, “Aristoxenus” in Die Schule des Aristoteles.
58
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Geron), and compiled (as by Cleonides); he was diagrammed (as by
Nicomachus),22 he was mathematicized (as by Ptolemy);23 he was stylized (as by Aristides Quintilianus),24 he was put into one context – the
Pythagorean (as by Nicomachus)25 – and taken out of another – his own
22
23
24
25
This material has also been compiled by Da Rios in her edition of Aristoxenus
under Testimonia, pp. 95–136.
Nicomachus Manual, ch. 12 (Jan, 264. 8–40) and Excerpta 9 (Jan, 280. 12–281.
1–17). These diagrams with their ancient notational symbols are reproduced
with modern notation by Levin, Manual, pp. 175–76; p. 196. Bacchius’ treatise
is one of three ancient works on music that employ the question and answer format of a catechism. The two others are the nineteenth book of the Aristotelian
Problems and The Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music by Ptolemaïs of
Cyrene, of which only a few fragments remain. Ptolemaïs stands out amid the
specialists in music not only for being a woman – a rarity indeed – but, more
important, for daring to criticize the Pythagoreans on fundamental grounds,
something that no musical writer but Aristoxenus had undertaken to do. To be
sure, Ptolemy criticized the Pythagoreans when they seemed too dogmatic to
him, but he was at heart a Pythagorean himself. Of the writers mentioned here,
Cleonides is the most consistently Aristoxenian. On Ptolemaïs, see Chapter 6.
I believe that one of the most important contributions which Ptolemy makes
toward our better understanding of Aristoxenus’ theory is his demonstration of the Aristoxenian measurement of musical intervals. In Harm. I. 13
(Düring, 29, 11–12), he explains Aristoxenus’ method as one which treats
intervals not as numerical ratios, but as tonal distances on the line of pitch:
“He [sc. Aristoxenus] divides the tone sometimes into two equal parts, sometimes into three, sometimes into four, and sometimes into eight” . . . (trans.
Barker II, p. 303). The implications of Aristoxenus’ method are discussed
in Chapter 5.
Aristides’ accounts of notes, intervals, systems, genera, keys, and modulation
are derived almost entirely from the teachings of Aristoxenus. When Aristides
says in his De musica I. 4 (Winnington-Ingram, 4. 18–19): “Music is the study
of melody and everything pertaining to melody,” he, like Bacchius, places himself squarely in the Aristoxenian tradition. On the importance of this definition, see Mathiesen, Aristides, Introduction, note 111; “‘Melos’ is a technical
term that refers to the complete musical complex . . .”
In the second chapter of his Manual ( Jan, 238. 18–240. 26), Nicomachus offers
a detailed account of pitch attributes which is based upon a concept of motion
radically different from that of the Pythagoreans. Instead of a Pythagorean
analysis of motion as consisting in physical vibration, as would be expected
here, Nicomachus describes it as a subjective phenomenon residing in senseperception. This, the method of Aristoxenus, was applied by Nicomachus to
We Are All Aristoxenians
59
(as by Gaudentius);26 all this and more, until the dynamic principles
underlying his theory were finally oversimplified out of existence. Apart
from the incomplete Harmonic Elements of Aristoxenus himself, all that
remains of his theory can be read in the compilations and abridgements
of his followers, the now unknown and long-forgotten “Aristoxenians.”
For all their efforts, however, they are remembered in the following
terms by M. L. West:27
Aristoxenus’ harmonic theory was highly influential, and it is regurgitated in several works written probably between the second and fifth centuries ad, where
lost proportions of Aristoxenus’ exposition are also reflected. [italics added]
Given West’s infelicitous characterization of these Aristoxenian treatises, it
is a wonder that any of them were ever deemed worthy of study. West’s opinion notwithstanding, these documents can be effectively mined for the nuggets of Aristoxenian wisdom that they contain. Marcus Meibom, for example,
a prodigious scholar of the seventeenth century, thought it important enough
to provide the Greek texts of these works together with his own Latin translations and commentaries, a contribution that to this day continues to be of
great value.28 And Charles-Émile Ruelle thought it worth his while to translate them into French between the years 1871 and 1898.29 To these major
contributions to the field must be added that of Andrew Barker, who has
something that was never its specific object – number. His reasons for doing so
are discussed by Levin, Nicomachus, pp. 56–57.
26 Whereas Bacchius, following Aristoxenus, refers every aspect of the study of
music to melody and all that pertains to melody, Gaudentius seems to have
had a different objective, one for which he has received little recognition: to
reconcile the mathematically based harmonics of the Pythagoreans with the
musical imperatives of Aristoxenian theory. Thus, Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre,
p. 503: “It is remarkable that he [sc. Gaudentius] presents these intervals [sc.
octave-and-a-fourth] not only in Aristoxenian terms as the number of tones contained in each interval but also in Pythagorean terms as numerical ratios . . .”
27 West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 5.
28 Marcus Meibom, Antiquae musicae auctores septem (Amsterdam 1652).
29 Each of Ruelle’s translations is listed separately by Mathiesen in Apollo’s Lyre,
Bibliography under items: 1352 (Sextus Empiricus); 1011 (Nicomachus); 329
(Cleonides); 77 (Aristoxenus); 54 (Aristotelian Problems); 26 (Alypius and
Gaudentius; Bacchius).
60
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
translated more ancient musical treatises into English than anyone else since
Meibom first cast them into Latin. Barker offers this reason for his failure to
include among his translations the writings of Bacchius and Gaudentius:30
In mitigation I can plead that the bulk of the information they offer can be
found either in Aristoxenus’ El. Harm. itself, or in the first book of Aristides
Quintilianus. . . . I might add that they make dreary reading: Aristides
Quintilianus, for all his faults, at least has some fire in his belly.
To make matters worse for the followers of Aristoxenus, Giovanni
Comotti sees no reason for studying them at all:31
It is evident that the authors of these treatises were little concerned with
music as it was performed, and only wished to define the theoretical underpinnings of music in the abstract. The motives behind such attitudes can
be explained by the traditions of ancient thought. But in any case a lengthy
consideration of their works would not contribute appreciably to our knowledge of the history of Greek and Roman musical culture.
On the contrary. The De Musica of Aristides Quintilianus, to take
just one example, not only contains evidence of a high antiquity, but
also offers a considerable mélange of Aristoxenian material, together
with some critical insights into Aristoxenus’ originality of thought.32
30
31
32
Barker, II, p. 3.
Comotti, Music in Greek and Roman Culture, p. 3.
In his De mus. I. 7 (Winnington-Ingram, 12–13), Aristides lists a set of nine
ancient modes in a notation, the first line of which appears to be a set of numbers, while the rest is not to be found anywhere else. Cf. Barker, II, p. 412,
n. 80. Even more provocative is what Aristides has to offer in De. Mus. I. 9
(Winnington-Ingram, 19. 2ff.); for here Aristides lists together with ancient
notation the six harmoniai or modes which “the divine Plato mentions in the
Republic” [399A]; these, the Lydian, Phrygian, Mixolydian, Dorian, Iastian,
and Syntonolydian (Intense Lydian), so graphically described by Aristides,
have provoked almost endless discussion and controversy among scholars.
For a vigorous argument against the authenticity of Aristides’ evidence, see
Monro, The Modes of Ancient Greek Music, pp. 95–100. The evidence is treated
most seriously by Landels, Music in Ancient Greece and Rome, pp. 103–06 and by
Anderson, Music and Musicians in Ancient Greece, pp. 154–57, who queries the
translation and commentary of Mathiesen on this passage (p. 154, n. 9).
We Are All Aristoxenians
61
Much of this evidence was passed on by Martianus Capella between
410 and 439 a.d. in an idiosyncratic treatise addressed to his son and
entitled On the Nuptials of Mercury and Philology (De Nuptiis Mercurii
et Philologiae).33 Aristoxenian musical formulations are preserved also
in the fragment known as Bellermann’s Anonymus;34 they show up
where least expected, in a Pythagorean context, by way of Nicomachus
of Gerasa;35 they reappear intact in the treatise on harmonics by the
Byzantine theorists, Manuel Bryennius and George Pachymeres.36
Apart from the valuable anecdotal evidence of such writers as Plutarch,
Strabo, Athenaeus, Vitruvius Pollio, Boethius, Porphyry, and many
others of sufficient stature to guarantee Aristoxenus’ fame by the mere
mention of his name, Aristoxenus remains today either unknown or,
where known, unappreciated for his remarkable accomplishments in
music. The technical manuals, however important they may be, do not
do justice to Aristoxenus’ originality of thought. They are devoted for
the most part to the applied aspects of Aristoxenus’ theory, as distinct
from the a priori principles of unity in which they are grounded. In sum
33
Thus, Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, p. 523: “Aristides Quintilianus remains unmentioned
by name in any datable source earlier then Martianus Capella.” Capella has been
translated into English by W. H. Stahl, Martianus Capella and the Seven Liberal Arts.
34 These are the remains of three treatises containing vital information on rhythm
and rhythmic notation, musical theory, and melodic composition, much of
which is derived from Aristoxenian sources. The set has been edited, translated,
and provided with a commentary by Dietmar Najock, Drei anonyme griechische
Traktate über die Musik.
35 See note 25. Nicomachus’ motive, as suggested, seems to have been to advocate the primacy of Pythagoras and his followers in all matters concerning
music.
36 Manuel Bryennius, the tutor of the astronomer Theodorus Metochites
(c. 1260–1332 a.d.), wrote a three-volume Harmonics sometime around
1300 a.d., and his older contemporary, George Pachymeres (1242–after
1308) wrote a Quadrivium (comprising arithmetic, music, geometry, and
astronomy) sometime earlier. Both works are fascinating, not only for their
appreciation of Aristoxenus, but also for their abundant transmissions
from the works of Aristides, Ptolemy, Nicomachus, et al. For Bryennius,
see G. H. Jonker, The Harmonics of Manuel Bryennius; for Pachymeres,
see P. Tannery, Quadrivium de Georges Pachymère. These and other Byzantine
works are discussed by Lukas Richter, Momente der Musikgeschichte Antike und
Byzanz, pp. 188ff.
62
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
then, among all the Aristoxenian specialists from Aristoxenus’ own day
until the Byzantine era, there was no one of Aristoxenus’ own intellectual capacities to argue for his aims or for his methods. Andrew Barker
states the case in these words:37
By contrast [with Aristoxenus’ own approach], many later ‘Aristoxenian’ writers sought only to give a scholastic exposition of the master’s ‘doctrines,’ and to
reduce them to an academic system, neglecting the need for harmonic understanding to be grounded in real musical experience, and ironing out many of
the penetrating ideas that Aristoxenus had derived from that source himself.
However dull, dreary, and derivative the writings of his followers
may be thought by scholars, Aristoxenus himself, while not an especially graceful writer, is always an arresting one, particularly for musicians. For that, he deserves a fate far better than the one allotted to him
by intellectual history. He should, in fact, be numbered, as he once was,
among those most eminent in their field. Indeed, like “The Geometer,”
as Euclid was known, “The Philosopher,” as Aristotle was called, and
“The Astronomer,” as Ptolemy was titled, Aristoxenus was for centuries
almost always distinguished by the epithet, “The Musician.” If today
he is scarcely known at all by musicians, the cause cannot be assigned
solely to the dullness or apishness of his followers’ writings. Nor can
Aristoxenus’ loss of standing in the history of musical thought be
ascribed to the “confusion with which subsequent theorists interpreted
his central thesis,” as Richard Norton postulates:38
Hack theorists disseminated a mixture of Aristoxenian theory, casually mixed
with their own speculations, until Aristoxenus was made to support the very idea
he sought to defeat – the principles of pitch measurement according to atomic
microtones and the authoritative basis of Pythagorean number proportions.
As matters stand today, whenever and wherever the subject of music
is raised, it is, for the most part, not Aristoxenus, but Pythagoras, who
is held to be the universal well-spring of musical knowledge.39 But
37
38
39
Barker, II, p. 5.
Richard Norton, Tonality in Western Culture, p. 101.
Lukas Richter has recently summed up the power and the dimensions of
Pythagorean thought in his Momente der Musikgeschichte Antike und Byzanz,
We Are All Aristoxenians
63
this was not always the case. To Cicero, for example, who lived almost
three-hundred years after him, Aristoxenus was still the ultimate and
unchallenged authority in all things musical:40
Quantum Aristoxeni ingenium consumptum videmus in musicis?
Do we realize how great the talent of Aristoxenus was that he lavished on
musical subjects?
Moreover, as Cicero saw it, Aristoxenus, like Damon before him,
was to music even as Hippocrates was to medicine and as Euclid and
Archimedes were to geometry.41 And as if Cicero’s words were not
praise enough, Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. early third century a.d.),
the great commentator on Aristotle, had this to say of Aristoxenus:42
θείη γὰρ ἂν τις ὡς ἔνδοξον τὸ ὑπὸ
Ἱπποκράτους λεγόμενον ἐν ἰατρικῇ
καὶ τὸ ὑπὸ Ἀρχιμήδους ἐν γεομετρίᾳ
καὶ τὸ ὑπὸ Ἀριστοξένου ἐν μουσικῇ
For anyone might hold as a matter of the highest importance what is
said by Hippocrates in medicine, and what is said by Archimedes in
geometry, and what is said by Aristoxenus in music.
Writing some two hundred years after Alexander of Aphrodisias,
Martianus Capella ranked Aristoxenus with no less a performing musician than Orpheus himself, the very personification of music:43
Linum, Homerum Mantuanumque vatem reditos canentesque
conspiceres, Orpheum atque Aristoxenum fidibus personantes,
Platonem Archimedemquem sphaeras aureas devolventes.
40
41
42
43
p. 196: “The Pythagorean philosophers conceived of number as the very essence
of things (arithmetica universalis) and saw harmonia, that is, the union of opposites, realized in the whole world, in the soul of humankind and in the lawful
ordering of intervals in the tonal system. The particular sequence of intervals
of the individual modes determined the characteristic effect of the music which
we account for as a repatriation of the soul to the cosmic harmonia.”
Cicero De finibus V. 18. 49 = Fr. 69b Wehrli.
Cicero, De oratore III, 33, 132 = Fr. 69a Wehrli.
Alexander Aphrodisias Comment. In Aristot. Topica 105a34 = Fr. 69e Wehrli.
Martianus Capella, II. 212 = Fr. 69f Wehrli.
64
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
You might contemplate Linus, Homer and the Mantuan bard,
and the wreathed singers, Orpheus and Aristoxenus, playing on their
strings; Plato and Archimedes spinning their golden spheres.
Orpheus, Hippocrates, Euclid, and Archimedes, not to mention
Plato, Homer, and Virgil, stand today with the most towering figures
in the history of human knowledge: no one needs to be told who they
are or why their fame has persisted undiminished through the ages.
Aristoxenus, however, whose work in music was once considered one
of the high-water marks of ancient Greek musical culture, entitling
him to be ranked with the likes of Orpheus, Plato, and Euclid, et al., is
today all but forgotten, even by his own countrymen and by sharers in
the art of music. For, ironically enough, despite all the evidence of his
once supreme eminence in music, Aristoxenus continues to be eclipsed
by the figure of Pythagoras. It is a modern Greek composer then, who
offers this maxim for present-day musicians to contemplate:44
We are all Pythagoreans.
Xenakis might have said more rightfully:
We are all Aristoxenians.
For the inescapable truth is that if we claim to be musicians, then we
are, at heart, all Aristoxenians.45
Once as well-known a name as Euclid’s and Archimedes’, that of
Aristoxenus has been almost completely obliterated from the pages of
intellectual history, and no single reason can be assigned for this penalty
against musical thought and aesthetics. According to Barker (note 37),
and Norton (note 38), the cause must lie with the incapacity of his
followers to transmit his doctrine adequately. By contrast, Comotti,
44
45
This statement by Iannis Xenakis stands as an epigraph in Jamie James, The
Music of the Spheres.
There are two things that give Aristoxenus’ theory a universal significance;
the first is explicit, the second must be inferred: (1) melody admits of sizeless
points between which there is an alignment and among which there are centers
of gravity. Though they have no size, these points have position, so sharp and
so apparent that they coincide perfectly with idealized instants of time. (2)
the time which music inhabits becomes by virtue of this habitation an eternal
present; it is this that makes all music contemporary.
We Are All Aristoxenians
65
by managing to confuse the doctrine of Aristoxenus with that of the
Pythagoreans – something that Aristoxenus’ followers never did –
contributes greatly to Aristoxenus’ loss of standing in the field:46
The method, formulations, and goals of Pythagorean acoustical research had
a decisive influence on the direction of all subsequent speculative work in the
field of music. Damon and, after him, Plato and Aristotle especially, advanced
the study of the effects of music on the human soul. Aristoxenus, on the other
hand, and all the scholars of the Hellenistic and Roman periods – with the
exception of the Epicurean theorists – took as the basis for their research the physical and mathematical principles embodied in Pythagorean doctrine. [italics added]
Perhaps the most interesting reason for Aristoxenus’ fall from grace
is that offered by Meibom (see note 48). For by the time Meibom completed translating Aristoxenus’ Harmonic Elements into Latin (1652),
Aristoxenus had already been long since forgotten. In rediscovering
Aristoxenus’ writings for himself, Meibom realized that he had before
him the work of the most illustrious expert in music and the chief
authority on the subject (de hac disciplina scriptis celeberrimum,
Musicorum principem, Aristoxenum). As Meibom explains, the cause
of Aristoxenus’ hard fate was twofold: the near-limitless difficulty of his
theory; the ignorance of those who attempted to fathom it. He says:47
Quamvis enim semel atque iterum, sua lingua ac Romana loquens, in
publicum fit productus, semper tamen, ob scientiae sublimitatem,
neglectus ab omnibus ad bibliothecarum angulos redire fuit coactus.
Tantum potuit mali creare viro maximo fatalis nostro aevo ac superiore
Musicarum litterarum ignoratio.
For although he has now and again been published, speaking in his own and
in the roman tongue, he has nevertheless always been forced to return
to the narrow corners of libraries, neglected by all because of his having
touched upon almost the highest limit of his science.48 Only ignorance of
46
47
48
G. Comotti, Music in Greek and Roman Culture, pp. 27–28.
Meibom, Antiquae Musicae, Vol. I, Preface to Aristoxenus, entitled Lectori
Erudito, p. 1 [pagination supplied].
Meibom thought of Aristoxenus’ musical theory as sublimitas, literally,
“beneath the very topmost limit” of a science, a theory which was a genuine
66
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
musical studies in our own and in earlier eras could have contrived for
our most eminent man such a fate.
Aristoxenus’ scientia of music is indeed as difficult as Meibom’s word
sublimitatem implies, and critics from antiquity to the present day have differed as to its proper interpretation. When Meibom charged Aristoxenus’
interpreters with ignorance, however, he did not have in mind critics like
Ptolemy or Theon of Smyrna or Porphyry of Tyre, for example;49 on the
contrary, he reserved this judgment for the likes of Antonius Gogavinus,
whose Latin translation of 1542 he found to be completely inept, and of
Johannes Meursius, whose Greek edition of 1616 he considered to evince a
gross ignorance of musical theory.50 In contrast to these Renaissance copyists and translators, whose views can be dismissed on Meibom’s warrant,
those of Ptolemy are substantive enough to have influenced the course
of Aristoxenian studies for centuries to come. As Ptolemy saw it, the
Aristoxenians were arbitrary in placing so much value on the evidence of
science insofar as it contained truths that are independently verifiable. It was
in this sense that medieval humanists regarded poetry as a science to which
revelatory functions could be assigned. To Meibom, the value of Aristoxenus’
theory consisted in its handing down to posterity a fine grasp of the nature of
music, and a full consciousness of music’s technology and technical elements.
49 On Aristoxenus’ ancient critics, see note 18. Theon of Smyrna ( fl. 115–140
a.d.) wrote a work in three parts (Arithmetic, The Numerical Laws of Music,
Astronomy) entitled Mathematics Useful for Understanding Plato (Expositio
Rerum Mathematicarum Ad Legendum Platonem Utilium). His criticism, like
that of other mathematicians, focuses on Aristoxenus’ violation of the norms
of mathematics by insisting that the fourth “comprises two and a half perfect tones” (Hiller 67. 10–12). Porphyry of Tyre (232/233–304/305 a.d.),
originally named Malchus (Arabic Malik = King), was called Porphyrius
(the regal “Purple”) by his teacher, the Neoplatonic philosopher, Longinus.
Porphyry’s Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy is of special interest for
transmitting fragments from the work of one of Aristoxenus’ rare champions,
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, for whom, see Chapter 6. Only portions of Porphyry’s
Commentary have been translated into English, by Barker, II, 229–44. A full
English translation is forthcoming by Jon Solomon.
50 Cf. Macran, pp. 91–92. Da Rios, Prolegomena, pp. xii–xiii concurs in characterizing
the edition of Gogavinus as “abounding in serious errors (cum gravissimis mendis redundet) and that of Meursis as afflicted by a “total ignorance of Aristoxenus’
doctrine” (maxime Aristoxeni doctrinae omnino ignarum se praebuit).
We Are All Aristoxenians
67
perception (aisthēsis) and unscientific in treating reason (logos) as secondary
in importance.51 Porphyry, the commentator on Ptolemy’s Harmonics, agreed
51
It is on these fundamental grounds that Ptolemy Harm. I. 9 (Düring, 20.
11–14) attacks the Aristoxenian method. For, as he argues, the Aristoxenians
[namely, Aristoxenus himself] allege that a whole-tone is perceived by the ear
to be the difference between the fourth and the fifth; yet they ignore the fact
that the whole-tone is in reality the difference between two notes standing in an
epogdoic (9:8) ratio. In pursuing this argument against Aristoxenus, Ptolemy
himself ends up in a logical cul-de-sac, because he cannot abide the fact that
Aristoxenus’method of tuning by consonances reveals the consequence of an
infinite number of pitches within each ratio. As Barker, II, p. 294, note 85, so
aptly puts it, Ptolemy’s argument here “is a fantastic muddle.” On the various
kinds of ratios under discussion, see Fig. 2, in which ratios are listed by name.
1 1
2
1 1
3
1 1
4
1 1
3
1 1
6
1 1
7
1 1
8
1 2
3
1 3
4
1 4
3
1 2
3
1 4
7
1 5
9
Figure 2. Names of Ratios
68
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
with Ptolemy and suggested further that whatever else one might say of the
Pythagorean method, one thing was certain: the Pythagoreans were altogether right in supposing that nature’s logic is discoverable only through
the instrumentality of the intellect. Porphyry’s implication is that any theory that accords too little value to the activity of reason risks admitting
random properties. And because random properties cannot be supposed to
exist in nature, they must derive from the vagaries of perception. It was
in treating reason as secondary, therefore, that the Aristoxenians ended
up contradicting the norms of scientific inquiry as Ptolemy and Porphyry
understood them.52
Ptolemy argued, accordingly, that the Aristoxenians contradicted
the norms of scientific inquiry first, by failing to accept the Pythagorean
ratios as clearly established by mathematical truth; second, by placing
more emphasis on the spaces between the notes of melody than on the
notes themselves; third, by defining the musical elements in a circular
fashion.53 To such errors as these Ptolemy added that concerning the
measurement of the fourth:54
They [the Aristoxenians] are mistaken, furthermore, about the measurement
of the first and smallest concord, composing it as they do from two tones and a
half, so that the fifth is put together from three and a half tones, the octave from
six tones, and each of the other concords in the way that follows from this one.
For reason [logos], being more worthy of trust than perception [aisthēsis] in the
case of differences as small as these, proves that this is not so, as will be clear.
52
53
54
As Aristoxenus saw it, the nature of music is so unlike that of the world at large
that the laws of traditional mathematics, by which the Pythagoreans explained
the natural phenomena, could never succeed in explaining the phenomena of
music. Barker, in “Music and Perception: A Study in Aristoxenus,” JHS xcviii
(1978), 12, states the case succinctly: “Perceived similarities simply do not
correspond to mathematical ones, and it is the perceived similarities which constitute properly musical groupings or categories.” Barker’s insight here lies at
the heart of the Aristoxenian method.
The circularity (peritrapein) of which Ptolemy complains in Harm. I. 9 (Düring,
20. 18–22) is unavoidable according to Aristoxenus quite simply because all
the elements in Aristoxenus’ harmonic science must, in the final analysis, be
defined by reference to one another, and not by reference to anything outside
music’s own domain. Cf. Barker, II, p. 294, n. 83.
Harm. I. 10 (Düring, 21. 21–22. 1); trans. Barker.
We Are All Aristoxenians
69
And this criticism is enlarged upon by Theon of Smyrna with the
added authority of Plato:55
It is agreed by everybody that the fourth is greater than two whole-tones, but
less than three whole-tones. But Aristoxenus says that it consists of two complete whole-tones and a semitone, while Plato says it consists of two wholetones and the so-called leimma (remainder). He says that this remainder (leimma)
does not have a name, but that it stands in a number to number relation as 256
to 243; and that this is an interval the difference between whose terms is 13.
To Meibom, Aristoxenus was engaged in something that he thought
worthy enough to be characterized as scientiae sublimitatem (see note 48);
to his critics, however, Aristoxenus’ theory could not be called a science
at all, for, as they saw it, the object of his musical representation could
not be an object of knowledge in a strict sense. In other words, musical
notes, as they construed them, do not have any significative force, but
are merely the sound of a voice or an instrument. In short, Aristoxenus’
critics could not consider the possibility that music might reveal the
nature of things with an intensity and depth unmatched by rational
thought. Aristoxenus was engaged in something, to be sure. If, as his
critics alleged, it was not worthy of the name, science, it might more
properly be called logic – musical logic. Indeed, its limits are even as
Aristoxenus’ modern critics have judged them to be. But they were selfimposed limits. For they arise from Aristoxenus’ having debarred his
field of inquiry from all other branches of knowledge, leaving himself
with nothing to deal with save music itself and its forms. This was his
intention, but it won him the same disapprobation in modern times
as befell him in antiquity, so much so that he might with justice have
said (pace Peter Abelard):56 “Omnibus me supra modum ignotum atque
obscurum effeci.” [I have made myself opprobrious beyond measure as
well as unintelligible to everyone.]
Aristoxenus cannot rightfully claim the credit for making himself ignotum and obscurum to all, nor can his followers be charged with
55
56
De limmate (Hiller, 67, 8–16). Theon’s treatise has been translated by R. and
D. Lawlor.
Cf. Peter Abelard, Epistola I: Historia Calamitatum Abaelardi (Cousin) I, p. 17.
70
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
having effaced him from the literature on music. Modern musicologists
have managed to do this without any assistance from the followers of
Aristoxenus or from the master himself. Examples of these successful efforts abound. To J. F. Mountford, an especially acrid critic, who
could conceive of harmonic theory in no other terms than those of
Pythagorean science, Aristoxenus was scarcely worthy of study:57
Sharply distinguished from this metaphysical theory [the Pythagorean doctrine]
is the system which was first enunciated by Aristoxenus. For him pure mathematics and physics had no attraction. He postulated that in music the ear is the
sole and final arbiter and that a mathematical formula has little or nothing to do
with music. In this he was absolutely wrong, so far as theory goes; and so far as
the art of music is concerned, he was only partially right. Ears differ in sensitivity
and one naturally asks what kind of ear is to be the sole criterion; is it to be the
ear of a highly critical musician or the average listener? To rely only upon the ear
for the data of a system of musical theory is to use a rough-and-ready method.
Having said this much, Mountford went on to provide a concise and
very accurate outline of Aristoxenus’ theory, stressing with admirable clarity its two pivotal axioms, both of which contradict at the deepest level the
Pythagorean doctrine of harmonics: (1) the progression of melodic sound
from the low pitch to the high ones and back again is as a continuous line;
(2) this continuous line of pitch, or continuum, is infinitely divisible into
equal parts. Given these axioms, Aristoxenus could arrive at the logical
conclusion that the difference between a perfect fourth and a perfect fifth is
a whole-tone, which is itself capable of infinite divisions. This Aristoxenian
anti-Pythagorean doctrine provoked Mountford to say grudgingly that
although it “has a superficial lucidity,” it cannot be taken too seriously:58
This linear conception of intervals, however, lies at the very root of the
Aristoxenian theory and proves to be a quite impenetrable barrier to a proper
knowledge of the nature of Greek scales. It would be grotesque to suggest
57
58
In K. Schlesinger, The Greek Aulos, Introduction, p. xxi.
Ibid. Aristoxenus knew, as do all musicians, that “the subtle and changing
relationships of tones and semitones within the structure of a scale produce
continuous variations to the discerning ear.” Cf. Blum, Casals and the Art of
Interpretation, p. 35.
We Are All Aristoxenians
71
that this theory can be entirely neglected or to deny that from it we can infer
much that is worth knowing; but for the fundamental question about the size
of the intervals of the Greek scales it is too unscientific to be of real service.
Another critic of Aristoxenus’ method had this to say:59
Aristoxenus was a prolific writer who has been extensively quoted by later
authors. He scorned the application of numbers to music. He preferred his
own slipshod method of guesswork.
Thus, when Aristoxenus estimated the enharmonic diesis (quartertone) to amount “to one fourth of the difference between the fifth and
fourth,” or, more easily said, one-fourth of a whole-tone, the same critic,
E. Clements, professing, as it seems, to know more about ancient Greek
scales than Aristoxenus himself, observed:60 “The diesis of Aristoxenus
was a conception of no practical value.”
More important by far than the criticism of Aristoxenus voiced by
Mountford and Clemens, is that of R. P. Winnington-Ingram. For in
a single article dating from 1932 and entitled “Aristoxenus and the
Intervals of Greek Music,” Winnington-Ingram succeeded in influencing the course of Aristoxenian studies for the rest of the twentieth century.61 Winnington-Ingram is not only historically important in his
own right; he represents, better than any other scholar in the field of
ancient Greek music, an important type of musical theory: the mathematical. Equally important, in his criticisms of Aristoxenus, he has, in
many respects, clarified Aristoxenus’ own teachings, for he has revealed,
with as much consistency as possible, the type of theory advocated by
Aristoxenus and the critical points at which it conflicts with the mathematical. His arguments are always compelling, and his statements of
Aristoxenian philosophy are far clearer than those of Aristoxenus’ own
followers. His sympathies are with Ptolemy, Archytas, the Pythagorean
of the fourth century b.c., Eratosthenes, the astronomer and mathematician of the third century b.c., and Didymus, a first century b.c.
59
60
61
E. Clements, “The Interpretation of Greek Music,” JHS xlii (1922), 139.
Op. cit., 140, n. 7.
R. P. Winnington-Ingram, “Aristoxenus and the Intervals of Greek Music,”
CQ 26 (1932), 195–208.
72
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
source for Ptolemy and for Ptolemy’s commentator, Porphyry.62 At the
same time, however, his respect for Aristoxenus is very great, save for
one instance, when he could not contain his annoyance at Aristoxenus’
having disregarded the enharmonic computations of Archytas. But even
here, he confined his displeasure to a parenthesis: “(he [sc. Aristoxenus]
was, by all accounts, a maliciously-minded person).”63
As Winnington-Ingram saw it, Aristoxenus’ theory is very hard to
understand not because of its sublimitas, but because of its lack of scientific rigor. Thus, whereas Aristoxenus’ predecessors and contemporaries
realized that musical intervals can only be expressed as ratios of stringlengths and that the addition and subtraction of intervals requires
mathematical processes of squaring and finding the square roots of the
numerical terms in the ratios, Aristoxenus ignored these laws of mathematics entirely. Instead, he consulted his own musical consciousness
and relied on the data given him by the ear. He postulated therefore
that intervals must be treated spatially, that musical space is symmetrical, and that musical intervals, being capable of infinite division, can
be added together and subtracted from one another by the most convenient methods of addition and subtraction of whole numbers. Because
of what Winnington-Ingram considered the unscientific nature of these
postulates, he could not accept the results to which they led. Whereas
he conceded that the mathematical theorists may be under “suspicion of letting irrelevant factors intrude into their calculations, he [sc.
Aristoxenus] must equally be suspected of yielding to the attractions
of symmetry and convenience.”64 Winnington-Ingram would accept
62
63
64
Ptolemy Harm. II. 14 (Düring, 70. 5–74. 3) compares his own division of the
canon in all three genera with those of Archytas, Eratosthenes, and Didymus,
using the ratios of mathematical theory. In addition, he attempted to convert
Aristoxenus’ measurement of the same intervals into the language of mathematical
ratios. Barker, II, p. 346, n. 117, says rightfully of his effort: “Since the arithmetical differences between terms in Pythagorean ratios are quite different forms of
quantity from the ‘distances’ between Aristoxenian pitches, the attempt is quite
incoherent.”
Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 201, took Aristoxenus’ failure to distinguish
properly, that is, mathematically, between the major and minor whole-tones as
a deliberate snub against Archytas.
Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 195.
We Are All Aristoxenians
73
Aristoxenus’ computations on one condition only: if they happened to
agree with those of Archytas.65
When, therefore, Aristoxenus added and subtracted musical
intervals as though they were so many equal units or quanta, and
did so, moreover, according to the dictates of an arithmetic system
which he himself devised, Winnington-Ingram could not but think
of such an approach as productive of factitious nuances. In addition,
Aristoxenus’ method of tuning by consonances, whereby he revealed
how in the circle of fifths the consonances end up varying within
a minute locus, is rejected out of hand by Winnington-Ingram on
the basis that the human ear cannot be trusted to judge correctly of
ten successive consonances.66 Finally, where other scholars have been
66
As Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 208, puts it: “The chief service of
Aristoxenus’ account of the genera seems, on examination, to be the confirmation of Archytas.”
See Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 199. On the circle of fifths, see Fig. 3, in
which the tuning discrepancies are shown.
en
gF
din
ifth
s
As
ce
nd
ing
Fi
G
ft
C
hs
De
c
65
F
A
D
E
B�
D
B
G
C
E�
A
F#
C#
F
B�
A�
A#
A�
E�
D#
G�
F#
Figure 3. Circle of Fifths
E
C�
D�
C#
G#
B
74
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
willing to credit Aristoxenus with having discovered a method for
tempering the scale, Winnington-Ingram has this to say:67
The term “equal temperament” is often used in connection with Aristoxenus;
and in a sense by dividing the octave into six and the tone into two he has
produced “equal temperament.” But the difference between his procedure
and the temperament of modern theory is more important than their resemblance. Our equal temperament is dictated by practical convenience in the
matter of modulation. The modern theorist knows that the intervals are distorted upon a tempered instrument and by how much. But Aristoxenus did
not live in an age when temperament in the modern sense was either necessary or desirable.
In sum then, Winnington-Ingram judged Aristoxenus’ theory to
be, if “not wholly nonsensical,” then seriously flawed for being wholly
unscientific.68 All things considered, it would appear on WinningtonIngram’s reading that Aristoxenus’ chief service to the field consisted
not so much in his aiming at strict equality in the division of musical
space, but, more important, in his computations of melodic intervals
that confirm those of Archytas.
Aristoxenus was struggling to do something that he said had never
been attempted before: to offer composers a system that would allow
for a flexibility that is matched only by the workings of the human
voice and that is sanctioned only by the perception of the human ear.
In addition, Aristoxenus aimed to codify the laws of melodic consecution so as to satisfy the requirements of true melodiousness (emmelēs).
To accomplish this task, he fashioned a theoretical panoply of fixed and
moveable notes, linked and unlinked tetrachords, genera and nuances,
in order to systematize and account for everything that he recognized
to be melodious in the music he had been hearing from childhood
on. His theory was designed to incorporate, therefore, everything that
made for what Plato had characterized as the “rightness” (orthōtēs) of a
melody.69 But Aristoxenus’ critics found more to censure than to praise
67
68
69
Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 198.
Cf.Winnington-Ingram (note 61), 208.
Plato Laws 670A6–B6.
We Are All Aristoxenians
75
in this, his codification of melody’s laws. For one thing, as WinningtonIngram demonstrated, the size of the diesis, or quarter-tone, seemed to
be unsettled in Aristoxenus’ schemata, but varied with the nuances
of melody beyond what theory could capture. Even worse, the very
symmetricality of his systems seemed to level away all the remarkable
subtleties and nuances of the ancient modes known as harmoniai to
Aristoxenus’ predecessors.70
Warren Anderson argued, accordingly, that the ancient and distinctive modes of diverse ethnic origin and called harmoniai (tunings) –
Dorian, Iastian (Ionian), Phrygian, Aeolian, and Lydian – were all but
lost in the theoretical symmetries of Aristoxenus:71
All this [Aristoxenus’ system] has a certain complex majesty, but it takes us
into a realm of theoretic perfection which Harmoniai of the earlier Hellenic
period can hardly hope to have known.
As Anderson explains, by locating these independent modal tunings within
the framework of a fifteen-note diatonic system – the Greater Perfect System,
so-called – a sequence found in the white keys of the piano ranging from A
to A2, Aristoxenus transformed what had hitherto been a series of differentiated modes into segments or species (eidē) of the octaves contained in this
larger system. In so doing, he effectively dissolved the ancient Harmoniai
into a homogenized system in which more was apparently lost than gained.
Anderson’s exposition of Aristoxenus’ standardized system is clear and concise; but for reasons unstated by him, he omits what may be vital where the
issue of modality is concerned: the chroai. Thus, Anderson:72
A final principle of differentiation is the distinction according to genus
(kata genos), determined by the type of interval sequence within the fixed
70
Aristoxenus Harm. El. II. 36 (Da Rios, 46. 9–10) speaks of his predecessors as
being occupied “only with the seven octochords which they called harmoniai.”
As Henderson, “Ancient Greek Music,” 349 justly points out, Aristoxenus
himself identified these tropes of the classical idiom as melē – “melodies” – and
not merely octave scales.
71 Anderson, Ethos and Education in Greek Music, p. 18.
72 Anderson (note 71), pp. 17–18. Cf. Fig. 4, showing the octors species and the
tonoi.
76
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
boundary notes of each tetrachord. While Aristoxenus lists a variety of
diatonic and chromatic genera, we may disregard the nuanced varieties known
as “shadings” (chroai) and cite the following sequences as fundamental.
Criticism of Aristoxenus by some of the leading specialists in the
field has continued to the present day. Reading it, one is given the
decided impression that Aristoxenus is a writer whose evidence on
ancient Greek music can either be dismissed as completely unreliable
or, at best, taken cum grano salis. M. L. West, for example, suggests that
Figure 4. Paradigmatic System with Octave Species
We Are All Aristoxenians
77
Aristoxenus did not even understand what he himself was saying as, for
example, in the case of the whole-tone interval:73
Apart from that [sc. shades of intonation], there is a problem about what
exactly is meant by a “tone.” The Greek writers define it as the interval by
which a fifth is greater than a fourth. Strictly speaking, that is the interval
given by the ratio 9:8, or 204 cents. But Aristoxenus regards it as being at
the same time a unit of which a fourth (properly 498 cents) contains exactly
two and a half. In effect he is operating with a tempered tone of 200 cents
and a tempered fourth of 500 cents. He does not understand that that is
what he is doing; he is simply working by ear. . . . Sometimes he speaks of
intervals such as a third of a tone or three eighths of a tone. We must take
these with a little pinch of salt, not as mathematically precise measurements but as approximations gauged by the ear.
Making matters even worse for Aristoxenus, there is discord among
his critics. This is especially true when the question of modulation
arises. As Winnington-Ingram stated authoritatively (see note 67),
equal temperament is most necessary for the purpose of modulation,
but in Aristoxenus’ day temperament, he said, was neither desirable
nor even necessary for this purpose. But West insists, as did Anderson
before him (see note 71), that the ancient modal scales were submerged
in Aristoxenus’ system of keys precisely because he was more interested in providing for the possibilities of modulation than in preserving
modal distinctions:74
In working out his system of keys, Aristoxenus was not primarily concerned
with the placement of modal scales interpreted as octave species. . . . but allowed
the concept of mode to be submerged in that of key. What he was more concerned about was to provide for and account for every kind of modulation.
Nor is that all. Aristoxenus was not only condemned to inferiority
as a musical theorist, but also to unreliability as a historian of his own
musical heritage. To be sure, Aristoxenus’ arresting personality, which
he never attempted to mitigate, will probably always provide historians
73
74
West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 167.
West (note 73), p. 229.
78
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of music with ample material about which to quarrel.75 Yet one thing
is certain: Aristoxenus must have known far more about his own musical tradition than we can hope to fathom completely at this distance
in time. When, therefore, he tells us about the enharmonic genus, for
example, and the great difficulty that it presented to musicians of his
own antiquity, his words bespeak the intimate knowledge of the art
that is given only to a skilled practitioner. He says this:76
There appear to be three genera: for every melody that is consistent with
the same tuning throughout is either diatonic or chromatic or enharmonic.
We must consider the first and oldest of these to be the diatonic, for human
nature happens upon it first; the second is the chromatic and the third and
most recondite (anōtaton)77 is the enharmonic, for the ear becomes accustomed to it at the very last and only after great effort and practice.
That is firsthand evidence from Aristoxenus himself. But there is
also some thirdhand evidence on the enharmonic genus and its discovery that appears in the Plutarchian treatise On Music, which reports
what Aristoxenus had learned from certain unnamed musicians who
apparently lived long before him:78
75
Thus, Barker, II, p. 119: “He [sc. Aristoxenus] was notoriously humourless, acerbic, and opinionated, outspoken and unscrupulous in speech as in writing. . . . To
judge by what he says [in his Harmonic Elements], all previous writers on harmonics were incompetents or charlatans. He and he alone has understood how
the subject should be pursued, and has grasped the truths it contains.”
76 Harm. El. I. 19 (Da Rios, 24. 17–25. 4).
77 Anōtaton, a superlative formed from anō, is, in its literal meaning, “topmost,”
virtually unintelligible, as numerous scholars have pointed out. A history of the
various solutions offered is reviewed by Da Rios, Aristosseno, p. 29, note 1, who
prefers “piú elevato degli altri” (“the most elevated of the others”). Barker, II, p. 139,
n. 73, allows her reading as possible, but suggests instead, “Most sophisticated,”
which would aptly describe the enharmonic genus. Macran’s “most recondite”
seems most fitting, however, in the light of Artistoxenus’ words that follow, these
detailing the musical difficulties associated with the enharmonic genus.
78 Ps.-Plutarch De Musica, Ch. 11; 1134f. Because the treatise that has come down
under his name is judged not to have come from the hand of Plutarch himself, it
is designated by some scholars as Pseudo-Plutarch or Plutarchian. On its importance as a source for the classical period, see West, Ancient Greek Music, pp. 5–6.
We Are All Aristoxenians
79
Olympus, as Aristoxenus says, is accepted by the musicians as having been
the inventor of the enharmonic genus; for before him all melodic genera had
been diatonic and chromatic. The musicians conjecture that the invention
came about in this way: that Olympus was turning a melody around upside
down (anastrephomenon) in the diatonic genus and time after time he had it
leap over to the diatonic parhypatē (F), sometimes starting from the paramesē
(B), and sometimes from the mesē (A): and when he omitted the diatonic
lichanos (G), he became aware of the beauty of the ethos. He was so struck
with wonder at the system composed from this tonal distribution that he
adopted it and in this system he composed music in the Dorian key.
What has been set out here with archaic simplicity is the discovery
of the most primitive form of the enharmonic genus, that which exposes
the interval most characteristic of this genus: the ditone or Major third.
According to this account, Olympus was composing music using
five notes from the diatonic genus: E (which is inferred to be hypatē),
F (parhypatē), G (lichanos), A (mesē), and B (paramesē). Any number of
fine melodies could (and have been) composed from even so few notes as
these. But in writing down these bare and lifeless pitch-relations shorn
of all melodic motion, rhythm, and timbre, we cannot begin to capture
the essence of the melodies that Olympus was composing, much less the
genus he was in the act of discovering. We can only imagine the oboelike
tones of his aulos79 descending sometimes from B to F and sometimes
from A to F, filling in the notes between (B A G F) and (A G F E). It was
79
The aulos, the chief wind-instrument of the ancient Greek musicians, has often
been mistranslated as “flute,” an error noted by West (note 78) in words that bear
repeating (Introduction, p. 1): “ . . . and now the only excuse for calling an aulos a
flute is that given by Dr. Johnson when asked why he defined ‘pastern’ as the knee
of a horse: ‘Ignorance, madam, pure ignorance.’” The most important work on the
aulos remains that of Kathleen Schlesinger, The Greek Aulos, who argued vigorously for the aulos as a true conveyor of the ancient harmoniai, or modes. Her work,
having generated more criticism than praise, is, as a consequence, sadly under
appreciated. Thus West (above, note 78), p. 96: “Kathleen Schlesinger wrote a
massive, terrifying book, The Greek Aulos, based on the belief that the Greek pipes
too had equi-distant finger-holes.” Schlesinger’s theory deserves more attention
than it has received. There were two types of auloi: the double-reed, like the modern oboe; the single-reed, like the modern clarinet. Virtually everything that is
known about the auloi is summarized by West (note 78), pp. 81–109.
80
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
only when Olympus left out the note G (lichanos) that he came upon the
beauty of the ditone, F – A, and conversely, A – F. And he was seized
with wonder at the sound, the same wonder that Aristoxenus expressed
when he too encountered the indescribable beauty of the Major third
in its enharmonic context.80 But this was only at a later stage, when
the full complement of the enharmonic genus was established. With
Olympus’ invention, we are given a glimpse of the most primitive form
of the scale (descending): E – C – B – A – F – E.
Holding Aristoxenus to be the primary source for this account, West
faults him on the details, thus discrediting him as a reliable theorist. He
allows that Aristoxenus was right, however, in inferring that the enharmonic developed from a “single infix” into the semi-tone, an inference
that is not even voiced by Aristoxenus (or his sources) in this account.
Taking no notice of paramesē (B) and its role in Olympus’ melodic
experiments, West goes on to say:81
Aristoxenus went wrong, however, in supposing that Olympus arrived at
his e f a trichord by leaving out a note. On the contrary, the diatonic system
represents the filling in of the wide interval in the trichord by means of a
second infix.
West’s analysis of this passage most effectively challenges and depreciates Aristoxenus’ evidence on the history of the genera. For, as Aristoxenus
had stated explicitly, the diatonic in the distribution E F G A was the oldest of the genera. That being the case, its “second infix,” so-called by West,
must have been present and used by musicians long before the invention of
the enharmonic genus. In other words, no second infix was required.82
80
81
82
Harm. El. II, 39 (Da Rios, 49. 12–14).
West (note 78), p. 164.
On the reading of Aristoxenus’ evidence by Fr. Aug. Gevaert, La musique de
l’Antiquité, I, pp. 298–300, the earliest form of the enharmonic genus was that
of a transilient scale resulting from the omission of the diatonic lichanos (G):
“As for the enharmonic, its beginnings fall in an epoch that was already claimed
by history: Aristoxenus expressly confirms that it came last of all. His testimony
must be taken as veracious and must prevail over the contrary opinions which
were already current in antiquity.” As Gevaert goes on to explain, the primitive enharmonic was founded upon a rudimentary perfect system of tetrachords
(descending: E – C – B and A – F – E). These, when converted to a trichordal
We Are All Aristoxenians
81
In sum then, however willing Winnington-Ingram, Anderson,
West, and others have been to grant Aristoxenus importance for being
the earliest writer on music whose work has reached us at least in part,
they have, more often than not, seen more to censure than to praise
in his approach to the subject. At best, his theory has been judged to
be overly symmetrical and unrealistically homogeneous in its forms
and structures; at worst, it is considered to be too unscientific to offer
any real assistance to our understanding of the ancient art. The most
recent scholar to express these views is John Landels, who says:83
This [the acoustic theory of the Pythagoreans] is in contrast to the ‘musical’
school of thought, best represented by Aristoxenus, which held that the
notes were, so to speak, points with no magnitude, and that the intervals
between them were the measurable quantities. Members of this school pretended, by the use of fractions and additions and subtractions, that they
were making scientific measurements, but in fact they were merely judging
the “quantities” of the intervals by ear and by guesswork.
As is all too evident then, Aristoxenus has always provided his critics with a battle-ground for opposing and contradictory views. On the
one side, that, for example, of Comotti, Aristoxenus is considered to
have been too involved with Pythagorean mathematics and mathematical principles to notice, as did Plato and Aristotle before him, the
effects of music on the soul. On the other side, that of Mountford,
Winnington-Ingram, Landels, et al., Aristoxenus is seen to be fundamentally unscientific and unreliable precisely because he relied solely
on the perception of the ear (aisthēsis) while ignoring the Pythagorean
mathematical principles secured by reason (logos). With the possible
exception of Comotti, Aristoxenus’ critics seem to have agreed on one
thing: mathematics has the final word in all things musical, because,
conjunctive system in the Dorian Mode (D C B♭ A F E), “were decomposed into
two intervals only: a major third [A – F] and a semitone [B♭ – A], the wholetone [A – B] now lost in the conjunction [B♭ – A]” (p. 300). The resulting scale
was (descending): D B♭ A F E. At this stage in the formation of the enharmonic
genus, the “infix” into the semi-tone had not as yet been made. This innovation
was probably introduced later by the aulos-virtuoso, Polymnastos (p. 300).
83 Landels, Music in Ancient Greece and Rome, p. 132.
82
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
as the Pythagoreans had so successfully demonstrated, quantity exists
in music, and where there is quantity, there is number. To his critics,
Aristoxenus’ hostility toward the views of the Pythagoreans, and his
insistence on the irrelevance of mathematics to music ultimately led
him into difficulties from which he could never extricate himself.84 But
it was not for this alone that he was condemned to the near-total obscurity in which we find him today. It was because his theory, in contrast
to that of the Pythagoreans, had applications to one subject only: the
nature, or physis, of music.85 In comparison to Aristoxenus, who never
looked beyond music and its laws, Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans,
universalized the laws that they had derived from the lengths of the
lyre-strings so as to include the whole cosmos and all of human life.
Aristoxenus’ theory, derived as it was from the ear’s knowledge and
from musical intelligence (dianoia), could never extend beyond music
and its own laws.
Meibom’s assessment in 1652 of Aristoxenus’ status in the history of
Western culture is, therefore, almost as true today as it was then. For if
Aristoxenus is to be found anywhere at all, it will not be in bookstores
or in the more-frequented sections of public libraries; instead, he can be
discovered only in the narrow confines of academic libraries, “neglected
by all because of his having touched upon almost the highest limit of his
science.”86 Pythagoras, however, will be found almost everywhere. This is
a strange and ironic fate for “The Musician” of antiquity, the author of 453
separate works, some twenty or more of which were devoted to every aspect
84
85
86
Barker (note 52), 10, finds Aristoxenus’ understanding of the nature of music
and the principles to which it leads to be innovative and fruitful. Attractive as
it may be, however, Aristoxenus’ approach leads to problems; as Barker says,
“. . . it generated difficulties from which I am not sure that he can disentangle
himself.” The difficulties to which Barker calls our attention in this important
article are examined in Chapter 5.
The nature, or physis, of music, as treated by Aristoxenus, has nothing to do
with the physics or acoustical theory of sound. It has reference, rather, to the
natural movement and the functional principles according to which musical
pitches are ordered in melody. On Aristoxenus’ conception, melody has within
it both a principle of movement and an initiator of movement (the human
voice), the final form of which is governed by musical intelligence (dianoia).
See note 7.
We Are All Aristoxenians
83
of music.87 But despite the penetrating and innovative treatment of music
that emerges from his extant writings, Aristoxenus’ name is seldom to be
found in even the most comprehensive and sophisticated studies of the subject written in this century. On the rare occasions in which he is mentioned
at all, he is usually given only a passing reference or, at times, only a nodding acknowledgment from a secondary source. Jamie James, for example,
mentions Aristoxenus twice in The Music of the Spheres, his first citation coming by way of Leibniz, his second from Oliver Strunk.88 Although he is not
mentioned even to this extent in the writings of numerous specialists in
music, Aristoxenus’ principles and analyses are mirrored, almost uncannily
so at times, in their treatment of the subject. He comes vividly to life, for
example, in the words of Ernest Ansermet, a musician whose credentials
cannot be challenged. Thus, where Aristoxenus was roundly criticized for
his method of tuning by consonances,89 Ansermet not only details that same
method of tuning, together with the musical notation, but even sees in it
the very foundation of tonality in Western music. He credits the method
simply to “die griechischen Musiker” and says of it:90
87
We know from numerous sources, such as Plutarch, Philodemus, Athenaeus,
Porphyry, and others, that Aristoxenus wrote on the technical, the practical,
and the performing aspects of music, the dance, and instrumental practices.
Of all the works he wrote, only portions of his Harmonic Elements (note 20) and
fragments from the second book of his Rhythmic Elements are extant. The latter
have been translated by Barker, II, pp. 185–89. The texts have been edited,
with a translation and commentary, by Lionel Pearson, Aristoxenus: Elementa
Rhythmica. Among the lost works of Aristoxenus to which our authorities
refer are: On Composition, On Hearing Music, On the Unit of Time, On Instruments,
On Auloi, On the Boring of Auloi, On Choruses, On Dance in Tragedy, On Auloi
Performers, for which, see Louis Laloy, Aristoxène de Tarente, pp. 16–17; Wehrli,
Frs. 69–94. Of all his works on music, the loss of two in particular is cruelly
felt: On Music, which, judging from the fragments that have come down, must
have contained much valuable information on the practices of Aristoxenus’ own
musical tradition; On Keys (Tonoi), this being one of the most disputed of all the
topics discussed by scholars in the field. The definitive work is that of Otto J.
Gombosi, Tonarten und Stimmungen der Antiken Musik. The subject is reviewed
by André Barbera, “Greece,” New Harvard Dictionary of Music, 346–57.
88 James, The Music of the Spheres, p. 78; p. 90.
89 See note 66.
90 Ernst Ansermet, Die Grundlagen der Musik in menschlichen Bewusstsein,
pp. 676–77.
84
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Without knowing it, the Greek musicians had already prepared the way
through their fifth-fourth tuning of the lyre to the beginning of a world
of key positions, which is based on a fifth-fourth relationship, that is, of a
world of key positions stemming from their inner relations to one another
(B stands in an inner relation to A through the middle member E; the relation of the ascending fourth and the descending fifth is the inner, genetic
foundation of the outer relation B–A).
Aristoxenian thought permeates the works of countless musicians
and musicologists in places and in situations too numerous to mention.
On the question of notation, for example, Robin Maconie might well
have been consulting Aristoxenus, for his estimation of the role of notation in music is identical to that of Aristoxenus:91
And yet, despite its [notation’s] remarkable intellectual virtues, the inadequacies of notation are obvious enough. Ask any ethnomusicologist about
the problems of transcribing recorded folk music, and among the first to
spring to mind is the inherent impossibilities of accommodating standard
notation to the more elusive qualities of musical expression among oral
cultures, including ambiguous pitches and characteristic instabilities of
intonation.
One has only to ask Aristoxenus, who states in the second book of his
Harmonic Elements that notation, like the study of meter, should be treated
as a separate science for the very reasons mentioned by Maconie: notation
cannot capture the essence of a melody. As Aristoxenus puts it:92
It is not necessary that one who has written down a Phrygian melody know
exactly what a Phrygian melody is. Clearly then, notation should not be the
end-all of our aforementioned science.
And when Robert Jourdain speaks of the demands made by music on
the listener, he, too, is of a mind with Aristoxenus. Thus, Jourdain:93
91
92
93
Maconie, The Concept of Music, p. 114. Cf. E. Pöhlmann and M. L. West, who, in their
Preface to Documents of Ancient Greek Music, speak of Aristoxenus’ condemnation of
notation as a “banausic skill, too defective to form part of serious musicology.”
Harm. El, II. 39 (Da Rios, 49, 12–16).
Jourdain, Music, the Brain, and Ecstasy, p. 135.
We Are All Aristoxenians
85
Form makes itself known through a kind of intellectual discovery that
demands a well-developed musical memory for sustaining musical fragments over long periods.
Aristoxenus adds importantly to what Jourdain says, with these
details:94
It is clear that understanding melodies as they are being played is to follow
with both the ear and the intellect things that are happening in their every
distinction; for melody, just as the other parts of music, consists in a coming to
be (genesis). The understanding of music comes from these two faculties: perception and memory. For we must perceive what is happening, and remember
what has happened. There is no other way to follow the events in music.
To make the interesting point that composers themselves often cannot account for the source of their own inspiration, Peter Kivy cites
Socrates’ insight in the Ion to this effect:95
For I think Socrates’ insight in the Ion still stands. The creator may draw
from he knows not where – the gods, if you like, or the depths of the
unconscious, if you prefer . . .
Kivy might have cited Aristoxenus on this point to even greater effect.
For whereas Socrates in the Ion sees poets as seers or Bacchanals who compose
in a state of inspiration in which they are “possessed” by a higher power,
Aristoxenus places the composition of music on a much higher plane. For
him, the composition of music is an intellectual activity (synesis) on a par
with phua or native genius that “is hidden deep within the soul.”96
Once prominent in antiquity as “The Musician,” Aristoxenus’ claim
to a minor place in intellectual history derives today primarily from his
nonmusical writings. These include works on history, education, mathematics, and Pythagorean studies. Of his historical works, those that
94
95
96
Harm. El. II. 38 (Da Rios, 48. 11–18).
Kivy, Music Alone, p. 119.
Harm. El. II. 41 (Da Rios, 51. 16). Aristoxenus may have been making a conscious
reference here to Heraclitus’ observation on the unfathomable depths of the soul
(Vors. B22; Fr. 45): “Though you were to travel every road, you would not discover
the limits of the soul; so deep is the logos it contains.” Cf. Albert Cook, Myth and
Language, pp. 86–87 on the link between the logos and the soul.
86
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
have won him some little celebrity are biographies, these constituting
a new literary genre that he and his colleague at Aristotle’s Lyceum,
Dicaearchus, inaugurated. Of the five Lives whose titles have come
down to us, four were devoted to Pythagoras, Archytas, Socrates, and
Plato, the fifth being that of Telestes, presumably the dithyrambic poetmusician of Selinus. Thus today, where he is cited at all, as by Hellenists,
it is more for the evidence that he brings to Pythagorean studies than
for his contributions to philosophy and aesthetics, let alone to musical lore and theory. Most recently, he is mentioned as an authority on
the Pythagorean principles of procreation, the testimony offered in his
name never even once hinting at his greater authority in music.97
Yet, with Aristoxenus, we are not merely in the world of those
once-renowned musicians whom he notices – Lasus of Hermione, Epigonus
of Ambracia, Eratocles, or Agenor of Mitylene – all masters of the art of
music, the teachers and theorists of ancient Greek music;98 we are also among
the musicians of the world – performers and composers – for whom the
modes of music represent all the states of the human soul. The transmutation of these spiritual states into melodic expression is the work of musicians.
Aristoxenus, as will be argued here, by his orderly research into this work
of musicians, was the first to reveal the logical bases and the permanent elements that underlie the apparently limitless diversity and heterogeneity of
the musical phenomena. The instruments of his research were his ear (akoē),
his musical rationality (dianoia), and his musical intuition (synesis).
Aristoxenus did not begin his task by making hypotheses or inventing
principles according to which he sought to explain everything musical.
Instead, he based his research on the concepts of practicing musicians,
organic concepts that have been controlling the whole range of musical
utterance from the very beginning of our knowledge. On the strength
of these concepts, he was able to reveal those subtle links that bind the
music of all ages and cultures together and that make music intelligible
97
98
See Kathy L. Gaca, “The Reproductive Technology of the Pythagoreans,
Classical Philology 95 (2000), 113–32.
Aristoxenus mentions these, his predecessors, primarily to criticize them, at
times most scathingly. His reasons are analyzed instructively by Andrew Barker,
“`OI KALOUMENOI `ARMONIKOI: The Predecessors of Aristoxenus,”
PCPS 24 (1978), 1–21.
We Are All Aristoxenians
87
on its own terms. These links stand out in his theory as the universals of
music. They are mind-made – invented by the musically intuitive mind
but at the same time classifiable by the logic of musical rationality. They
possess the unchanging and eternal characteristics of all universals but,
as Aristoxenus was concerned to show, they are not incompatible with
the changing interests of musicians or the changing forms of music. In
consideration of these factors in Aristoxenus’ orientation to music, his
theory shows him to have been musically conscious to a degree attained
by no other ancient authority and by few of their modern counterparts.
Aristoxenus’ aim was to trace the active principle in music – that
strange, mysterious faculty which draws strength, color, and character from musical pitches – to disengage it and to mark the degree to
which it penetrates all utterances that are instinct with melody. He
began with a knowledge that consists of these factors: music moves in
its own space and time; its energy derives from the smallest of units;
its range is not simply one of a vertical pitch dimension but also one of
depth, the perspective of which may hinge on the function, or dynamis,
as he called it, of a single note. With all that in mind, he framed an
adaptive system, a collection of simple, germinal elements that interact
to generate subsequent bits of melody, these to be molded into a complex whole. Throughout this endeavor, Aristoxenus showed himself to
have been gifted enough to take the prodigious path of a true disciple
of Aristotle, the better to raise in the name of philosophy an immense
and opulently appointed edifice of musical knowledge. There he housed
those few principles into which all the forms of music could be accommodated, and all the particular sciences of music for which they set
the conditions: harmonic, rhythmic and metrical sciences, compositional, instrumental, and vocal sciences – in short, all those branches of
the theoretical, practical, and performing disciplines that are, he said,
“embraced by the general science that concerns itself with melody.”99
99
Harm. El. I. 1 (Da Rios, 5. 4–6).
3 The Discrete and the Continuous
At the recurring end
of the unending
T. S.Eliot, Little Gidding
one of the most perplexing musical questions familiar to
e veryone was raised early on by Aristoxenus in his Harmonic Elements:
What is it that makes one melody musical and another unmusical?1 The
1
88
From the time of Pythagoras to that of Aristoxenus, the ancient theorists saw
the particularity of this problem, but they approached it in terms of different
questions: What is there in the phenomena of music that makes for their objective coherence or intelligibility? What is there in the phenomena of music
that makes for their affective power? It is essentially the latter question that is
posed in Ps.-Aristotle Problems: “How is it that rhythms and melodies, which
are only sound, resemble moral characters, while flavors, colors, and scents do
not?” And Plato was in effect asking the former question when he observed
of melody in Laws 657B2: “If one could grasp what sort of thing constitutes
the correctness of melodies, one could confidently submit them to law and
order.” On this law-like inevitability in musical melody, Roger Scruton, The
Aesthetics of Music, p. 79, speaks in these Platonic terms: “This virtual causality is sometimes perceived as physical relations are perceived: namely, as
law-like and inevitable.” Aristoxenus goes even further; as he has it, the difference between a musical melody (emmelēs) and an unmusical one (ekmelēs) is not
simply a matter of law and order; it involves something far more fundamental
(Harm. El. I. 19; Da Rios. 24. 5–10): “For now, let me say in a general way that
although a well-attuned melody admits of many differences in its collocation of
intervals, nevertheless, there is a kind of attribute that will be asserted of every
well-attuned melody, an attribute that is one and the same for all, and is possessed of so great a power that with its removal, the attunement is destroyed.”
This crucial power is understood by Aristoxenus to be continuity (συνέχεια).
It assumes not only the proper or lawful succession of intervals, but also the
proper or musically rational analysis of intervals. For intervals, as Aristoxenus
defines them, are not simply the sizes of the spaces between notes; they are
The Discrete and the Continuous
89
full implications of his answer to this central question should become
clear by considering the way in which he dealt with more specific problems, in particular, with the more controversial ones. Of these problems, one of the most important concerns the proper analysis of the
concept of the continuum – the topology, as it were, of melody, and the
notion closely allied to it – that of infinity. The problems connected
with the continuum and with that of infinity arise in an early stage
in Aristoxenus’ reflections on two issues that pertain to melody: the
apparently unlimited possibilities available to the human voice of placing notes in continuing sequences on the line of pitch; the apparently
limitless possibilities granted to the human voice of subdividing the
distance between any two of these sequential pitches. These problems
reemerge at later and more subtle stages in Aristoxenus’ analysis about
discrete and continuous quantities and their relation to the continuum
of melody.
In the earliest stages of his education, Aristoxenus would have probably concerned himself with infinity, not on its own account, but as it
related to Pythagorean mathematical theory – a relation that, especially
in Pythagorean harmonics, was very close. Indeed, Aristoxenus’ early
training in Pythagorean mathematical theory would have brought him
into direct contact with two of the greatest problems related to infinity
that had occupied Greek mathematicians for centuries: the irrationality
in the length of the hypotenuse of the right-angled triangle and the irrationality in the magnitude of the whole-tone musical interval. For on the
division of the hypotenuse of the right-angled triangle and on that of the
whole-tone musical interval in the ratio 9:8, there is yielded the same
irrationality in the form of √2 – a number as productive of infinity as π,
the ratio of the diameter of the circle to its circumference.2 Archimedes
more properly determined by the functions (dynameis) of the notes delimiting them. Implicated in this crucial power is the continuum against which all
melodic changes occur.
2 See above, Ch. I, pp. 5–6. As the Pythagoreans discovered to their dismay, there
is no number which, when multiplied by itself, will yield √2. It is an irrational number, because it cannot be expressed as a ratio of whole numbers, as is
the case with the octave (2:1), the fourth (4:3), and the fifth (3:2). At the same
time, if converted into decimals, √2 is productive of infinity: 1.4142135. But
whereas √2 is a solution of the algebraic equation , x2 – 2 = 0 , π, which can
90
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
had attacked the problem of π by inscribing and circumscribing in the
circle a regular polygon of ninety-six sides, thereby demonstrating how
his method of reconciling the irreconcilable could be carried to any
degree of approximation. As Archimedes showed all too clearly, this is
all that any method of approximation can accomplish with the problem of π.3 Aristoxenus’ goal was much the same as that of Archimedes:
to arrive at a similarly effective kind of approximation for dealing with
the irrationality of the whole-tone musical interval. Succeeding in this
endeavor meant providing a degree of approximation that would answer
the practical needs of singers and instrumentalists. In order to prosecute
this goal, however, Aristoxenus had to find a way to deal with infinity,
not simply as it related to mathematical theory, but on its own account.
Aristoxenus was singularly well qualified for the undertaking.
Born about 360 b.c. in Tarentum in southern Italy, his life was almost
be rendered in decimals as 3.14159265358 to infinity, differs from √2 in that
it cannot be the root of an algebraic equation. This means that π is not only
irrational, it is also transcendental. On the transcendance of π, see Beckmann,
A History of π (Pi), pp. 166ff. In brief, π transcends infinity; √2 does not. As
Lavine, Understanding the Infinite, pp. 246–47, interestingly remarks: “We have
already seen that the infinite is nowhere to be found in reality, no matter what
experiences, observations, and knowledge are appealed to.” Perhaps it is in
music that we are experiencing what is not available to us in any other kind of
reality: namely, infinity. That is, the space of a whole-tone can be thought of as
infinite, since every point within its limits is as much a “center” as any other
point.
3 Archimedes’ method, sometimes referred to as “the method of exhaustion,”
is ascribed to Eudoxus (c. 408–c. 355 b.c.), but its foundation was laid by
earlier mathematicians of the Athenian school, in particular, by Hippocrates
of Chios (in Athens during the second half of the fifth century b.c.) and by
Menaechmus (?375–25 b.c.), a pupil of Eudoxus and a somewhat older contemporary of Aristoxenus. The method of exhaustion led Archimedes to an
exact result in squaring the parabola; but in the case of the circle, it led to successive approximations. By inscribing and circumscribing a regular polygon of
96 sides, Archimedes proved that π is less than 3–17 and greater than 310
–71. This
means that (3+10
–71) Diameter < Circumference <3 + –17 Diameter. The upper
limit is the Archimedean approximation π~22
–7 , or 3.1428571. For a detailed
account, see Dijksterhuis, Archimedes, pp. 222ff. See also Heath, A History of
Greek Mathematics, I, pp. 221–23, who traces the method back to Antiphon,
the Sophist and contemporary of Socrates.
The Discrete and the Continuous
91
coextensive with one of the most transforming periods in the history of
the ancient world – that of the campaigns and conquests of Alexander
the Great.4 Around the time that he was to begin his studies at the
Lyceum with Aristotle, Alexander was defeating the Persians in the battle of Gaugamela (331 b.c.) and Darius, king of the Persians, was fleeing
for his life. Of all these events there is no mention in the extant works
of Aristoxenus. He was turning his mind far away from the spectacle
of war and human misery to contemplate instead the mysteries of music
and the eternal world of ideas and beauty. In this, he was in total harmony with the most learned men associated with the city of his birth:
Philolaus (b. c. 470 b.c.), Lysis (fourth century b.c.), and Archytas (first
half of the fourth century b.c.), Pythagoreans all. For Tarentum was a
leading center of Pythagorean studies and activities, the city in Magna
Graecia where Pythagoras himself was said to have lived for a time long
before.5 Philolaus and Lysis had of course died long before Aristoxenus
4
Most of what we know about Aristoxenus’ life comes from the historical and
literary encyclopedia compiled at the end of the tenth century a.d. and known
today as Suda or Suidas (Fortress or Stronghold). The article on Aristoxenus,
consisting of about a dozen lines, is reproduced by Laloy, Aristoxène, pp. 1–2
and translated also, p. 2, n. 1. It is offered by Wehrli as Fr. 1 and also by Da
Rios, p. 95. It states the following: “Aristoxenus, the son of Mnesias, also called
Spintharus, a musician from Tarentum in Italy; after studying in Mantinea,
he became a philosopher. Having also devoted himself to music, he achieved
no small success. He was a student of his father and of Lamprus of Erythrae;
thereafter, he studied under Xenophilus the Pythagorean and, finally, under
Aristotle. After Aristotle died, he indulged in disrespectful language toward
him, because Aristotle chose Theophrastus to succeed him as head of the school,
even though he, Aristoxenus, had won a great reputation among the students
of Aristotle. He lived during the time of Alexander and his successors, so that
he is of the one hundred and eleventh Olympiad [c. 333 b.c.] and a contemporary of Dicaearchus of Messina. His works on music, philosophy, history and
every aspect of culture come to 453 books.” Additional facts about Aristoxenus
come from the writings of Athenaeus, Porphyry, Ptolemy, Vitruvius, Boethius,
and many others. Cf. Da Rios Testimonia, pp. 95ff.
5 We owe a charming story about Pythagoras in Tarentum to the Neoplatonist philosopher from Syria, Iamblichus (c. 250–c. 325 a.d.) For it was here in Tarentum
that Pythagoras, as Iamblichus has it, demonstrated his Orpheus-like dominion
over animals. One day, Pythagoras encountered a bean-eating cow in the pastures
around Tarentum. When he suggested to the cowherd that he instruct his cow to
92
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
was born, but Archytas may quite possibly have been known personally
to Aristoxenus, as he was a close friend of Aristoxenus’ father.
Aristoxenus’ first teacher in philosophy, mathematics, and music
was in fact his father, Spintharus, a renowned musician, whose circle of
friends included the celebrated musicians Damon (fl. c. 430 b.c.) and
Philoxenus (c. 435–c. 380–79 b.c.), as well as the cultivated Boeotian
general Epaminondas (d. 362 b.c.) and even Socrates (469–399 b.c.). In
due course, Aristoxenus was sent for advanced study to a certain Lamprus
of Erythrae, whose name has come down to us only because he had once
taught the son of Spintharus. Sometime thereafter, Aristoxenus progressed to Mantinea, an outstanding center for the serious cultivation of
music, a city where his welcome reception would have been guaranteed
by Spintharus’ association with Epaminondas, its Theban liberator.
In Mantinea, everyone was, it seems, either a professional musician or,
at the very least, a cultivated and knowledgeable listener. The city actually
required that every young man up to the age of twenty be well trained in
all aspects of music. Indeed, no city could have been more congenial to
the tastes and inclinations of the young Aristoxenus, for it was here that
the artistic excellence of ages past was being preserved with a diligence
matched only by that of Aristoxenus himself. The Mantineans’ humility
toward the composers of the past – toward Pindar, Terpander, Alcman,
and Tyrtaeus – was acknowledged throughout the world of music. Their
conservatism was vigorously upheld by Aristoxenus, whose own devotion toward time-honored traditions and techniques had been instilled
in him since early childhood. In Tarentum, he had had Spintharus to
form his tastes and set his standards of excellence; here in Mantinea, he
was to perfect his skills under the guidance of music’s master-teachers.6
A city of the plain, Mantinea was the Curtis Institute of its day.
6
give up eating beans, the cowherd laughed aloud, observing that he did not speak
cow language. Pythagoras thereupon took the cow aside and whispered into its
ear for a while. The cow responded by giving up beans forever after, and the citizens erected a statue of a cow in the town square to commemorate the miracle.
See Iamblichus De vita Pyth. 13. 61–62 (Deubner, 33. 8–21).
Philodemus (for whom, see Chapter 1, note 72) thus speaks of the people of
Mantinea, Lacedaemon, and Pellana as being leaders in the field of music and
known for their diligent and intense practice of the arts (Kemke, 10. 19).
And Ps-Plutarch confirms him in speaking of the conservative practices of
The Discrete and the Continuous
93
When Aristoxenus marveled at the wondrous ordering in music, he had
one thing in mind: melody. He had no patience, therefore, with composers like Timotheus, Philoxenus, and Krexus – the avant-garde of the fifth
century b.c. – who, in his view, had introduced their own idiosyncratic
ideas into the ancient art solely for the sake of newness. To Aristoxenus,
their technical innovations were more for self-proclamation than for genuine musical expression.7 When melody was at issue, he bound himself to
the practices of such composers, now ancient in his own day, as Alcman
(7th century b.c.) and Stesichorus (c. 632–c. 556 b.c.). In his words:8
There is an innovation of the Alcman and Stesichorean type; indeed, these
practices do not depart from the beautiful. But Krexus and Timotheus and
7
8
“the Lacedaemonians and Mantineans and Pellanians, who selected only one
mode or, at most, only a few modes which they believed would contribute
to the harmonization of upright characters, this being the music which they
practiced” (De Musica, ch. 32; Ziegler-Pohlenz, 26. 24–27). Cf. Anderson,
Ethos, p. 153. Aristoxenus’ community of spirit with the Mantineans is noted
by Lasserre, Plutarque, p. 32: “The excellent reputation won by Aristoxenus
among the exemplary practices of the Mantineans, to whom he devoted a book,
is certainly inseparable from their attachment to musical institutions reputed
to be as ancient as those of the Lacedaemonians.”
Timotheus is the most famous representative of this revolutionary school
of music. His dates – c. 450–360 b.c. – make him a contemporary of
Aristophanes. He is known for having increased the number of strings on the
cithara to eleven and for having been a virtuoso as well as a prolific composer.
According to Ps.-Plutarch De Musica, ch. 30 (Ziegler-Pohlenz, 25. 3), the
comic poet, Pherecrates, in his now lost play, Cheiron, speaks of Timotheus’
melodic innovations as “deviations in the form of ant-tracks,” an opinion no
doubt shared by Aristoxenus himself. Cf. Comotti, pp. 35–37. Philoxenus
(c. 435 – c. 380–379 b.c.), a famed composer of dithyrambs, is cited frequently in Ps.-Plutarch De Musica for his originality and ornamental style.
And Athenaus XIV. 643D–E has the comic poet, Antiphanes, speaking of
Philoxenus in these none-too-measured terms: “He was a god among men,
since he truly knew music.” Krexus (c. 450–400 b.c.), also famous as a composer of dithyrambs, introduced something remarkable for his time: an accompaniment on the cithara using notes that differed from those of the song itself.
Traditionally, the accompaniment on the cithara doubled in unison the notes
of the vocal melody. In sum, then, Aristoxenus was deploring musical practices
that were being introduced roughly a hundred years before his time.
Ps.-Plutarch De Musica, ch. 12 (Ziegler–Pohlenz, 10.19–11.2).
94
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Philoxenus and the composers of that era have become more vulgar and
lovers of novelty in their pursuit of what is now called a prize-winning
and crowd-pleasing style. For it turns out that the simple and noble type
of music based upon a small number of strings has become completely
antiquated.
In this approach to the classical art of music. Aristoxenus, like the
conservative Mantineans, had a special kind of moral purity and loftiness of purpose, which is most impressive. He was consistently sincere,
even though he was all too often shrill, censorious, and impatient; but,
above all, he was invariably concerned to tell the reader as simply as he
could what he felt to be more important than all else: melody. When,
therefore, he asked his like-minded colleagues, few in number as they
might be, “to go off by ourselves and remember what sort of art music
used to be,” he can easily be imagined discussing the melodies of old
with the musicians of Mantinea.9
One of these, a certain Telesias of Thebes, who had received an exemplary training in music, tried to break away from established melodic
norms and compose in the style of Philoxenus and Timotheus, with this
result:10
[Aristoxenus] says that it befell Telesias of Thebes to have been trained
when he was still a child in the finest kind of music and to have studied the
works of the most highly-esteemed composers, among whom were Pindar,
Dionysius of Thebes, Lamprus and Pratinas and other masters of lyric and
instrumental composition.
Aristoxenus goes on to relate that, in the course of time, Telesias
became so captivated by the theatrical music being written by such
composers as Philoxenus and Timotheus that he made every effort to
master its techniques himself. But when he actually tried to compose
9
10
Athenaeus Deipnosophists xiv a–b = Fr. 124 Wehrli.
Ps.-Plutarch De Musica, ch. 31 (Ziegler–Pohlenz, 25. 16–21) = Fr. 76 Wehrli.
Commenting on this passage, Wehrli points out, p. 71, that the Telesias mentioned in this citation is otherwise unknown; but Dionysius of Thebes was the
teacher of that most cultivated military man, Epaminondas. Cf. West, Ancient
Greek Music, p. 371.
The Discrete and the Continuous
95
in the Philoxenian style, he failed utterly. The reason for this lay in his
early training: he had been so firmly grounded in the classical art as
practiced by Pindar, Lamprus, Pratinas, and others that he could not
compose vulgar and theatrical melodies even when he tried.
The metaphysics of Aristoxenus began in Mantinea, where no one
seems ever to have feared such a thing as musical obsolescence. His
success there as a practicing musician was considerable, but from his
earliest days he felt himself equally drawn to the study of philosophy.
And, as it came fruitfully to pass, it was philosophy that would eventually provide him with a way to deal with the nonmathematical properties of music’s nature.11 He left Mantea, then, for Athens, his original
intention being to master Pythagorean mathematical theory down to its
most refined details; to this end, he sought out the leading Pythagorean
expert of the day: Xenophilus the Chalcidean of Thrace, who, like
many other celebrated Pythagoreans, had made his home in Athens.12
Traveling from Mantinea to Athens, Aristoxenus made an important
stop in Corinth, where he became acquainted with the exiled tyrant
11
12
Among those properties that mathematics cannot represent are the musically
logical ordering of melodic intervals, those rules of continuity that are, as it
were, the counterpart of a linguistic grammar. In her Language, Music, and Mind,
Diana Raffman quotes F. Lehrdahl and R. Jackendoff, A Generative Grammar
of Tonal Music, to this effect (p. 18): “Like its linguistic counterpart, the musical grammar (the “M-grammar”) models an underlying competence. That is, it
models “the largely unconscious knowledge (the ‘musical intuition’) that the
listener brings to his hearing – a knowledge that enables him to organize and
make coherent the surface patterns of pitch, attack, duration, intensity, timbre,
and so forth.” It is this knowledge, this innate competence, that Aristoxenus
calls “the synesis of music,” or musical intuition. Mathematics is defeated by its
range of understanding. Cf. Levin, “Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory,” 213–14.
Xenophilus is so obscure a figure today that his name is not to be found in even
the most specialized works on Pythagoreanism. Citing Aristoxenus, Lucian
(c. 120 a.d.), the satirist, wrote some five hundred years after Xenophilus in
his work on old age (De longaevis 18 = Fr. 20a Wehrli): “Xenophilus, the musician, as Aristoxenus says, devoted himself to the philosophy of Pythagoras and
lived past one hundred and five years.” According to Diogenes Laertius VIII.
46, Xenophilus was among the last of the Pythagoreans whom Aristoxenus
knew. They were themselves pupils of Philolaus and Eurytus of Tarentum,
Aristoxenus’ hometown.
96
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of Sicily, Dionysius the Younger, who had now become a teacher of
grammar. This would have been some time around 340 b.c., some three
years or so after Dionysius had surrendered his dominion to Timoleon
and was granted asylum in Corinth. To judge from Aristoxenus’ account
of this meeting, Dionysius, now given to recalling incidents from his
former days of power, found in Aristoxenus an avid listener, one who
used the occasion to record whatever bore especially upon his interest in
Pythagoreanism. Just as he had absorbed many anecdotes as a boy from
his father, Spintharus, so now he took down from Dionysius the celebrated story of the model Pythagorean friends, Damon and Phintias,
which he later incorporated into his Life of Pythagoras.13
At this point in Aristoxenus’ career, there could have been no better
master living than Xenophilus who, in addition to being a most erudite
Pythagorean scholar, was also a musician. Aristoxenus tells us this of
Xenophilus:14 “Xenophilus, the musician, lived in Athens until past the
age of 105, having devoted himself to the philosophy of Pythagoras.”
It was from Xenophilus, therefore, that Aristoxenus, already initiated
into the fundamentals of Pythagorean harmonics, would have learned how
inextricable were the bonds between harmonics and arithmetic, geometry,
cosmology, and astronomy. For the Pythagoreans believed that harmonics
was the medium through which the laws of number become applicable to
the whole physical universe. That Xenophilus also exemplified the best to
which the human spirit can aspire induced Aristoxenus to say in remembrance of him:15 “He lived exempt from all human disadvantage and died
in the glorious supremacy of his consummate erudition.”
His mind invincible to the end, Xenophilus had become a friend as
well as a master to Aristoxenus, despite his being more than sixty years
older than Aristoxenus. To his credit, Aristoxenus evidently treated a
man’s age as a mediator rather than as a barrier between himself and the
13
14
15
Much of what Aristoxenus wrote concerning his visit to Corinth has found
its way into Iamblichus De vita Pyth. 233–37 (Deubner, 125. 18–127.11).
Cf. Frs. 26–32 Wehrli.
See note 12.
Fr. 20b Wehrli = Valerius Maximus VIII. 13. Ext. 3: “ut ait Aristoxenus
musicus, omnis humani incommodi expers in summo perfectissimae doctrinae
splendore exstinctus est.”
The Discrete and the Continuous
97
accumulated knowledge he was seeking. And Xenophilus could not but
bring him all the closer by his years to the source of this knowledge:
Pythagoras. The repository of wisdom that the years of Xenophilus represented to Aristoxenus must have rewarded both of them well with an
age-proof friendship.
Aristoxenus’ last teacher was Aristotle. He entered Aristotle’s school,
the Lyceum, when he was probably in his late thirties and remained
there until Aristotle was forced by his political enemies to withdraw to
Chalcis, where he died in 322 b.c.16 Here at the Lyceum, where lay the
grove sacred to Apollo and the Muses, Aristoxenus walked up and down
every morning in the loggie with Aristotle and his other pupils discussing the most profound questions of philosophy and logic. Afternoons
and evenings were devoted to lectures on less esoteric subjects to which
the general public was invited. Aristoxenus offers us a rare glimpse into
one of these lectures – the exoteric or popular type – in which he tells
us what Aristotle had to say about a lecture on the Good given by his
master, Plato, at the Academy:17
It is perhaps better to go through what kind of study this is beforehand, so
that, understanding in advance the road, as it were, which we must travel,
we may proceed more easily by recognizing what part of it we are at and by
not getting unawaredly a misconception of the plan of study. As Aristotle
used always to relate, such was what befell most of those who listened to
Plato’s lecture on the Good. For, he said, they came, each expecting to find
out some one of those things that people think good, such as wealth, health,
strength – in general, some kind of wonderful happiness. But when the
discourse was manifestly concerned with mathematics and numbers and
16
17
The biography of Aristotle (384–22 b.c.) by Diogenes Laertius V is our main
authority for his life. According to Diogenes, a charge of impiety was brought
against Aristotle on the basis of a hymn and an epitaph that he wrote on
Hermeias, a former fellow-student of his at the Academy. Both the hymn and
the epitaph are reproduced by Diogenes; neither of them betrays any sign of
impiety, but only admiration for the courage of Hermeias who had fought
against the Persians. More likely, it was the surge of anti-Macedonian feeling
after the death of Alexander that provided the Athenians with the real reason
for forcing Aristotle to leave.
Harm. El. II. 30–31 (Da Rios, 39.4–40.4).
98
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
geometry and astronomy and the end result was that the Good is One, it
seemed to them, I think, to be quite contrary to their expectations; some
of them either derided the subject matter, while others found fault with it.
Aristotle’s point in telling this story was not lost on Aristoxenus: in
order to discover the principles and natural divisions of any science –
one has first to define its province. In applying Aristotle’s dictum to
his own concerns – the science of Harmonics – Aristoxenus defined
its province as Melody. From the facts of melody and melody alone,
Aristoxenus was able, therefore, to discover the principles and natural
divisions of harmonic science.18
Listening to Aristotle’s advanced discourses – the acroamatic – as
well as the more popular ones – the exoteric – Aristoxenus found the
master-influence of his life. In the years he spent at the Lyceum, he was
numbered among a group of gifted men who were united by a common
view – that articulated by Aristotle: the goal of the state must be to
produce men of the highest cultivation, men who would combine a love
of learning and of the arts with a respect for law, “equality according to
proportion,” and virtue. At the same time, each member of this select
company was encouraged to pursue his own individual goals with what
must have been a splendid independence. It was during these years,
then, that Aristoxenus developed his theory of music to a point far
beyond what any musician had theretofore conceived of. He seems also
to have lectured occasionally – as Aristotle’s most outstanding pupils
were invited to do – on the aspects of music that were to form the basis
of his most important works. One such lecture was apparently of the
advanced, or acroamatic, type, for like Aristotle’s course of lectures on
Physics called Physikē Akroasis, it was called Mousikē Akroasis.
18
Melody, as Aristoxenus says in the opening lines of his treatise, comprehends
numerous types of study, Harmonics being only one of them; the other types
that pertain to melody are not defined by him but must be inferred from the
treatise itself. In his words (Harm. El. I . 1; Da Rios, 5. 4–7): “The study of
melody is a multifarious one and is divided into numerous types, of which the
one called Harmonic must be considered first in rank and having an elemental function.” The question raised by scholars is: What are the other studies of
melody besides Harmonic? These, the other studies pertaining to melody, are
the focus of the chapters to follow.
The Discrete and the Continuous
99
In time, Aristoxenus won a great reputation for being a thinker
among thinkers, prodigious scholars all. They came to be called the
Peripatetics from the fact that they would walk with Aristotle, listening
and learning, discoursing and speculating, whether in he covered stoa, the
peripatos, or among the Lyceum’s groves.19 To a man, these Peripatetics
were polymaths of dazzling accomplishments, men to whom philosophy was a way of life. These were some of Aristoxenus’ colleagues:
Clearchus of Cyprus, who wrote on ways of living (bioi), on zoology
and mysticism, as well as an encomium to Plato, erotica and paradoxes;
Eudemus of Rhodes, who wrote on logic and rhetoric, as well as on theology, astronomy, geometry, and on Aristotle’s Physics; Dicaearchus of
Messana, who was much admired by Eratosthenes, Plutarch, Josephus,
and Cicero, who wrote a history of culture, numerous biographies, and
a geography of the known world. He also wrote on the constitution of
various cities, a dialogue on the soul, works on Homer, and on competitions in music and poetry; Demetrius of Phalerum, who wrote on history, literary criticism, and rhetoric. He also wrote fables and proverbs;
Meno, who wrote compendia of ancient medicine; Phaenius of Eresus,
a valuable source for Plutarch and author of works on tyranny. And
then there was Theophrastus, also of Eresus, the most renowned of all
the Peripatetic pupils of Aristotle. Unlike Aristoxenus, whose father
was a distinguished musician and scholar, Theophrastus was of humble
descent, his father having been a fuller, or what we would call today a
dry cleaner. Despite what disadvantages he may have suffered as a youth
on that account, Theophrastus’ abilities as a writer, scholar, speaker, and
teacher came to be so valued, not only by his colleagues at the Lyceum
but also by the Athenian public at large, that as many as two thousand
people were said to have attended his lectures. His name was originally
Tyrtamus, but in recognition of the “divine gracefulness of his style,”
19
See Ross, Aristotle, p. 5. The image of Aristotle discoursing with his prodigious
students in the groves of the Lyceum brings to mind what Victor Hugo said
in his Oration on Voltaire: “. . . great men rarely come alone: large trees seem
larger when they dominate a forest; there they are at home. There was a forest
of minds around Voltaire; that forest was the eighteenth century. Among those
minds were summits.” Among his students, Aristotle may have been the summit; but he was not the only tall tree in the Lyceum.
100
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Aristotle renamed him Theophrastus. When it came to selecting his
successor to head the Lyceum, it was Theophrastus whom Aristotle designated in his will for this signal honor.20
Like Aristoxenus, Theophrastus wrote an enormous number of
works, all of which were said to have abounded in excellence of every
kind. Judging from the titles that have come down to us, Theophrastus’
intellectual range seems to have had no limits. He was an authority on
plants, animals, human nature, the law, politics, mathematics, physics, precious stones, meteorology, and much more. Nor was that all.
Theophrastus was the only Peripatetic, aside from Aristoxenus, to have
written on music. Of his works in this area – On Music in two volumes, and On the Musicians – only a few pages from the first-named
work have survived.21 Enough remains, however, to show that he and
his colleague, Aristoxenus, though born of Aristotle, as two branches
of a common trunk, disagreed so fundamentally from each other that
they must have spent their days at the Lyceum in perpetual discord. On
one thing only were they in full agreement: Pythagorean mathematical
theory could never succeed in accounting for the perceived properties of
music.22 When it came, however, to defining the precise nature of these
20
21
22
Aristotle’s relationship with Theophrastus was long-lived and profound.
Theophrastus’ influence on Aristotle in scientific matters especially was so
great that some scholars, such as Werner Jaeger and Joseph Zürcher, have gone
so far as to attribute to Theophrastus many of the writings of Aristotle himself.
See Grene, A Portrait of Aristotle, pp. 28–29. As reported by Diogenes Laertius,
Theophrastus was a man of remarkable intelligence; industrious and diligent,
he was always fond of discussion and always ready to do a kindness. His disciples seemed to have adored him and kept alive many of his pithy sayings, one
of the nicest being: “The re-reading of one’s writings makes for revisions. The
present generation no longer puts up with delay and is altogether negligent.”
These have been preserved by Porphyry in his Commentary on Ptolemy’s
Harmonics (Düring, 61.16–65.15). They have been translated by Barker, II,
pp. 111–118.
Thus Lippman, Musical Thought in Ancient Greece, p. 161: “Common to the
theories of vibration and velocity is the explanation of pitch as basically numerical, and in taking issue with this conception, Theophrastus joined Aristoxenus
in a rejection of Pythagoreanism that is much more radical than that of their
teacher, for in spite of his revision of the status of number, Aristotle made use
of it in his own way to account for the phenomena of music.”
The Discrete and the Continuous
101
properties, Theophrastus and Aristoxenus stood worlds apart from each
other. Theophrastus approached the problem as a philosopher of nature
or, in the ancient sense, as a physicist; Aristoxenus’ approach was solely
that of a musician.
According to Theophrastus, “The nature of music is one.”23 This
singleness or oneness of music seems, on Theophrastus’ analysis, to
be a kind of circumambient stuff wherein the high and low pitches of
music are present, but not limited or made distinct by any intervening
intervals. Musical pitches seem simply to exist as a plurality of distinct things in a single mixture in which they are all together and from
which they are somehow separated out. As Theophrastus has it then,
pitch is all in all; it is in fact that without which sound itself cannot be
said to exist. At the same time, he is at pains to argue that sound and,
hence, pitch, has nothing to do with quantity, since, as far as the ear is
concerned, quantity is a wholly irrelevant factor:24
But if it is as notes that high and low ones differ from one another, we shall
no longer have any need of quantity: for their own intrinsic difference will
be sufficient by itself for the generation of melodies, and knowledge of the
difference will be possible. For the differences will no longer exist in accordance with the quantities, but in accordance with the quality peculiar to
the sounds, as is the case with colors.
Theophrastus apparently meant by this statement that the ear does
not hear the quantitative causes of pitch differences – frequency of
vibration or plurality of impacts on the air; the ear registers only the
effects of such causes – the pitch differences themselves. And these
pitch differences are sufficient in themselves for the generation of
23
24
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonica of Ptolemy (Düring, 65. 14–15).
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonica of Ptolemy (Düring, 62.21–25, translated by Barker, II, p. 113. As Barker II, p. 113, n. 12 explains, “His
[sc. Theophrastus’] claim, summarily, is that nothing can be a note, or even
a sound, without having a pitch. Hence, if the quantitative aspect were taken
away, then on this hypothesis what was left would not be a sound at all, no
matter what other attributes it had. . . . Sound is not a pitchless material on
which pitch, in the guise of some ‘quantity’, can be imposed – a sound must
have some pitch in virtue of being a sound.”
102
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
melodies. The next question would be: What is the nature of that
special class of musical pitches which the mind intuits to be melodious? Theophrastus did not address this problem; instead, he continued trying to prove by one argument after another that quantity
is an irrelevant factor in the production of melody. Paradoxically, the
harder he tried to prove this point, the more deeply and inextricably
he involved himself in quantitative analysis. He began by interpreting
pitch in terms of human physiology; then he proceeded to interpret
pitch in terms of musical instruments; and when he failed to find a
positive basis for the irrelevance of quantity, we see him reduced ultimately to a psychological explanation for the production of melody.
His physiological analysis, as applied to the wind-pipe of the singing
voice, almost immediately demanded certain terms of quantity: longer,
shorter, wider, narrower:25
This is clear from the force exerted when people sing. For just as they need
a certain power in order to give out a high sound, so do they also in order
to utter a low one. In the one case they draw in the ribs and stretch out the
windpipe, narrowing them by force; in the other they widen the wind-pipe,
which is why they make the throat shorter, since the width contracts the
length.
Turning to musical instruments, Theophrastus was led into the same
cul-de-sac: the relevance of quantity. The quantitative terms in this case
are “shorter,” “longer,” “thicker,” “thinner”:26
In auloi, in fact, the case is even clearer; for a high note requires less labor,
since it arises from the holes that are higher up, while a low note demands
greater force, if the breath is impelled through the whole [pipe], so that
however much length is added, there is added the same amount of strength
in the breath. In strings it is clear that there is equality in the two cases:
for by whatever amount the tension of the thinner is tighter, by the same
amount the one that seems slacker is thicker.
25
26
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonica of Ptolemy (Düring, 63.1–6), trans.
Barker.
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonica of Ptolemy (Düring, 63.6–14), trans.
Barker, II , p. 114.
The Discrete and the Continuous
103
Whereas he insisted that the apprehension of pitch differences is
based on qualitative factors, Theophrastus ended up framing his explanation of these factors on the laws of quantity in the production of
pitch. It is this that makes his inquiry so hard to follow. Lippman,
Musical Thought in Ancient Greece, has put the case in this way:27
Theophrastus does recognize special laws of quantity in tone, but the discussion of these, based as it is on a sensitive but qualitative science, constitutes a section of his inquiry that is quite difficult to comprehend.
Theophrastus’ psychological explanation of melodic production is
somewhat easier to follow, since it accords so well with the manifest
conclusions of many modern musicologists, especially those who assert
that music is the language of the soul:28
For the movement productive of melody, when it occurs in the soul, is very
accurate, when it [the soul] wishes to express it [the movement] with the
voice. It [the soul] turns it [the voice], and turns it just as it wishes, to the
extent that it is able to turn that which is non-rational.
Up to a certain point, then, Theophrastus is plain enough. The
singing voice and that of musical instruments produce various pitches
that can be organized into melodies. Such melodies derive, he argues,
not from mathematical factors, but from the intrinsic qualities of musical pitches themselves. The musical form that such melodies eventually take is actuated by one agency only: the human soul. He says of
music’s nature, therefore:29 “It is the movement of the human soul
that occurs on its release from the evils arising from the passions.”
It is when he turns to the question of the musical pitches themselves and their nature that Theophrastus is at his most original and
maverick-best. The question that he addresses is: What makes the pitches
differ from one another? In answering this question, he seems almost
27
28
29
Lippman (note 22), p. 158.
Porphyry (Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 61.22–24), trans.
Barker. See Bowman, Philosophical Perspectives on Music, pp. 103ff. on the
“Sounding Inwardness” of music.
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 65.14–15).
104
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
to endow pitches with an actual existence, up to their very shape and
form; that is to say, they are not for him lifeless components of melody
that resemble nothing in actual nature. He insists then that musical
pitches differ in highness and lowness from one another not by virtue of
such quantitative factors as frequency of vibration, but solely because of
differences in their intrinsic characters. A low note, for example, tends
to spread out more in that it “travels everywhere all around,” whereas a
high note is more directional in that it moves “in the direction in which
the utterer compels it to go.” Theophrastus’ argument to this effect is
based on an assumption that is fundamental to understanding his theory: pitch differences are not constituted by the distances of intervals
between them. Indeed, for him, intervals as such do not exist independently. In his words:30
Again, it is not the intervals, as some people say, that are the causes of the
differences [between pitches] and hence their principles, since if these are
left out the differences still remain. For when something comes into being
if certain things are left out, these are not the causes of its existence, not as
productive causes, but [only] as things that do not prevent it.
It is not easy to give precision to Theophrastus’ point regarding musical intervals, but, according to Barker, this is what he seemed to mean:
a sound’s pitch cannot be understood simply in terms of its distance – or
interval – from another pitch, but must be an intrinsic feature of the
sound itself.31 That being the case, an interval cannot be thought of as
the cause of a difference between any two pitches; rather, the difference
between any two pitches must exist as an independent phenomenon. As
Barker says:32
The distance on the continuum between two given notes is conceived as
constituted by a range of intervening pitches. Theophrastus is arguing that
these cannot be the ‘cause’ of the difference between the two given notes,
since that exists whether the intervening pitches are sounded or not.
30
31
32
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 64.25–27), trans.
Barker.
Barker, II, p. 117, n. 39.
Barker, II, p. 117, n. 40.
The Discrete and the Continuous
105
The critical word in Barker’s exegesis is continuum, this being one of the
three elementary phenomena of music. The two others are time and
motion. In this, the extant portion of his treatise On Music, Theophrastus
was not only arguing that intervals on the continuum cannot be causes of
pitch differences; he was doing much more: he was looking for a way to
divide the continuum of melody without destroying it.
Zuckerkandl, Sound and Symbol, spoke of the melodic continuum in
this way:33
What do we hear – a progress advancing in uninterrupted continuity or an
alternation of skips and halts, a discontinuous progress? There can be no
doubt about the answer: we could not hear the melody as motion if we did
not hear it as continuous. . . . Where is the continuously progressing line,
the symbol of continuity of motion? Stasis-gap-stasis-gap; our graph is the
perfect image of discontinuity. One is at a loss to understand how this can
be heard as a continuous process.
The gapped motion heard by Zuckerkandl is thoroughly paradoxical:
a melody which is perceived by the ear to be moving by leaps along an
unbroken line, is in reality stopping at every change of pitch. How then
can there be such a thing as tonal motion if a thing in motion from one
place to another does not skip any of the intervening spaces, much less
stop in any of them? This is the paradox for which Theophrastus found
a thoroughly inventive solution. To begin with, he knew that pitches
could not constitute spatially distinguishable parts of what is continuous, because what is truly continuous cannot be constituted of distinguishable or indivisible parts.34 To deal with the paradox presented
by tonal motion, Theophrastus followed the teachings of his master,
Aristotle: that is, he thought of musical space as Aristotle thought of
homogeneous natural substances – air or water. Aristotle thought of
such substances as continuous in that their extremities are of a oneness
and wherein there is no intermediate boundary or point. It is in this
33
34
Zuckerkandl, Sound and Symbol, pp. 118–19.
Thus Aristotle Physics 231a24–26: “Something that is continuous (synechēs)
cannot be composed of indivisibles, such as a line composed of points, if indeed
the line is continuous, but the point is indivisible.” On Aristotle’s claims to
back up this argument, see White, The Continuous and the Discrete, pp. 23–24.
106
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
sense that Theophrastus speaks of music as something whose nature is
“one.” He believed in the reality of the melodic continuum, as he had no
difficulty in conceiving of it as a real substance: pitch, pure and simple,
a substance that is common to all melody and, hence, to all music.
But if all such substance were to be sounded at the same time, there
would be no melody and, certainly, no music. There would only be stasis. Rothstein has described the case in these terms:35
Our sense of musical movement is continuous while pitches change in a
melody by discrete steps. The movement from A to E is a leap. Yet somehow we experience it as a continuous movement. If we attempt literally to
connect these tones, to fill the spaces between them, we get no more than a
slide or a siren – a sound which is almost musically irrelevant and can also
seem oddly static.
Theophrastus’ plan was to give a logical explanation of the melodic
continuum; but he met with difficulty at the very beginning of his undertaking. How could one speak of a continuum while allowing at the same
time for the simultaneous presence of the distinct and paradoxically
separate pitches of melody? Was the melodic continuum in fact a continuous magnitude constituted of nothing but a set of densely ordered
discrete elements? Was there a fundamental continuity by virtue of
the fact that the limits of these elements touched one another, thereby
becoming one? Theophrastus’ answers to these questions was apparently “Yes” – this because he believed in the existence of an actually
subsisting continuum of melody. To him, it was something concrete, and
not simply a confused perception of reality. Instead of trying to prove
its existence, however, he left it to the composer of music to deal with
as an actually existing musical substance. In this, its raw and unworked
state, he saw it to be something unmelodic (ekmeleia), something as illdefined as a slab of unpolished stone. In order for the composer to transform it into a work of art – something melodious (emmeleia) – he had to
extract each note from its surroundings and reject all of the underlying
35
Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, pp. 100–1. So, too, Theophrastus in Porphyry
Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 64.32–65.2): “For if someone
were to sing simultaneously the continuous series of intervening positions as
well, the sound produced would certainly be unmelodic” (trans. Barker).
The Discrete and the Continuous
107
continuum that he judged to be irrelevant or unfit for his melody. The
finished product is understood by Theophrastus to be a copy of the
human soul being released from its passions’ ills. It is like a sculpted
work – the Milan Pieta of Michelangelo Buonarroti, say, seen emerging
from its stony medium. Unlike the effort of Michelangelo, however, in
which part of the unsculpted background appears in the finished product, nothing appears in melody but the notes themselves. What has
been discarded and rejected are the intervals between the notes of the
finished composition. In Theophrastus’ words:36
It is therefore a great help that melody revolves around these [the melodic
and the unmelodic], enabling us to find the notes that are attuned to one
another. But it is these notes that are the causes of melody, while if the
rejected intervals are made apparent, they are the causes of the unmelodic,
whose principles they might be said to be, not those of melodic sound. Thus
neither are the intervals the causes of the melodic, but damage it, at least
when they are made apparent.
The ultimate conclusion of Theophrastus’ theory is that there can be
no empty space in the domain of music: there are only continua filled to
capacity with densely ordered sonorous potentialities, some of which
are pressed into service as melodic notes on the release of the soul’s emotions. Whether this conclusion was faithful to Aristotle’s conception of
one-dimensional continuous magnitudes is open to argument. But one
thing is certain: Theophrastus was trying his utmost to produce a theory that would satisfy Aristotle’s criteria for the formal, structural properties of continuous magnitudes. That being the case, he felt confident
that his was a defensible theory. Otherwise, he would not have treated
intervals as he did, namely, as the principal cause (aitia) of ekmeleia: all
unmelodic utterance. Intervals, on Theophrastus’ conception, were by
their very nature cacophonous; this was because they admitted an infinite number of discrete elements which, when sounded simultaneously,
produced the very opposite of melody. Those people, therefore, who,
he says, treated intervals as “the causes of pitch differences and hence
36
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 65.4–9), trans.
Barker.
108
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
their principles,” were in his estimation altogether misguided. Indeed,
such people seem to him to be trivializing the significance of something real – pitch itself – by focusing their attention on something
completely unproductive – intervals. Theophrastus’ criticism on this
point is a none-too-thinly-veiled attack on his colleague, Aristoxenus.
For it was none other than Aristoxenus who was arguing vigorously
(and probably constantly) that the miraculous order he heard in the
constitution of melody had as much to do with intervals of various types
of composition as it did with notes of variously distributed pitches.
When it came to dealing with his critics, Aristoxenus was never at a
loss. Quite the contrary: he could be downright scathing. Unfortunately,
he was not in a position to refute his most challenging critics: Ptolemy,
in the second century a.d. and R. P. Winnington-Ingram in the twen
tieth. But he was on hand to reply to Theophrastus, and in this instance
he was simple, direct and, it must be said, typically withering. To be sure,
he did not mention Theophrastus by name; instead, he allowed the otherwise unknown harmonician, Eratocles (and his school), to bear the full
brunt of his scorn:37
Most of the harmonicians did not even perceive that a treatment of the
subject (intervals) was necessary; but we discussed it in an earlier work.
Eratocles and his school said only this much: that melody splits in two
in either direction from the interval of a fourth; but they do not distinguish whether this melodic split derives from every fourth, nor do they
say what the cause of this is; neither do they inquire into what way other
intervals are put together with one another, or even whether there is a principle of synthesis for the constitution of one interval with another. . . . And
though there is a miraculous ordering in the composition of melody, music
is charged by some people with the height of disorder, because of how some
of them have meddled with the subject under discussion.
To be sure, Theophrastus never charged music with the height of
disorder, but his treatment of intervals may easily have been regarded
by Aristoxenus as “meddling” in the extreme. For, as Aristoxenus saw
37
Harm. El. I . 5 (Da Rios, 9.15–10.7). On Eratocles, see Barker, II, p. 129,
n. 22.
The Discrete and the Continuous
109
it – quite in opposition to Theophrastus’ stated position – the intervals
between the notes of melody are as vital as the notes themselves. His
reason for this was a strictly musical one: it is within the intervals
between the notes of melody that the motion of melody takes place.38
To Theophrastus, in his attempt to give a scientific account of music’s
nature, two sets of phenomena seemed important: the intrinsic character of musical notes themselves, in isolation from their context; the
gaps or intervals between notes, the contents of which are left out in
the formation of melody. Aristoxenus, however, being the complete
musician he indeed was, evidently had little patience with the subtleties of arguments such as that of Theophrastus. He regarded only one
thing as supremely important: the knowledge of his own ear; and he
valued theories and hypotheses only insofar as they were consistent with
this knowledge. Theophrastus’ theory had to have been regarded by
Aristoxenus as inconsistent with the ear’s knowledge in the most fundamental respects, the most obvious being that single notes taken out
of context do not make for melody. Equally important, the context of
melody is dependent upon the intervals between the notes of melody.
Most important of all, Theophrastus’ theory took no account of those
phenomena that Aristoxenus considered axiomatic in the perception of
melody: time, motion, and the melodic continuum.
Aristoxenus began by asserting the existence of motion by the singing voice as it progresses from note to melodic note in the production of
melody. “Does the voice really move?” Theophrastus might have asked
with a certain degree of scepticism. There is nothing conciliatory or
accommodating in Aristoxenus’ reply to such a question:39
38
As Aristoxenus explains in Harm. El. I. 13 (Da Rios, 18. 1ff.), Pitch (tasis) must
be distinguished from tension (epitasis) and relaxation (anesis) on the grounds
that pitch is where the voice comes to rest, while the risings and fallings of the
voice occur between the pitches. Barker, II, p. 133, note 42, says accordingly:
“he [sc. Aristoxenus] applies the terms primarily to vocal sound itself, not to
the physical means of its production: it is the vocal sound, not the vocal organ,
that is tensed or relaxed . . .”
39 Harm. El. I. 9 (Da Rios, 13.23–14. 4), trans. Barker. In his note on this passage,
Barker, II, p. 132, n. 38, points out that the “different enquiry” deals with the
physics of sound.
110
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Whether it is actually possible or impossible for the voice to move and then
come to rest upon a single point of pitch, is a question belonging to a different enquiry, and for the purposes of the present science an account of the
motion involved in each of these is unnecessary.
The implication in Aristoxenus’ reply is clear: no musician would think of
asking such a question. The reason is incontestable to a musician: motion
is what the ear apprehends in melody. Zuckerkandl has stated the case in
terms that Aristoxenus would have been pleased to acknowledge:40
Musical contexts are motion contexts, kinetic contexts. Tones are elements
of a musical context because and insofar as they are conveyors of a motion
that goes through them and beyond them. When we hear music, what we
hear is above all motions.
The skeptic might have pursued the subject: “If, as you insist, the
motion of the singing voice is not merely an illusion, that it is, in fact, real
to the ear, and that the focal point in music must be sought in melodic
motion, tell me, then, where does this motion actually take place and
how specifically does it manifest itself?” Aristoxenus says, “The voice
must in singing a melody pass imperceptibly through the space (topos) of
the interval.” “Well, then, if, as you say, the motion of the voice through
the spaces or intervals between the notes of melody is imperceptible,
what is it that the ear apprehends as genuine motion?” Aristoxenus
explains that the two key elements that promote the motion of the singing voice are tension (tasis) and resolution, or relaxation (anesis):41
It is evident that in singing the voice must make its tensions and relaxations
imperceptibly, and when uttering the pitches themselves must make them
apparent; for its progress across the interval which it traverses, whether
relaxing or increasing tension, must not be detected, whereas it must give
out the notes that bound the intervals clearly and without movement.
In these profound utterances on the nature of melody, Aristoxenus
applies the concept of motion not to the vibration of vocal chords, or to
40
41
Zuckerkandl, p. 76.
Harm. El. I. 10 (Da Rios, 15.6–12), trans. Barker, II, p. 133.
The Discrete and the Continuous
111
that of strings or air-columns, not, that is, to the physical production
of musical sound; he applies the concept of motion uniquely to musical sound itself. It is here that Aristoxenus reaches across the millenia
to modern musicians. Thus Cooke who, in his exasperation with many
writers on music, sounds much like Aristoxenus himself:42
The simple but amazing fact is that, although certain directional movements of pitch have occasionally been analysed as ‘symbols’ (Schweitzer on
Bach, for example), no one has seriously got down to the business of discovering, in each particular context, exactly what the notes of the scale are and what
tensions exist between them.
And Rothstein might have been consulting Aristoxenus himself when
he wrote:43
Continuity [what Aristoxenus termed synecheia] comes from something
beyond literal pitch, found in the very notion of relation. Just as a mathematician can see a number in terms of its nexus of relations to others – its
properties granted by nature, and its place in a particular organization of
concepts and rules established by the art – so does a musician experience
tone. Melody is a musical state in which those relations are harnessed, creating a field of tensions and relaxations, anticipations and surprises.
The main doctrine to which Aristoxenus remained constant throughout his writings on music concerned melodic determinism and the composer’s own musical intuition. He believed that there is no such thing as
chance in melody, but that the production of a melody that will move
the soul is determined by natural laws.44 He insisted, therefore, that the
composer must understand the properties of his material – the notes
42
43
44
Cooke, The Language of Music, p. 40.
Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, p. 102.
To Aristoxenus, the natural laws governing the ordering of the melodic elements are comparable to those productive of intelligible language. As he
explains in Harm. El. I. 27 (Da Rios, 35.10–17), the placement of notes and
intervals in melody is not at all random, but is as carefully determined as the
placement of letters and syllables in language. Analogies between speech and
melody did not originate with Aristoxenus, but seem to have their roots in
Plato Philebus 17Aff. Cf. Barker, II, p. 213, n. 12.
112
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
and intervals of the singing voice in its progress (by moving and stopping) through musical space. This motion and stopping peculiar to the
singing voice he termed “intervallic” (diasystēmatikē) as opposed to the
motion of the speaking voice, which he called “continuous” (synechēs).
As he says:45
We say, therefore, that the speaking voice is continuous, since when we
speak the voice moves through space in such a way that it seems never to
stand still [on pitch].
Without a careful discrimination between the properties of speech and
song, he felt that it would be very difficult, if not impossible, to understand the properties of notes and intervals, the elemental components
of the material of music. For just as bricks can be reduced to their components – earth and water, let us say – so the material of music – the
sounds produced by the singing voice – are reducible to single units in
the form of individual notes and the intervals between them. When,
however, these single units or notes are compounded into scales and
modes in which each is assigned a particular function (dynamis), something miraculous happens, something that no pile of bricks or stones is
capable of achieving: a gravitational field of motion is released within
the scale, the distinctive characteristics of which are transferred to any
melody that is composed according to the laws of that particular scale.46
Such a melody was for Aristoxenus the embodiment of true harmonia,
and he regarded it as a miraculous ordering of the musical phenomena.
The concept of harmonia under which Aristoxenus assembled the
components of melody had as its ruling principle, not number, but,
45
46
Harm. El. I. 9 (Da Rios. 14. 12–14).
Zuckerkandl, Sound and Symbol, p. 100, speaks of this phenomenon in melody
as a dynamic field: “. . . a rise and fall not in tonal space but in the tonal dynamic
field, in relation to a given audible center of force.” And Rothstein, Emblems of
Mind, p. 103, observes of such systems of organized notes and relations: “It is
a kind of musical geometry, articulating relations of closeness and distance,
curved lines and intersections. And it is found in this most elementary form
of relation – two notes defining a kind of force field in musical space.” Thus
Barker, “Aristoxenus’ Theorems,” 62: “Not all our tunes obey all Aristoxenian
laws, but his system has been modified and elaborated rather than buried” [italics
supplied].
The Discrete and the Continuous
113
rather, the disposition or natural synthesis of magnitudes or intervals
that admit motion (kinēsis) and the discrete points of pitch that admit
stoppage (stasis). The figures, or schēmata, of this type of synthesis were
as formal as those of an Aristotelian syllogism; they admitted of no
extraneous elements. As Aristoxenus explained it, a melody that accords
with the laws of harmonia owes its melodiousness not simply to the
notes and the intervals of which it is composed, but above all, to a
definite principle of synthesis whereby its intervals (possessed of motion)
and its notes (possessed of stoppage) are collocated. Aristoxenus’ fundamental conviction, which lies at the basis of his doctrine, is this: the ear,
whether educated by habit or ordained by nature, will find continuity
wherever it truly exists. And he firmly believed that continuity exists in
its purest form in melody.
There is, however, a serious logical difficulty about this doctrine.
It begins with Aristoxenus’ description of the singing voice and its
motion through the intervals or spaces between the notes of melody. It
is a motion that is peculiarly “intervallic”:47
The voice seems to the ear to stop on a point of pitch, and having done so,
to come to a stop on a second point of pitch, and to repeat this alternating
process continuously.
The question is, if the voice is moving from note to note, where
in fact is it in the interval between notes? And what, in reality, is the
nature of an interval between notes? In Aristoxenus’ theory, intervals
are spatial magnitudes that appear to have the formal, structural properties of infinite divisibility. Indeed, he even characterizes the locus of a
particular note – the lichanos – as apeiron, or infinite. At the same time,
he treats all notes as discrete entities that are themselves indivisible.
But these facts, derived as they are from the ear’s perception, contradict the fundamental ontological principle laid down by Aristotle: what
is infinitely divisible and continuous cannot be constituted of discrete
points. Theophrastus had seen the dimensions of this problem in music
and had attempted to deal with it just as Aristotle did with the universe: he approached the domain of music as if it were a self-contained
47
Harm. El. I. 9 (Da Rios. 14.8–12).
114
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
universe, one that was finite in extent and filled entirely with matter
(see note 20).
As Aristoxenus saw it, the most obvious way of avoiding the logical
difficulties of the continuum was first to accept motion of the voice as a
fact of experience; and following that, to assume that a thing can move
only in an empty space. In this way, he could proceed to distinguish
between matter – the material elements of music – and space – the topos
wherein the voice moves. According to this view, musical space cannot be construed as nothing, but is of the nature of a receptacle which
may or may not have any given part filled with matter.48 And where
there is not matter, there is still something: those miraculous tensions
and relaxations occurring between the notes of melody. Aristoxenus
believed further that musical space, if considered solely in the abstract,
is infinite in extension and, as seen in the case of the locus of a lichanos,
infinitesimal in diminution.49 Thus, he says of both concords (octaves,
fifths, and fourths) and discords (all intervals smaller than a fourth) that
they are theoretically capable of infinite extension; for if one adds to an
octave, for example, any concord, “whether greater than, equal to, or
less than an octave, the sum is a concord. From this point of view, there
is no maximum concord.”50 One can also say that, theoretically, there
are micro-intervals without number. But since Aristoxenus was determined to compose a theory of music based wholly on human capabilities and not on abstract theory, he did not consider it necessary to deal
with anything such as a maximum interval that lies beyond the ear’s
48
49
50
Within this topos or continuum, there are only two directions in which the voice
can move: up and down; but there are countless ways in which the voice can
effect changes of quality and aspect. To an Aristotelian, all such changes are
construed as motions. At the same time, the topos in which these motions transpire is defined in Aristotelian terms solely by the things that move within it.
The moving thing in this case is the moving voice, and the topos in which it
moves is a continuum which is, by definition, homogeneous.
As Aristoxenus puts it in Harm. El. I. 26 (Da Rios. 34.3–4): “The number of
lichanoi must be thought of as infinite.” The identity of any lichanos depends
upon its melodic function (dynamis), as Aristoxenus goes on to explain in more
elaborate detail in Harm. El. II. 47–48 (Da Rios, 58. 10–60. 3). On Aristoxenus’
concept of dynamis, see Barker, “Aristoxenus’ Theorems,” 52ff.
Harm. El. I. 20 (Da Rios, 25.17–26.2).
The Discrete and the Continuous
115
ability to judge, or to admit of any interval too small for the voice to
negotiate. He therefore limited his theory to two things only: that space
within which the ear can discriminate every type of melodic motion
that is musically intelligible; those intervallic motions in musical space
which the voice is capable of executing. In his words:51
Whether the constitution of melody, if considered in the abstract, will turn
out to extend to infinity, should perhaps be the subject of another inquiry
and not necessary to the matter at hand; this is a subject that must be
undertaken at a later time.
For the present then, Aristoxenus was concerned only to establish the
most natural limits of melody: the minimum concordant interval – the
fourth – within whose bounds the voice can place its pitches and those
placements of pitch that the ear can readily distinguish; the maximum
concordant interval that the ear can readily identify and the voice can
securely produce. This maximum interval, he concluded, was at best
two octaves and a fifth. He says accordingly:52
It is evident from what has been said, therefore, that when we progress
toward the smaller limit, it is the nature of melody itself that determines
the smallest concord, the fourth; but when we progress toward the greater
limit, the greatest of the concords is determined somehow by our own natural capacities.
To make his theory a fully realized system of logically interrelated
propositions, Aristoxenus had first to link it to three things of major
import: what is thought, what is experienced, and what is. What is
thought belongs in Aristoxenus’ view to the activity of the musically
intelligent mind (dianoia) and, because this activity determines what
is embodied in the synthesis of all melodic consecution, it must be
consulted as the final authority on the subject. This activity is powerful
enough to transcend the ear’s perception and, as such, is so mysterious
that Aristoxenus cannot attribute any predicates to it; he can only speak
51
52
Harm. El. I. 15 (Da Rios, 20. 11–14). This theoretical point is not discussed
subsequently, however.
Harm. El. I. 21 (Da Rios, 27. 8–11).
116
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of it as something that is all-knowing and all-determining. His word
for this activity of the musical mind is synesis. Because it is capable of
determining a priori to there being given in particular instances of melody those conditions that make for all musical discourse, it is rendered
here as “musical intuition”:53
And if musical intuition (synesis) is hidden somewhere deep within the
soul, and is not palpable or visible to the average man, as is the working of the hands and other such operations, we must not suppose our
statements to be inconsistent on that account. For unless we regard that
which does the determining as our absolute and ultimate authority as
opposed to that which is determined, we shall end up missing the truth
altogether.
It is as hard to say exactly what one experiences on hearing music as
it is to define time. Time – the paradigmatic continuum – was defined by
Plato as “the moving image of eternity,” because time, he felt, could not
be thought of apart from the eternally moving planets in their heavenly
orbits.54 So, too, music, as it is experienced, may be thought of as the
moving image of time, since it cannot transpire apart from the time it
charters for itself. As it is experienced, music makes for us a world of
ideal conditions; it appears to the ear to admit of sizeless points between
which there is an alignment and among which there are centers of gravity. Although these points have no size, they do have position, and they
seem so sharp and apparent that they coincide perfectly with idealized
instants of time. They seem to be alive, but at the same time they are
as evanescent and ungraspable as points of energy or bolts of lightning.
Combined together into melodies, they erupt from emotional depths
whose source can never be adequately plumbed because, as Aristoxenus
53
Harm. El. II. 41 (Da Rios, 51. 16–52. 4); Cf. Levin, “Synesis in Aristoxenian
Theory,” pp. 212–14.
54 Plato Timaeus 37D5. Thus Taylor, Commentary, p. 187: “The sensible world
is a thing of passage, but it never passes away; its passage fills all time, and
of course, the formal laws of its structure remain the same throughout. So it
really is a moving or passing ‘image’ of the truly abiding. . . . i. e. time, which is
measured duration, may be said to be, in virtue of its character as measurable, an
image of eternity.”
The Discrete and the Continuous
117
says, “It is hidden somewhere deep in the soul.” Musical notes in a
melodic context are not experienced as sound waves; if anything, they
seem to be more akin to brain waves. At the very moment they are present to us, they have already begun to pass away – like time itself. They
are felt to be as untrappable as visual photons.
In attempting to describe the experience of music, Aristoxenus
invoked the phenomena of tension and resolution in the motion of
melody; and these provided him with a model of gravitation and attraction, a model of magnetism in action.55 This in turn rewarded him with
an awareness of the energy, or dynamis, operating between the notes
of melody. He argued therefore that wherever one perceives tension
and resolution in melody – and one perceives it everywhere – one can
assume that a mobile order of attunement has brought a diversity of
musical functions (dynameis) into play. Zuckerkandl says much the same
thing, for like Aristoxenus, he has consulted his own ear of musical
reason. He begins by asking if on hearing two notes in succession – E
and A – whether we hear only the succession of two notes of different
pitch, and answers his question in this way:56
It is music with which we are dealing – and we have found that in the entire
range of music no such thing as “the tone e” or “the tone a” occurs; what
occurs is always and only the tone e with a particular dynamic quality, the
tone a with a different dynamic quality. The dynamic quality, not the pitch,
makes the tone a musical fact. Hence, whenever we have a succession of two
notes, an interval, as a piece of tonal motion – as an element, that is, in a
musical context – we must necessarily hear something in it besides different
pitches, namely, different dynamic qualities.
55
56
The phenomena of tension and resolution that are so keenly felt between the
notes of melody were described for the first time by Aristoxenus. Since then,
almost every practicing musician has had occasion to remark on their mysterious vitality in melodic expression. And this has in turn provoked many a
musician to insist that the spaces between the notes of melody are as important in the interpretation of melody as are the notes themselves. Thus Cooke,
The Language of Music, p. 40: “The expressive basis of the musical language
of Western Europe consists of the intricate system of tensional relationships
between notes which we call the tonal system.” See note 43.
Zuckerkandl, Sound and Symbol, p. 91.
118
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
These are just some of the phenomena that are experienced in melody
and which, if changed even minimally, cause the melody to lose its essential identity. The problem is that these phenomena have no correlation in
the real world, namely, in the world of what is. For what is consists of those
things that have actual existence outside of the mind, but which cause in
us a mental sign of their existence. The second part of the problem is this:
everything that exists in the real world contradicts what is experienced by
the ear in melody. On hearing a melody, the ear experiences a continuity
of intervallic motion in a symmetrical and homogeneous space; here the
singing voice moves unimpeded by anything save its own limitations and
those constraints imposed on it by the laws of melody. In reality, however,
melody is composed of distinct parts – discrete notes that cohere closely
together while leaving spaces between them. The question is: How can
what is truly continuous be constituted of distinguishable or indivisible
parts? It is a conundrum similar to that involving time: measuring time
and finding discrete instances of time is, as Rothstein observed, “like considering an arrow to be at rest at every moment of its flight because we
can specify its location.”57 To resolve this difficulty, Aristoxenus had to
do much more, then, than to distinguish the material elements of melody from the space or topos within which the singing voice moves in its
distinctly intervallic way. He had to find a way of reconciling what he
believed to be the continuity of musical space with the physical fact of its
discontinuity. In other words, he had to do something virtually impossible: he had to create continuity out of discontinuity.
This discontinuity can be discovered in two ways: tuning an instrument by ear; dividing an octave in the ratio 2:1 mathematically. The
first method, which is described by Aristoxenus in explicit detail, is
still being used today by harpsichordists and players of stringed instruments. It entails tuning by the concords, fourths and fifths.58 If one
57
58
Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, p. 49, thus points out: “These paradoxes succeed
in baffling us because they present an idea of space and time that is utterly at
odds with our everyday experience. They proclaim an endless procession of
detached points instead of a seamless, continuous motion, in which there is no
such thing as a ‘next instant’ in time or a ‘next point’ in space.
In Harm. El. II. 55, 56 (Da Rios, 68.17ff ), Aristoxenus explains how the loci
of all the pitches of a scale are determined solely by tuning through fourths
and fifths; the final arbiter in this process is the musically educated ear. Tuning
The Discrete and the Continuous
119
tunes by taking successive true fourths, that is, fourths that conform to
the Pythagorean ratio 4:3, and true fifths, that is, fifths that conform to
the Pythagorean ratio 3:2, all the resulting octaves will be slightly out
of tune. The reason lies in the physical discontinuity of musical space. To
put it in mathematical terms, the expansion of the octave ratio, 2:1, is
incommensurable with the expansions of the internal concords, fourths
and fifths. This means that one can never hope to arrive at a true octave
by tuning with true fourths and fifths. This rupture in the musical
topos – a kind of shifting of its planes – is commonly represented in the
circle of fifths, so-called, within which any starting note will become a
launching pad into an infinity of discontinuities. The result is an endless series of notes differing in pitch from one another, such as: E♯ and
F, B♯, C and D♭♭, F+, G and A♭♭, and so on into infinity.59
Richard Wagner said somewhere that music is “the inarticulate speech of the heart, which cannot be compressed into words,
because it is infinite.” This “inarticulate speech of the heart” is in fact
confirmed by mathematics to be alogos, literally, “inexpressible” or
“unspeakable.” It is embedded in the square root of 2 (or √2), which
appears on the division of the whole-tone in the ratio of 9:8. It is
considered to be alogos, an irrational number, for when it is converted
into decimals it yields the infinite series 1. 4142135... . Infinity thus
pours forth from the discontinuity of the octave with its own parts,
by consonances from a pitch E, for example, will fix the pitches in a diatonic
scale:
E – A, A – D, D – G, G – C, C – F, F – B♭, B♭ – E♭, E♭ – A♭
Tuning in the reverse order from the same pitch E, will fix these pitches:
This yields the pitches of the sequence
B♭ C D E♭ F G A B♭
E – B, B – F♯, F♯ – C♯, C♯ – G♯, G♯ – D♯
This yields the pitches of the sequence:
E F♯ G♯ A B C♯ D♯ E
For a diagram of the process, see Barker, II, p. 169, note 114. Cf. Hubbard,
Harpsichord Regulating and Repairing, pp. 29–31.
59 The problem is explained in detail by Sir James Jeans, Science and Music,
pp. 165–68. See Fig. 3, in which ascending and descending Perfect Fifths lead
to an infinity of atonalities.
120
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
so that the octave is to its internal twelve semi-tones as .666666666
to infinity.60
60
Infinity has not always been greeted with enthusiasm. For example, Felix Holt
(in George Eliot’s novel of the same name) observed: “Your dunce who can’t
do his sums always has a taste for the infinite.” The most alarming occurrence
of the infinite series 666 is to be found in Revelations 13.18: “Here is wisdom.
Let him that hath understanding count the number of the beast: for it is the
number of a man; and his number is Six hundred threescore and six.” Perhaps
this is another way of saying that music and nature are alike in that they are
each inexhaustible, that theories about both will always end up being “better
and better approximations, and that this process will never come to an end.”
See Richard Morris, Achilles in the Quantum Universe, p. 117.
4 Magnitudes and Multitudes
A quantity is a multitude
if it can be numbered;
but it is a magnitude if it can be measured.
Aristotle, Metaphysics 1020a8–10
in the opening lines to book ii of war and peace, tolstoy
offered the following insight on the continuity of motion:
By adopting smaller and smaller elements of motion we only approach a
solution to the problem, but never reach it. Only when we have admitted
the conception of the infinitely small, and the resulting geometrical progression with a common ratio of one tenth, and have found the sum of this
progression to infinity, do we reach a conclusion to the problem.
This is almost exactly what Aristoxenus did. As he conceived the
problem of melodic motion or, as he put it, the motion of the singing
voice, it was only by taking infinitesimally small units for measurement and attaining to the art of integrating them – that is, finding the
sum of these infinitesimals – that he was he able to arrive at the laws
of melodic consecution. The common ratio commanding the infinitely
small basic elements of his progression was one-twelfth. In working
toward this goal, Aristoxenus contrived to break down the mathematically logical opposition between magnitude (megethos) and multitude
(plēthos), in effect, between geometry and arithmetic.1 The very nature
1
Aristoxenus’ method, which will be treated in the chapter to follow, is one
of approximation. It allows as legitimate the notion of complete divisibility,
121
122
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of his method invited him to believe that he could achieve his goal
without altering the nature of scientific reasoning. Directly inspired
by his knowledge of Pythagorean theory, he discovered a completely
new way of dealing with musical intervals: he substituted arithmetic
for geometry. It was necessary for him to do this if he wished to extend
mathematically rigorous methods to problems where no quantity was
involved.
Magnitudes, as Aristoxenus had learned, were measurable distances
that could be expressed only as ratios of string-lengths or air-columns,2
the results of these computations proving that the octave in the ratio
of 2:1 was in truth something less than the sum of six whole-tones
and that the whole-tones in the ratio of 9:8 could not be divided into
equal halves. Yet, Aristoxenus maintained in the face of these mathematical proofs that the octave consisted of six whole-tones and twelve
semitones, that the fourth was equivalent to two whole-tones and a
semitone, and that the fifth was equivalent to three whole-tones and
a semitone. What is more, he insisted that the diesis or enharmonic
quarter-tone was obtained on the division of the semitone. This meant
that such micro-intervals as the eklysis consisted of three quarter-tones
2
according to which a musical interval or magnitude can be divided potentially
at any point whatever. In formulating his method, Aristoxenus relies on the
concept that in such an interval there is always at every point of division a
remaining interval left over, an interval that is itself subject to being further
divided. This amounts to saying that the conceivable divisions of an interval
are infinite. Accordingly, Aristoxenus saw his task as one of delimiting the
genuinely melodious divisions of any intervals while, at the same time, saving
the infinite from all efforts of geometers to abandon that concept.
A column of air when enclosed by some rigid material like wood or metal is,
in some respects, comparable to a stretched string in its mode of vibration.
There are also some marked differences between them: for example, the soundproducing waves traveling along a stretched string are transverse, being caused
by displacements of the string at right angles to the direction in which the
wave is traveling. In the case of air-columns, the traveling waves are longitudinal, the compressions and rarefactions of air traveling in the same line as
the waves themselves. In both cases, the same thing holds true: the period of
each vibration is exactly proportional to the length of the column of air which
is vibrating and to the length of string that is vibrating. Cf. Jeans, Science and
Music, p. 64; p. 113.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
123
and the ekbolē of five quarter-tones.3 He went so far as to verify these
calculations by a process of adding and subtracting rational numbers.
To an orthodox Pythagorean, this was mathematical heresy. In truth,
however, Aristoxenus was doing something highly original and daring in the extreme, something that no one had ever attempted before:
he was arithmetizing continuous magnitudes.4 His goal was to facilitate the treatment of these magnitudes as continua constituted of individual elements or sets of points that are intuited to be discrete. His
method – a radical departure from that of the Pythagoreans – consisted
in the ordering and disposition of the melodic elements – notes and
intervals – as they are apprehended by the ear. From his perspective,
the Pythagoreans, through their use of pure mathematics, had divorced
melodic knowledge from its perceived objects, thereby making of it
an abstract science. Aristoxenus arrived at a different method, one that
was determined by the peculiar nature of these same objects. In brief,
to Aristoxenus melody was distinct from mathematics as a science,
because its proper object was not quantity, but the motion of the singing voice. And this could not be expressed in mathematical ratios as if
3
Aristoxenus’ method of verifying these empirical facts involved tuning by consonance, the details of which are discussed in Chapter 3, note 58. But because
this method was no more reliable than that of mathematics for determining
the sizes of the various micro-intervals in melodic use, Aristoxenus invented a
strategy for mapping out these intervals, the originality of which is alluded to
in note 1 of this chapter. It was, in fact, so original that Aristoxenus had every
reason to assert in Harm. El. II. 35 (Da Rios, 44. 10–13) that no one before
him had ever attempted to do what he managed to accomplish against all
mathematical odds: that is, establish the loci (or topoi) of all the moveable notes
in the tetrachord, those notes which made for all the generic notes in melody.
In making this claim, Aristoxenus was implicitly rejecting the method of the
Pythagoreans, for this method proved that there was in fact no way to represent the micro-intervals. On that basis, they could be said to exist only in the
imagination of the mind’s ear.
4 The standard Pythagorean model for dealing with musical intervals was a
geometrical extension, or magnitude (megethos). In opposition to this frame
of reference, Aristoxenus was bent on reducing the mathematical model to
an arithmetic concept of multitude (plēthos), or collection of discrete quanta.
On the Pythagorean model and its origins in the Academy, see B. L. van der
Waerden, “Die Harmonielehre der Pythagoreer,” 164–65.
124
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
it were nothing other than quantity. In the end, however, Aristoxenus
was to controvert all the harmonic truths that had accumulated over
the centuries and that were eventually comprehended in the work of
the Pythagoreans’ best exemplar: the Sectio Canonis of Euclid. In the
process, he won for himself many critics and few, if any, champions.
As matters now stand, therefore, direct study of Aristoxenus’ theory is
matched only by endless disputes about his treatment of the subject –
harmonics. Admittedly, his writings, like those of his teacher, Aristotle,
go far to sustain the disputes. At the same time, however, the teachings
of Aristotle do much to support his position. It could scarcely be otherwise: Aristotle, to contemplate nature, took his evidence from the same
source as did Aristoxenus – the direct testimony of the senses – and
Aristoxenus approached music from the same position and for the same
purpose as Aristotle approached nature: to account for the way in which
the phenomena in question present themselves to the senses.
The phenomena in question here are pitch, loudness, and timbre, all
of which can be represented mathematically on the basis of the unifying
principle – motion. To their eternal credit, the Pythagoreans had found
a way to describe pitch in terms of number and numerical ratios. They
saw the cause of pitch in the vibratory motion of a stretched string;
they heard the effect of such motion in the corresponding rise and fall of
the pitch produced by the stretched string. Thus, they could conclude,
as did Archytas, that high-pitched notes move faster than low-pitched
ones.5 When it came, however, to vouch for the truth of their observations, they used their eyes. To be sure, they used their hands to pluck
the strings whose behavior they had under observation. But it was the
additional use to which they put their eyes in the interest of such observations that led them to relate the elements of pitch and interval to
5
Musical pitch was regarded by the Pythagoreans as inseparable from the motion
that is its cause. Archytas says accordingly (Vors. 47B1; DK, I. 435. 13–14):
“That the high-pitched notes move more quickly, while the low-pitched notes
move more slowly, has been made obvious to us from numerous examples.”
The assumption of motion as the principle, or archē of audible phenomena, and
the adduction of number as the primary element or stoicheion of musical pitch
supplied the Urstoff for the Pythagorean doctrine of harmonics. Cf. Alan C.
Bowman, “The Foundations of Early Pythagorean Harmonic Science: Archytas,
Fragment 1,” Ancient Philosophy 2 (1982), 79–104.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
125
number. This use was twofold: to make accesssible to science what the
eye cannot see; to verify and, if necessary, to correct what the ear hears
or, as the case may be, what the ear seems to hear. What the eye can
see is that the shorter the string under tension, the faster it vibrates,
and conversely, the longer the string, the slower its rate of vibration.
To these facts of observation, the ear can add its own: the lower pitches
emanate from the longer string; the higher pitches are emitted by the
shorter string. Because, however, the eye cannot determine with any
exactitude how fast a string may actually be moving, and the ear cannot be relied on, according to the Pythagoreans, to recognize the exact
degree by which one pitch may differ from another, the evidence of
measure had to be enlisted. For, touched at visually measurable lengths,
a stretched string can thereby be made to reveal its mathematical properties to a certainty – to the same certainty, that is, as those of a straight
line. Observing that between every pair of points on the line – or on
the stretched string – there was a relation having certain properties
in virtue of which such a relation was measurable, the Pythagoreans
developed a theory of harmonics based upon the metrical division of
the canon. This process of division or segmentation of a string stretched
above a canon, or ruler, was pursued by the Pythagoreans as a geometry of the straight line or, what Bertrand Russell in his Principles of
Mathematics, calls metrical geometry.6 The mathematical truths derived
over the centuries from this course of study were eventually formalized
by Euclid in the remarkable little treatise aptly titled Katatomē Kanonos,
Division of the Canon, or Sectio Canonis.7
6
7
As Russell explains in the Principles of Mathematics, pp. 407ff., in metrical geometry, the numbers adduced “can be given a one-to-one correspondence with the
various relations of the class in question.” The class in question in this instance
is distance, which the Pythagoreans treated as a class of magnitude, or megethos.
If the distances be magnitudes, any two must be equal or unequal. Since the
distance in this case is a rational number, and rationals are one-one relations,
additions and subtractions of such magnitudes are pursued not arithmetically,
but by relational multiplication and square roots, respectively. Cf. Russell,
Principles, pp. 254ff.
The treatise is contained in Jan, pp. 148–66. It is translated by Barker, II,
pp. 191–208. The text, translation, and commentary, together with the
commentaries of Porphyry and Boethius, are provided by André Barbera,
126
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
The opening lines of the Sectio Canonis bring into decisive action those
fundamental forces of the Greek genius for charting the road to truth –
thought and perception, the way of reason and the way of the senses.
They do this with the effortlessness of a master thinker and with the
presentiments of a genius at thought. For only the power and purpose
of a wisdom unrealizable by the average intellect could have inferred,
as does Euclid, so much from so little, and express it withal in the
majestic simplicity of the opening words of the Sectio Canonis.8 It begins
with stillness, the element of stricken silence, the better to introduce
motion, the physical cause of musical pitch:9
If there were stillness and nothing astir, there would be silence; with silence
and nothing at all in motion, nothing would be heard. If, therefore, something is to be heard, there must first be percussion and motion. Consequently,
since all musical notes derive from the advent of some sort of percussion,
and there can be no percussion without there first being motion – some of
which motions are more densely distributed, others more widely separated,
the motions of greater density producing the higher-pitched notes, those
more widely separated producing the lower-pitched notes – it follows necessarily that notes are higher in pitch when they are constituted of more
densely massed and more numerous motions, but they are lower in pitch
when they are constituted of more rarified and fewer motions.
The Euclidean Division of the Canon. See also, Barker, “Methods and Aims in the
Euclidean Sectio Canonis,” 1–16, for critical analysis.
8 The grounds for assuming that the Sectio Canonis is the unified treatise by
the single author, Euclid, were presented by Levin, “Unity in Euclid’s ‘Sectio
Canonis’,” Hermes 118 (1990), 430–43. This view is far from a unanimous one,
however. Over the centuries, opinions as to authorship have varied widely. The
arguments for and against Euclid as author have been collected and carefully
evaluated by André Barbera, The Euclidean Division of the Canon, pp. 3–29,
whose even-handed analyses do not favor one side of the debate over the other.
In an earlier work, “Placing Sectio Canonis in historical and philosophical contexts,” JHS civ (1984), 161, Barbera committed himself to the following view:
“The style and language of the Sectio are like those of Euclid’s Elements, and
there can be hardly any objection to calling the musical treatise ‘Euclidean’.”
For a history of the controversy about the date and authorship of the treatise,
see Burkert, Lore and Science in the Ancient Pythagoreanism, p. 375, n. 22.
9 This translation is from the text of Jan, pp. 148–49.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
127
Euclid then goes on to explain that number and ratio are implicit in
the increase or decrease of the vibratory motions responsible for the rise
and fall of pitch. Number thus refers to the multiplicity of the vibratory motions, whereas ratio refers to the relation of such numbers to one
another. That being the case, musical pitches can be thought of solely
in terms of number and ratio:
As a consequence, notes that are pitched too high can be lowered to the
proper level by a reduction of motion, while those that are pitched too low
can be raised to a proper level by an increase in motion. Since notes arrive at
a proper level by an increase or decrease in motion, they should be spoken
of as being constituted of parts. And since all things composed of parts are
spoken of in terms of the ratio of numbers obtaining between them, notes
should also be spoken of in terms of the ratio of numbers obtaining between
them. In the case of numbers, some are described as in multiple proportion,
others in superparticular proportion, and others in superpartient proportion. The necessary consequence is that notes should also be spoken of in
reference to one another in terms of proportions such as these. In the case of
these [numbers], however, those which are in multiple and superparticular
relations to one another are designated by a single name. We also know of
musical notes that some are concordant, while others are discordant; and
that the concords result when two notes effect a single blend between them,
while discords do not. This being the case, it is reasonable to assume that
notes are concordant when they produce a single blend of the voice from
their two pitches and that they are of the class of numbers which are designated under a single name between them, whether they be in multiple or
superparticular relation.
Insofar as Euclid found motion to be the basis upon which to express
the melodic facts – pitch and interval – in terms of quantitative values,
he could effectively formulate a science of relationships between the
sounds of melody while ignoring the prerogatives of those sounds
themselves: those tensions and remissions that operate with living vigor
between the sounds. Harmonics, as practiced by the Pythagoreans and
Euclid, was therefore distinct from the study of melody, as practiced by
Aristoxenus, because the object of Pythagorean harmonics was quantity and not those musical phenomena that cannot be represented by
128
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
mathematics. Nonetheless, for Euclid, certainly, mathematical names
had a wonderful power of suggestion, such names, for example, as
pollaplasios (multiple), epimorios (superparticular), and epimeres (super
partient). Indeed, they were invitations to him to deal with the concords
and discords of melody in the same way one does with the mathematical names by which the concords and discords are designated. The
result is that Euclid made the objects of harmonic knowledge – notes
and intervals – as similar as possible to those of mathematics. But, as
Aristoxenus saw all too clearly, there is a danger in this procedure: one
can easily make mathematics arbitrary in its results instead of making
the results of harmonic investigation mathematically evident.
Strictly speaking, the introduction to the Sectio Canonis, all of which
is translated earlier from Jan, for which see note 9, is concerned solely
with musical pitch, the product of vibratory motion; but its net effect
comes from the attention it turns on the vibratory nature of that motion
as it applies to the production of pitch. For, by turning his attention in
this direction, Euclid has in effect given a physical account of how the
sound of all musical instruments, the human voice included, is propagated into space, an account that is uncannily prescient in its comprehension. He accomplished this by relating vibratory motion, whether it
be of plucked strings, vocal cords, air-columns, or drum surfaces, to the
rate of percussion induced thereby on the surrounding air. In so doing,
he actually set the provisions, and even provided the technical terms, for
what would be discovered almost two thousand years later – namely, that
the succession of condensations (pyknoterai) and rarefactions (araioterai)
in the air, which reaches the ear and causes the sensation of sound, constitutes a sound wave.10 This, the discovery of the nineteenth-century
mathematician, Joseph Fourier, was of unprecedented importance in
10
The periodic succession of these condensations and rarefactions was understood by Isaac Newton to be “pulses” of air. As he put it in his Philosophiae
Naturalis Principia Mathematica, Book II, Section VIII, Proposition 43: “Every
tremulous body in an elastic medium propagates the motion of pulses on every
side straight forwards. Case 1: The parts of the tremulous body, alternately
going and returning, do in going urge and drive before them those parts of
the medium that lie nearest, and by that impulse compress and condense them;
and in returning suffer those compressed parts to recede again, and expand
themselves” [italics mine].
Magnitudes and Multitudes
129
that it made possible the mathematical analysis of those properties
of sound – loudness and quality – which had theretofore escaped all
scientific representation.11
To be sure, what is described in the introduction to the Sectio Canonis
is the “condensed” and “rarefied” motion of a string set into vibration,
a motion that appears to the eye as condensed by being closely packed
or rarefied by being widely spaced; but what is implied in this description is the corresponding pattern of motion in the air itself, that pattern
which Fourier found a way to reproduce graphically. In short, Euclid’s
words “condensation” and “rarefaction” carry in their meaning the
weight of all they imply. For in their meaning, the motion of a plucked
string, for example, is linked to the time during which that motion of
the string transpires. Indeed, without the factor time, there would be
no basis for imputing a greater or lesser density to the motion under
observation. Thus, to arrive at a theorem which would express the loudness of a sound in the amplitude of a sound wave, for example, Fourier
related the displacement of the air molecules in motion to the time of
their travel from the point of origin, just as one would relate the distance an object falls to the time it takes to fall. In surmising, moreover,
that any musical pitch can be analyzed into discrete components, each
one being a function of the lateral displacement of a string from its initial position and all in concert being time-dependent, Euclid implanted
in this introduction the first of the many signposts it would take to
mark the road to the most dazzling discovery of acoustical physics: the
harmonic analysis by which Fourier determined the components of
periodic vibrational motion and the harmonic synthesis by which he
determined the resultant periodic vibrational motion from a given set
of harmonic components. For with this process of harmonic analysis and
synthesis the tone quality of every musical instrument and every human
voice could be represented in mathematical terms.12
11
12
What Fourier showed is that any periodic vibration, or time-dependent tone,
however complex it might be, is in reality a combination of simple harmonics
whose frequencies are in the ratio of 1:2 : 3:4, etc. Cf. Wood, The Physics of Music,
p. 68; Roederer, Introduction to the Physics and Psychophysics of Music, pp. 103–6.
Fourier’s analysis stands in a remarkable sense as the counterpart of Aristoxenus’
method for dealing with the elements of melody. For where Aristoxenus found
130
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
From the time of Euclid to that of Fourier, there were myriad truths
to be discovered about sound and its complex properties of pitch, loudness, and quality. Euclid succeeded in penetrating into the outer rim
of one such truth – that concerning pitch and its relation to vibratory motion. To codify the laws governing this truth, Euclid began
by observing so distinct a conformity between the visible motion of
a stretched string and the pitch it produces, that the latter, the effect,
seemed precisely to copy the former, its cause. For, as he evidently saw,
the faster a string under tension moves, the higher the pitch it emits
when plucked; the slower its motion, the lower its pitch. Seeing also
that with the simultaneous production of two different pitches, the
faster and slower vibrations, to which these pitches conform respectively, must themselves be occurring over the same period of time,
Euclid deduced that the faster vibrations, if they were to occupy the
same time span as the slower ones, had to be more numerous, and hence
more densely packed, than the slower vibrations producing the lower
pitch. On this basis, he inferred that the vibratory motion productive
of musical pitch consists of discrete parts, the addition or subtraction of
which caused a corresponding rising or lowering of the pitch produced.
He reasoned, therefore, that because all things composed of parts can
be spoken of in terms of the numerical proportions obtaining between
them, musical pitch, because it conforms so precisely in its variations
to the enumerative vibratory motion causing it, ought to admit of a
similar mathematical construal. Euclid was, of course, right; vibratory
motion can be analyzed quantitatively. But the problem for Euclid was
that he had no reliable way of assigning to it the correct numerical
values.
Theoretically speaking, the vibrations of a long string might have
been slow enough for Euclid to count by eye, but practically speaking,
a way to synthesize the discrete series of notes and intervals into a continuum
of one-to-one terms, Fourier found a way of dissolving the continuum formed
by a steady, time-dependent tone into the discrete frequencies of the harmonic
series. He did this by resolving steady tones into a superposition of harmonics whose frequencies are integer multiples (as in note 11) of the fundamental tone. Aristoxenus’ method is discussed in the chapter to follow. Parts of
the present chapter are based upon Levin, “Unity in Euclid’s ‘Sectio Canonis’,”
pp. 430–43.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
131
those of a short string would have been far too fast for his or anyone else’s
eye to compute. With no scientific method for counting the wavelike
parts of a vibrating current, a method that would be discovered only in
the distant future by Marin Mersenne (1588–1648),13 and with no oscilloscope to render those parts visible on a fluorescent screen, Euclid was at
the same disadvantage as an astronomer without a telescope. No appeal
to direct experience was possible. Even if such an appeal were possible, it
would have been unnecessary, since he had in his possession a hypothesis
that was dictated by the facts as given him by nature, even though they
had to be extended beyond their warrant. Its truth consisted in this: the
vibrational frequency of a stretched string is inversely proportional to
its length.14 This meant that the motion responsible for musical pitch is
subject to laws of a mathematical nature. In writing these laws, Euclid
could not, of course, represent the particular pitches with which he was
concerned by numbers derived from the actual events of causal vibration.
There was no way for him to derive the number 440, for example, from
the fact that 440 actual vibrations per second produce the note A, that
note by which the mid-point or mesē of the ancient Greek scale-system
is conventionally represented.15 In short, Euclid was in that blessed state
of ignorance that makes it so easy for a genius to be original.
13
14
15
Mersenne was the first to explain the true relations obtaining between tension
and the frequency of vibration of a stretched string, relations subsequently
codified in ‘Mersenne’s Laws.’ As Mersenne discovered, the frequency of vibration of a stretched string is proportional to the square root of the tension. In
order, therefore, to raise the pitch of a stretched string to an Octave, the tension
exerted on it must be four times greater than that of the lower-pitched string.
See Jeans, Science and Music, pp. 64–65. Cf. Levin, “πλήγη and τάσις in the
Harmonika of Klaudios Ptolemaios,” Hermes 108 (1980), 205–6.
These facts of inverse proportion are an integral part of the Pythagorean
tradition. They are detailed by Nicomachus, the Pythagorean exponent par
excellence, in the tenth chapter of his Manual of Harmonics. See Levin, Manual,
pp. 143–44.
The ancient Greeks’ notion of pitch was not like that of ours: a comparison
with an external standard. Instead, they framed abstract scale-models and
based their transcriptions on the relations between the notes of those scales.
The procedure is explained by Chailley, La musique grecque antique, pp. 76–77.
The scale-model called Systēma Teleion Ametabolon is an example of such a scalemodel, or template, that accommodates the various modes and genera in a
132
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
To obtain results that agreed with the facts of his experience and
observation, Euclid gave precedence to his own powers of inference and
imagination. He based his computations on string-lengths instead of
on vibratory motion and, in the process, was able to describe in his
mathematical theorems – those twenty theorems that succeed the
Introduction to the Sectio Canonis – not the actuality of motion as it
pertains to musical pitch, but rather its correlative symptoms. To do
single unified system. Cf. West, Ancient Greek Music, pp. 222–23. The tables
of all the scale-systems together with their notational symbols are preserved
in the treatise by the otherwise unknown theorist, Alypius, called Introduction
to Music, contained in Jan, pp. 367–406. The method whereby musicologists
translate the Greek scales and pitch formations into modern notation is based
on an equivalence between our A2 and the sign C, which corresponds to the
mesē, or middle note. See Fig. 5: Greater Perfect System. For note 15, Chapter 4:
which depicts the linked tetrachords of the Greater Perfect System (Hypaton
and Meson) and Diezeugmenon and Hyperbolaion, these disjoined from the
first two tetrachords by the whole tone: A–B. It is this disjunction that is a
characteristic feature of the Greater Perfect System. As Fig. 5 shows, the Lesser
Perfect System contains only conjoined tetrachords.
Figure 5. Greater Perfect System: Lesser Perfect System
Magnitudes and Multitudes
133
this, he inverted the numerical proportions which would normally
represent the greater and the lesser speeds of vibration. On his standard then, the larger number represents the greater length of string (of
slower vibration) and the smaller number, the shorter length of string
(of faster vibration). Because the full array of experiential facts involving motion was unavailable to him, Euclid went beyond the empirical
by postulating truths of reason for truths of experience. And under the
former he assembled those propositions of logic and mathematics which
signify relations that are universally valid.
Taken in its entirety, the Sectio Canonis seems bent on giving a
roundly affirmative answer to the question posed in Ps-Aristotle Problems
19.23:
Why is it that nētē is the double of hypatē? First of all, is it because the
string when struck at half its length gives an octave with the string that is
struck at full length?
To frame his answer, Euclid in his Introduction took up one side of
the question, that according to which nētē is thought of as the double
of hypatē, because its string vibrates twice as fast as that of hypatē,
its speed increasing in inverse proportion with its length. To round
out his answer, Euclid’s theorems account for the other side of the
question, that according to which the string of nētē, producing the
faster vibrations, is half as long as that of hypatē, its string length
thus decreasing in inverse proportion with its speed of vibration. But
since the theorems do not mention vibratory motion and the introduction does not mention string-length proportions, we are left to
infer from the numerical ratios that are applicable to one side of the
question – namely, string-length proportions – those properties that
are imagined to be true of the other side of the question – namely,
speed of vibration.16
16
Because the vibration theory, as enunciated in the Introduction, must give the
larger numbers to higher pitches and smaller ones to lower pitches, while the
Propositions assign the numbers the other way round, scholars have seen reason
to question the authenticity of the treatise as a whole. Barker, in his “Methods
and Aims in the Euclidean Sectio Canonis,” JHS (CI), 1981, 1–2, sees evidence
of a missing link: “This anomaly may seem insufficient to justify suspicion. So
it is: it is less a sign of separate authorship than of the existence of a lacuna.
134
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
To be sure, Euclid knew full well that true knowledge should be
positive, that it should not be made up of what is unknown, that it
should be grounded in the fullness of what we do know. The problem
for him was, therefore, to find a knowledge that would surmount the
limitations imposed on him by the reality of vibratory motion. This was
the task he faced: how to establish facts and theorems about a motion
whose speed could not be rationalized in terms of actual numbers, but
could only be imagined in such terms. It required a choice: to think
without appealing to experience, or to imagine with the assistance of
common sense. Euclid chose to do both, by deciding to treat vibratory
motion as mathematics, that is, to substitute for the actual, experienced
world of sound, whose causal factors could not be measured accurately,
a geometric world made real in numbers, the terms of which would
describe the symptoms of vibratory motion as they are imagined to be.
Shifting his focus from frequencies of string vibration to stringlengths as the physical correlates of musical pitch, Euclid arrived at
three types of numerical ratios – multiple, superparticular, and superpartient – that would represent the two types of relations between any
two musical pitches – concordancy and discordancy. He thereupon
postulated that concords, or consonances, correspond only to those
types of ratios that are designated under a single name. And the only
ratios that are designated under a single name are, he says, multiples
and superparticulars. Because the names of the ratios that fall under the
class of multiples and superparticulars express what is a greater unity
between the numerical elements than do the names of the superpartient
class, which leaves the elements discrete and unblended, it should follow that the more unified consonances – such as octaves, fifths, and
fourths – must correspond to those ratios with more unified names.
Accordingly, of the multiple classes of ratios, that which is expressive
of the octave is called by the single name diplasios (2:1), that which is
expressive of the octave and a fifth is called by the single name triplasios
(3:1), and that which is expressive of the double octave is called by the
single name, tetraplasios (4:1). Of the superparticular class of ratios, that
What is missing is a way of relating the primary ratios of movements to the
reversed ratios of the lengths of strings.” Cf. Tannery, “Inauthenticité de la
‘Division du Canon’ attributée à Euclide,” 213–19.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
135
which is expressive of the fifth is called hemiolios (3:2) and that which is
expressive of the fourth is called epitritos (4:3).17
As Euclid readily acknowledged in his Introduction, what is known
must be derived initially from the ear’s own perception. In other words, the
ear must know in advance of what it hears that which enables it to recognize
as concordant or discordant those relations between the notes that it hears.
It is this knowledge on the part of the ear that requires the canonician to do
exactly what Euclid has described in his Introduction. This is to increase or
decrease the rate of vibration of a string until the pitch produced arrives at
the level which the ear accepts as proper. Clearly, then, the ear must know
in advance of what it hears how an octave or a fifth or a fourth should sound.
Otherwise, an adjustment of the sort detailed by Euclid would not be
needed to satisfy the ear’s expectations. Recognizing this necessity, Euclid
gave the ear its proper priority in the canonic enterprise; but he did so just
long enough for that knowledge, which only the ear can provide, to set into
motion that irresistible engine of truth – mathematical reasoning. From
that point on, Euclid did what every orthodox Pythagorean would have
done under the circumstances: he dispensed with the testimony of the ear
and introduced mathematical reasoning as an independent criterion that is
authorized to work on its own initiative.
By taking this strictly Pythagorean approach, Euclid was led to build
his Sectio Canonis on assumptions that Aristoxenus felt compelled to call
into question. For the moment that Euclid bypassed the evidence of the
ear and licensed reason to equate musical consonances with certain kinds
of ratios, he began to entangle the melodic elements in a maze of stubborn facts. And although these facts may be geometric marvels in their
own right and completely acceptable, if not delightful, on the grounds
of pure mathematics, they can contradict the ear’s testimony in surprising ways. Indeed, the ear’s peculiar knowledge consists not merely in
17
Barker (note 16), 2, explains the situation in these terms: “Whereas, in Greek,
superpartient ratios such as 5:3 can only be designated by compound expressions like ‘five to three’, there is a one-word name for every ratio in the other
two classes. . . . Of the superparticulars, the ratio 3:2 bears the special name
‘hemiolos’, that is, ‘half-whole’, while all the others bear names generated by
adding the prefix ‘epi-’ to an ordinal adjective.” On the problems raised by
Euclid’s “one name” requirement for concordancy, see also Barbera, The
Euclidean Division of the Canon, pp. 55–58. See Fig. 2.
136
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
its ability to discriminate between consonances and dissonances or to
distinguish one pitch from another; its more remarkable capacity lies
in its ability to interpret what it discriminates as melodious or not and
thus to find what it interprets as completely acceptable or not – and
even delightful or not – on the ground of the purely musical. In short,
hearing, like seeing, is not simply a passive process by which the ear
duplicates meaningless sensations that it has no power to interpret. On
the contrary, the great power of the ear, as all musicians know, is to construe forms out of the raw data given it. And once supplied with these
forms, musical reason is then prepared to discover the strictly musical intelligibility in the melodies that the ear is framed to understand.
This blending together of what is in effect musical intuition (synesis)
and empiricism made for an explosive combination in the mind of
Aristoxenus; it also made for a radical departure from the Pythagorean
method as exemplified in the Sectio Canonis.
Unity was presumably the common feature by which Euclid related
the musical consonances to certain kinds of ratios. To conceive of the intervals of melody as being, on this or on some similar basis, the same as the
ratios of numbers may perhaps answer a natural aptitude on the part of the
human mind to see all things as fundamentally the same – whether they
are seen to be the same as water, as with Thales, or air, as with Anaximenes,
or fire, as with Heraclitus, or an infinite, eternal primal substance, as with
Anaximander, or number, as with the Pythagoreans. In the case of the
Pythagoreans, certainly, their failure to represent the facts of audition faithfully stems from their unguarded use of a principle of unity that is present
solely in the mind. It is, therefore, Euclid’s predilection for fitting the
harmonic relations into a preconceived mathematical pattern on the basis
of such a principle that makes his Sectio Canonis so typically Pythagorean.
Paradoxically, though, the more Euclid proceeded as a pure mathematician in this effort, the farther he removed himself from the material he was
treating. And the less enslaved he was to the material he was treating, the
more he could, like a composer of music, be a free creator of his own world
of ordered beauty, one that differs from that of music by belonging to a
world of facts as opposed to a world of becoming.18
18
This notion comes from Aristotle Post. An. 100a6–9, in which he explains the
universal as the one that corresponds to the many, which provides the starting
Magnitudes and Multitudes
137
Of all the relations between two notes, unisons, or isotones, were for
the Pythagoreans the exemplars of unity, because the ratio by which
they are represented on the canon, namely 1:1, is, itself, of all the
relations between two terms, the epitome of unity. For there is no interval between the respective terms of either relation – the mathematical
or the melodic. That being the case, the Pythagoreans had a basis for
comparing the equality of distances on the canon, or ruler, with all
the melodic intervals of identical pitch (isotones). And if that comparison held true, they could, on the same basis, compare the inequality of
distances on the canon with melodic intervals of different pitch (anisotones). They saw, therefore, that in the case of unequal distances the
ratios of the terms involved certain characteristic differences, and they
assumed that where the relations between notes of different pitch were
concerned, characteristic differences of a comparable sort should obtain.
It is on this line of reasoning that the Sectio Canonis is framed.
Given this line of reasoning, of all the relations between unequal
terms, double ratios had to have been considered by Euclid and the
Pythagoreans the very best, on the obvious grounds that they come
closest to the unity that is epitomized in the ratio 1:1. This is because
it is only in the double ratio that the excess of one number over the
other is equal to the original number. And because the double ratio is
representative of that relation in which string-lengths productive of the
octave stand to one another, it followed for the Pythagoreans and Euclid
that the octave had to be the most consonant of all the intervals between
notes of different pitch. In this instance, they had the full concurrence of
the ear; for of all the melodic elements, the octave is that which sounds
to the ear most like the unison. To follow this Pythagorean hypothesis to
its logical conclusion, then, the closer to unity or oneness the relations
between string lengths are to one another, the closer to a unison will be
any anisotone that is produced; and, by contrast, the farther from unity
the relations of string lengths are to one another, the farther from a unison will be any anisotone that is produced. One need only add to this line
of thought that the farther from an isotone any melodic interval turns out
to be, the more dissonant it will sound to the ear. Thus, if distances on
point of art and science: art, if it pertains to the world of becoming, science, if
it pertains to the world of facts.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
138
a canon are defined by being a class of one-to-one relations with certain
mathematically assignable properties, then the melodic elements for
which they stand must themselves belong to a similar class of one-toone relations with certain melodically assignable properties.19
Armed with such an hypothesis, Euclid and the Pythagoreans could
dispense with the ear’s testimony altogether, for the numerical ratios
derived from the division of the canon told them all they needed to
know.20 With the best of Pythagorean intentions, then, Euclid directed
his efforts in the Sectio Canonis to the establishment of certain truths about
the canonic ratios without taking into account the facts of perception
to which they apply. Instead, it was solely from the mathematical properties of the straight line – the canonic symbol par excellence – that
Euclid inferred the concordant and discordant properties of the melodic
elements. Given this approach, it could not but be that what was true
of the canonic ratios would be true of the melodic elements also. This
meant that if a certain property such as divisibility was the outstanding
19
20
Barbera (note 17), pp. 52–54, calls this line of reasoning the Fundamental
Principle of Consonance, a principle that is the “central tenet of the Pythagorean
musical creed.”
The truth to be derived solely from the numerical ratios is elegant in its simplicity: the smaller the numbers in the ratios, the greater the concordancy; and,
conversely, the larger the numbers in the ratios, the greater the discordancy. To
this day, no one has been able fully to explain why this is so. Thus Jeans, Science
of Music, p. 154: “And though many attempts have been made to answer it, the
question is not fully answered yet.” The truth lies in the following relations:
Interval
Unison
Octave
Fifth
Fourth
Major Third
Major Sixth
Minor Third
Minor Sixth
Major Second
Minor Second
Ratio
1:1
2:1
3:2
4:3
5:4
5:3
6:5
8:5
9:8
19 :18
Largest Number
1
2
3
4
5
5
6
8
9
19
Magnitudes and Multitudes
139
feature of a particular ratio such as 4:1, the same property could be
posited of the melodic interval to which that ratio corresponds. The
interval in this case is the double octave. It is this divisibility that is at
the heart of Euclid’s Proposition 1 of the Sectio Canonis. This is Euclid at
work (the letters B, G, and D refer to points on a line):21
If a multiple interval when doubled forms a certain interval, this too will be a
multiple interval. Let there be the interval B G and let B be a multiple of G;
and let B be to D as G is to B. I say, then, that D is a multiple of G. For since
B is a multiple of G, G therefore measures B. But as G was to B as B was to D,
the result is that G measures D also. Therefore, D is a multiple of G.
The proposition may be diagrammed as follows:
D
8
B
4
G
2
This means that 8:4 :: 4:2; the double octave is therefore divisible.
By contrast, if indivisibility is the outstanding feature of a particular
ratio such as 3:2, the same property could be posited of the melodic
interval to which that ratio corresponds, namely, the fifth. Using the
geometric method in Proposition 3, Euclid proved that between any two
distances on the straight line that are in the ratio of 3:2, there is no number that will fall at the proportional mean between the one distance and
the other. For such a number would be less than the one distance and
greater than the other. The same thing holds true of the melodic interval, the fifth: there is no note in Pythagorean tuning that will divide the
interval into two identical halves. As Euclid proved, this is an impasse
that arises from the fundamental laws of mathematics, which musicians are powerless to change. The problem of the fourth in the superparticular ratio of 4:3 is the same as that with the fifth. The fourth is
indivisible for the same reason that the fifth is: no number will fall at
21
Jan, 150. 1–11. Cf. Barker, II, p. 194, n. 9. Barbera, The Euclidean Division of the
Canon, p. 119, explains that here as well as in the Propositions that follow, the
most essential parts of propositions and theorems are exhibited: enunciation,
proof, and conclusion. Cf. Heath, Elements, I. pp. 129–31.
140
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the proportional mean between the two distances on the line (or canon)
that are in the ratio of 4:3. That being the case, the melodic intervals,
fourth and fifth, like the mathematical ratios to which they correspond,
cannot be divided into two equal parts. If, to follow Euclid’s argument,
the property of a ratio be simplicity or the “oneness” that is expressed
in the more unified names by which such ratios are designated, as, for
example, diplasios, the double ratio, then the more unified the name of
the ratio, the more concordant the corresponding melodic interval can
be expected to sound to the ear. And, by the same token, the less unified
the name of the ratio, the less concordant the corresponding melodic
interval must necessarily be. The names of the ratios had therefore a
profound power of suggestion for Euclid, because he had what seemed
to him a firm basis for extending to all melodic relations those very
properties that are expressed in the names of the ratios themselves.22
To the human mind, which delights in uniformity and order, nothing could be more gratifying than these irrefragable mathematical
facts. For it was on the grounds of that unspeakable unity to which
all Pythagorean speculation tends that the names of the ratios could
be applied by Euclid to all logical relations of order, even to those of a
strictly melodic sort.23 Thus, it was that Euclid and the Pythagoreans
came to grief on the empirical fact that what the ear knows for a certainty
to be concordant, the geometry of the straight line confutes utterly on
the basis of its own logical necessity. By contrast, what ought to have
been incontrovertibly concordant on the basis of that same necessity of
mathematical logic, turned out on occasion to be distinctly discordant
to the ear. If the Pythagoreans were aware, as they must have been, of
22
Thus Lippmann, Musical Thought in Ancient Greece, p. 154: “Consonant tones . . .
are sounds that unite and mix together, or mutually blend; consonance is the
creation of a common character or a common principle. But in the Pythagorean
view, the auditory manifestation is in essence numerical; accordingly, Euclid
postulates that the consonant sounds are in ratios that are either multiple or
superparticular (2:1 or 3:2, for example), since only such ratios can be designated (in Greek) by a single word; like two consonant tones, their constituent
numbers also unite in a common character!”
23 As Lippmann (note 22) emphasizes with his exclamation point, the correspondences that Euclid alleges between the technical names and the sounds have no
aptness in languages other than ancient Greek.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
141
such discrepancies between the ear’s apprehensions and mathematical
logic, they suffered no real uneasiness on finding that the abstract connections they made between numerical ratios and melodic intervals had
such incongruous consequences. Quite the contrary; they proceeded, as
did Euclid, by ignoring those discrepancies that were all too obvious to
musicians, or else they simply charged the ear with being aberrant. As
they saw it, their theory had to be right, however much the ear might
hold it to be wrong, because their theory was one which had been discovered by reason itself (logos). And reason could not be the origin of
imperfect knowledge. Euclid saw nothing objectionable, therefore, in
asserting that concordant melodic intervals are designated by simple
names, whether they be in multiple or superparticular relations.
From the very beginning, the Pythagoreans had pledged themselves
to give mathematically true demonstrations of everything – every
proportion in the heavens and on earth that is magnified in the logic
of lines and angles, the long lines of every human and planetary law,
whatever the direction and however far afield they might extend. The
Pythagoreans had no use for mere probabilities; indeed, they made it
a cardinal point that number was all and that mathematical reasoning
was, as its agent, simple, permanent, uniform, and self-existent. Where
number is right, all sciences of number are bound to be right. With
number the Pythagoreans held a copyright on the world, and this conviction commended them to men of thought, to such men as Euclid.
The numbers in Euclid’s Sectio Canonis are, of course, mathematically
right. The problem is that Euclid’s generalizations, based as they are on
the geometry of the straight line, have the unavoidable consequence of
disagreeing with the testimony of the ear. For, on the ear’s reckoning,
not all the multiples are ratios of concords; and neither do all the concords belong to the class of multiple and superparticular ratios only, nor
do all superpartient relations on the canon yield discords, as would be
expected from Euclid’s statement.
To begin with, then, two distances on the canon in the multiple ratio
of 5:1 gives not an expected concord but an interval that was not only
accounted by the ancients to be discordant but one that did not even have
a place in their scale systems: the double octave and a major third. Yet
another exception to the rule of concordancy crops up in the case of the
superparticular ratio, 5:4, this producing not a concord, as prescribed by
142
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Euclid, but an interval which the ancients construed to be discordant: the
major third. In addition, the ratio, 9:8, being of the class of superparticulars,
does not yield an expected concord, but the discordant whole-tone interval.
Moreover, two distances on the canon in the superpartient relation of 8:3
gives not an expected discord, but that interval which the ear registers as an
indisputable concord: the eleventh, or an octave and a fourth, that interval
by which the scale system called Lesser Perfect is circumscribed.24
In the final analysis, the Sectio Canonis appeals essentially to the eye.
Its various comparisons between distances on the canon can be put down
on paper for everyone to measure visually. And when it enlists the aid
of mathematics, the symbols by which these distances on the canon are
represented can themselves be verbally expressed. Thus, for example,
in Proposition 6, to prove that all such distances in a double relation are
composed of the two greatest superparticulars, Euclid puts the numbers
standing for the distances in question in the following relations:25
a:b:c
12 : 8 : 6
24
The Lesser Perfect System, or Systēma Teleion Elasson, comprises three conjoined
tetrachords. Its contradiction of the Pythagorean and Euclidean theory of concords was noticed early on by Ptolemy Harmonics I. 6 (Düring, 13–15): “Such
being the hypothesis of the Pythagoreans concerning the consonances, the
octave and a fourth which is quite clearly a consonance, puts out of countenance
the ratio fitted to it by them.” As Ptolemy has it, the ratio 8:3 is itself insulted
by the discrepancy. The discrepancy so noted by Ptolemy has occasioned much
discussion among scholars. Barker in his “Methods and Aims in the Euclidean
Sectio Canonis,” 9ff, argues that the criterion by which any interval is judged
to be concordant or discordant is acoustic, not mathematical. He goes on to
conclude that “From this point of view the disqualification of the octave plus
a fourth is plainly illegitimate.” Euclid’s failure to mention the octave and a
fourth at all indicates how far the Pythagoreans were prepared to go in placing
reason (logos) over perception (aisthēsis) as the final arbiter of intervallic quality.
Opposing views on the question of the octave and a fourth are presented by
Barbera, “Placing Sectio Canonis,” 161, who observes that “The consonant character of the octave plus a fourth . . . is in no way certain, and the issue was hotly
debated in musical treatises throughout antiquity and the Middle Ages.” See
Fig. 5: Lesser Perfect System.
25 Jan, 154. 15–155. 22. This proposition consists of two parts, the first of which
is geometrically conceived as given here.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
143
Given this arrangement, a stands to b in the hemiolic ratio of 3:2 and b
stands to c in the epitritic ratio of 4:3. Therefore,26
2a=3b
3b=4c
2a=4c
a = 2 c
To interpret such a complex, one uses words such as hemiolic and epitritic
to express what are the two largest components of the double ratio. The
question is, however, what in fact has been interpreted when one uses
such technical language? Not the formal elements of melody, certainly,
because these, on Aristoxenus’ conception especially, cannot stand still
long enough to be embraced by such interpretations. What is being interpreted here instead are the formal elements of arithmetic and geometry.
The geometry of the Sectio Canonis is strictly metrical. The class of
relations that it analyzes is called diastēma, or interval, the outstanding
property of which is the single dimension it occupies, namely, the straight
line. If the notes of melody are conceived of as points on a straight line
forming a continuous series, then the distances between these points must
be a continuous series also. What is required for the measurement of these
distances is, therefore, number. That being the case, the elements of melody
can be translated into points and lines on one dimension and interpreted
in the discursive language of mathematics. The assumption that any two
commensurable magnitudes on a straight line can find their equivalent in
a corresponding interval between two musical pitches is that on which the
geometric method of the Sectio Canonis is based. Limiting himself, therefore,
to those relations prescribed by the geometry of the straight line, Euclid
succeeded in calculating the mathematical ratios to which the various distances on the canon correspond. This done, he proceeded to explore the
inherent properties of the ratios themselves and thereby revealed certain discrepancies between the melodic elements and the geometry of the straight
line. The most telling of these discrepancies is that the octave is less than six
whole-tones, a mathematical fact of enormous implications in music.27
26
27
This is a representation of the second part of Proposition 6, in which the proof
is rendered arithmetically. Cf. Barker, II, p. 197, n. 17.
Euclid’s proof is given in the ninth and last mathematical Proposition of the
Sectio Canonis, which states: “Six epogdoic [whole-tone] intervals are greater
144
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Euclid kept an intentionally tight rein on his subject, allowing nothing to impede his progress from pure mathematics to canonics, or applied
mathematics. To this end, he divided his twenty Propositions into problems
and theorems: the problems of Propositions 1 to 9, being strictly mathematical, concern the generation, division, subtraction, and addition of intervals, or distances on the canon; the theorems of Propositions 10 to 20, being
strictly harmonic, exhibit the melodic attributes of these same distances
on the stretched string of the canon. From Propositions 10 to 20, Euclid
thus applied his mathematical conclusions to the musical facts – that is, to
the distances between the musical notes, whose names he now introduced
for the first time.28 In Proposition 10, for example, he applied to the melodic
elements those facts that he had proved mathematically in Proposition 1:
“If a multiple interval is doubled and forms an interval, it, too, will be a
than one double interval [octave].” This is found in Jan, 157. 5–14. The application of this proof to harmonic analysis is given in Proposition 14 (Jan, 160.
20–161. 3), which states: “The octave is less than six whole-tones.” Since a
whole-tone ratio is 9:8, the six whole-tones of the octave form a progression
such that to the number assigned to the first one there is added an eighth
of that number, and so on successively to the completion of the octave. For
example, if the first assigned number is 64, then (64+64
–8 =8)=72.
The end result of this process will be a number that exceeds the limits of
the double ratio. As Barker, II, p. 199, note 22 explains it: “Each number
must be such that one ninth of it is a whole number.” Thus, one ninth of 72
is the whole number 8. The method of proof is given also in Euclid’s Elements,
Book VII, Proposition 2. These proofs are adamant. Yet Aristoxenus, in the face
of them, remained unshaken in his belief that six whole-tones are exactly equal
to an octave. This gives some indication of the value that he placed on his ear’s
perception.
28 The Greek nomenclature is considered, even by classicists, to be forbidding.
But, on examination, it turns out to be no more complex than, and just as
systematic as, the modern terms: tonic, supertonic, mediant, subdominant,
dominant, submediant, subtonic. The Greek names are derived from the position of the strings on the tilted lyre and, with the exception of lichanos, or forefinger, are adjectives modifying chordē. Relative to the performer, in ascending
pitch they are: (hypatē the string of the highest position), which emits the
lowest pitch, parhypatē (next to the highest), lichanos (the string plucked by
the forefinger), mesē (middle), tritē (third from the top), paranētē (next to the
top), nētē (the topmost string, which emits the lowest pitch). See West, p. 64;
pp. 219–20.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
145
multiple interval.” Proposition 10 is designed, therefore, to show how the
melodic elements – those forming the double octave – share the property
of the mathematical formulations in Proposition 1 – those of the multiple
ratio. Accordingly, there is between the note proslambanomenos (A1)29 and
nētē Hyperbolaion (A1) a proportional mean at mesē (A); the entire distance
between these limits cannot be represented by a superparticular proportion, since there is no mean number which falls proportionally between
the limits of the superparticular proportion. The entire distance between
proslambanomenos) (A1) and nētē Hyperbolaion (A1) must consist, therefore, of
two multiple intervals taken together. Of the three distances in question –
which may be represented as AB, BC, AC – one must be the greatest. This
is AC. Then in virtue of the definition, B (mesē) will be fixed between A
(proslambanomenos) and C (nētē Hyperbolaion). Therefore, AB and BC must
be multiple intervals. And this is to bear out the mathematical axiom that
things which are double of the same thing are equal to one another.
Proceeding in this manner, Euclid went on through Propositions 11
to 13 to prove that octaves are composed of fourths and fifths; that
fourths and fifths, being of the superparticular class of ratios, cannot be
divided in half; that if intervals which are not multiples be doubled,
their total will be neither a multiple nor a superparticular and, therefore, not a consonance; that a triple interval is formed from an octave
and a fifth (3:1); that if a fourth be subtracted from a fifth, the left-over
interval is an epogdoic or sesquioctave ratio of 9:8, the ratio of the wholetone. From this point on, that is, from Propositions 14 through 20, the
Sectio Canonis can be read as an unrelenting and meticulously argued
polemic against Aristoxenus’ principles of harmonics. Everything that
Aristoxenus had stated axiomatically about melodic intervals is systematically confuted by Euclid: that the octave consists of six whole-tones;
that the fifth consists of three whole-tones and a semitone; that the fourth
consists of two whole-tones and a semitone; that whole-tones are not
only divisible into two equal semitones, but also into quarter-tones by
which the Enharmonic genus is defined as such, as well as into other
micro-intervals that characterize the various chroai or nuances. In short,
29
On proslambanomenos, the “note added” to the five tetrachords of the Immutable
System, bringing its total range to two octaves. See Fig. 1: Immutable or
Changeless System.
146
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Euclid’s mathematical dismemberment of everything that Aristoxenus
held to be axiomatic about melodic intervals appears to be so pointed
and well targeted that it is hard to believe he did not have Aristoxenus’
work before him when he composed the Sectio Canonis.30
Euclid was, as it happens, only about a generation younger than
Aristoxenus. He is said to have been younger than the first pupils of Plato
(d. 347 b.c.) but older than Archimedes (287–212 b.c.), which would place
his floruit at about 300 b.c. He was apparently not long in winning fame
as a geometer, for his first appearance in the literature of antiquity has
him conversing on familiar terms with one of the most resplendent and
powerful figures of the age – Ptolemy I Soter, who reigned over Egypt
from 306 to 283 b.c. Ptolemy had just asked him if there were not some
shorter route to a knowledge of geometry than through the Elements. “Not
even for a king,” Euclid dared to reply in defense of geometry’s crowned
truths. The time must have been 300 b.c. or thereabouts and Euclid,
established by now in Alexandria, where he founded his own school of
mathematics, was perhaps not much more than thirty years old. His
birthplace is unknown, and no reliable genealogy has come down with
his name. But his chronicle of mathematics’ advancement allows us to
infer something about its author and how different from Aristoxenus he
must have been. For one thing, he seems to have had no quarrel with the
work of his predecessors. On the contrary, he was noticeably respectful of
all that had entered into the mathematical tradition, even to the point of
including for the sake of completeness much that he knew to be of little
current application. Where he himself invented, it was not to controvert
but, rather, to complement past endeavors in the field. His aim was to
offer as complete an account of mathematical science as his talents permitted. His talents rewarded posterity with his Elements, a work of which
it was said in October 1848:31
30
31
On the polemic nature of Euclid’s last few Propositions, see Barker, II, p. 204,
n. 57. Whereas Euclid seems to have had Aristoxenus’ method in mind as
he proceeded to frame his polemic, Aristoxenus, in his turn, seems to have
had Euclid’s method in mind as he proceeded to formulate the third book of
his Harmonic Elements. For in writing the rules of melodic topography in this
book, Aristoxenus adopted a Euclidian style for composing his strictly musical
Propositions and Theorems. Paradoxically, Aristoxenus chose the very style of
Euclid’s Elements to oppose his strictly mathematical method.
Heath, Euclid’s Elements, Volume 1, Preface.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
147
There never has been, and till we see it we never shall believe that there
can be, a system of geometry worthy of the name, which has any material
departures (we do not speak of corrections or extensions or developments) from
the plan laid down by Euclid.
Euclid was original but, unlike Aristoxenus, he never claimed to be
so. Yet, like Aristoxenus, he too could be impatient when he felt that the
assumptions of pure knowledge were being challenged. But that natural
sense of irony, so lacking in Aristoxenus, could encourage him to say for
the benefit of all students to come, what he once had occasion to say to a
student of his own. This student had asked him a question that would be
repeated in one form or another through the ages: “What shall I gain by
learning all this?” “Give him three obols,” Euclid told his servant, “since
his purpose in learning is to make a profit.”32 The student’s reaction may
be surmised. Unlike Aristoxenus, who took such unabashed pride in his
own contributions to knowledge, Euclid seems to have been a paragon of
modesty. He seems also to have had by instinct the fairness and generosity of spirit to advance all who would serve knowledge, neither anticipating by design what their methods and discoveries prefigured, nor
withholding credit when their contributions could enrich mathematics,
even if minimally. He was a man absorbed, not with himself, but with
his work. In fact, his individuality merges so closely with his work as to
vanish in it entirely. As a result, knowledge of Euclid, the person, and
the external circumstances of his life have had to suffer accordingly. Only
the thinker with the objects of his thought appears, the unshakable certainty embedded in the axioms and basic propositions of his mathematics proclaiming what he was and what he meant.
Unattended then by the persona of its author, Euclid’s Elements is concerned solely to document a knowledge – one whose truths it assembled
from the work of many schools of mathematicians that dominated Greek
intellectual life from the time of Pythagoras on. Mobilized for the first
time in a single unified work, these truths represent nature’s objective
realities in such terms as points, lines, angles, circles, triangles, cones,
cubes, and more – terms that do not represent the actual physical objects
of nature but, rather, the concepts abstracted from such objects. The
32
The source of the anecdote is the 5th century a.d. compiler, Stobaeus, Eclogae II.
228. 30 (Wachsmuth).
148
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
stretched string is such an object, and from it may be abstracted the concept of a straight line. When Euclid defined a mathematically straight
line, therefore, as a line which lies evenly with the points on itself, the
extremities of which are points,33 the abstraction from a stretched string
lying evenly between its fixed ends is obvious enough. That the properties of the stretched string are reflected in the mathematical abstraction
to which it gave rise required only that a string thus stretched be pressed
against a finger-board – as on the ruler of the canon – at any point whatever and plucked accordingly. Because any alteration, however slight, at
the point of finger-pressure produces a corresponding difference in pitch,
a single string can be made to yield a multiplicity of pitches. And so it
came about that the harmonic canon, or monochord, a lute-type instrument, said to have been invented by Pythagoras himself, was favored by
specialists like Euclid and the Pythagorean harmonicians.34
Euclid’s mathematically driven researches on the canon produced in
the Sectio Canonis a clearly articulated skeleton of the Immutable System
in the Diatonic genus (Proposition 20). He achieved this by locating the
fixed notes, so-called, which form the iron-bound consonantal scaffolding on which the five linked tetrachords of the Immutable or Changeless
System are built. These are the notes that remain fixed at one and the
same pitch, whether the genus be Enharmonic, Chromatic, or Diatonic.
The names of the five tetrachords are defined by these fixed notes to
reflect their position in the Immutable System: Hypaton (lowest), Meson
33
34
Euclid, Elements, I. Definitions 3 and 4.
Nicomachus Manual, 4 (Jan, 243. 14–16) says of the monochords that they
were “commonly called pandouroi but which the Pythagoreans called canons.”
Because the monochord and canon were, like modern guitars, provided with
a finger-board upon which marks (like frets) could be placed, indicating the
measurements of string length required for the production of desired pitches,
they were ideally suited for acoustic experiment. Aristides Quintilianus, a theorist of late antiquity, says in his De musica 3. 2 (Winnington-Ingram 97. 3–4)
that Pythagoras’ last words, just before he died, were to exhort his disciples
to use the monochord in their researches. Of the lute-type instruments mentioned by Nicomachus, the pandouros (pandoura) was the most ancient, having
been used by the Egyptians as early as the New Kingdom (c. 1570 b.c.). The
monochord, or canon, is described by Ptolemy Harm. I. 8 (Düring, 18. 1ff.)
in complete detail together with a diagram of its construction. For additional
references, see Levin, Manual, pp. 69–71.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
149
(middle), Synēmmenon (conjoined or linked), Diezeugmenon (disjoined
or unlinked), hyperbolaion (highest). The complete array of these tetrachords, together with their interior pitches – the movable notes,
so-called, because they change in pitch with the changing melodic genera – was computed by Euclid in Proposition 20 using only those ratios
that he had already assigned to the consonances: Double Octave (4:1),
the defining limits of the Immutable System; Octave (2:1), formed by
the two tetrachords, Hypaton and Meson, linked together on the note
mesē, with another note added at the base (proslambanomenos); Fifth (3:2),
formed by the tetrachord Meson and the whole-tone disjoining it from
tetrachord Diezeugmenon; Fourth (4:3), forming the boundary limits of
each tetrachord.35
Using the ratio of the whole-tone interval that is left over on the
subtraction of the Fourth from the Fifth – 9:8 – Euclid went on to
locate the two whole-tones in each tetrachord of the Immutable System:
the one that intervenes between the moveable notes parhypatē (next
to the lowest note) and lichanos (finger-note) of the lowest tetrachord
(Hypaton); that intervening between lichanos and mesē, the lowest note
of the middle tetrachord (Meson); that intervening between tritē (the
third note from the highest) and paranētē (next to the highest) in the
conjoined tetrachord (Synnēmmenon); that intervening between tritē
and paranētē in the disjoined tetrachord Diezeugmenon; that intervening
between paranētē (next to the highest note) and nētē (the highest note)
in both the disjoined and the highest (Hyperbolaion) tetrachords. In this
35
The guiding note is mesē, the middle note (A), and the paradigmatic scale
formed in relation to mesē has the same structure as the modern key of A natural minor (i.e., minus the G♯). This paradigmatic scale, or template, was the
ancient Hypodorian. Cf. Chailley, La musique grecque antique, p. 79. The addition of the tetrachord Synnēmenon, whose linkage to mesē provided a critical
note (B♭ C D), made for a range of an eleventh, an octave and a fourth. See note
24. According to Ptolemy Harm. II. 6 (Düring, 55. 19–22), the modulation
(metabolē) effected by this linking tetrachord presents the ear with an unexpected melodic deviation of the “very finest” sort, if it be properly managed.
In modern terms, such a deviation is comparable to a modulation from C
Major to F Major and was considered by the ancients as particularly melodic
(emmelēs).
150
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
way, Euclid marked out on the canon all those divisions that define the
Immutable System in the Diatonic genus.36
Euclid’s purpose in setting out these metrical divisions on the
canon was twofold: to reinstate all the facts that he had developed in
Propositions 17–19; to prove that the location of the interior, or moveable, notes of any tetrachord can be determined with mathematical
certainty in one melodic genus only – the Diatonic. This disclosure
of Proposition 20 was in all respects a carefully measured refutation of
Aristoxenus’ teachings on the divisions of the tetrachord.37 For, according to Aristoxenus, any division of the tetrachord was possible as long
as it was melodically intelligible. And for this to be so, it was necessary,
and even mandatory at times, to ignore the canonic rules for locating
the moveable notes of the tetrachords. Directly inspired by mathematics then, Euclid assembled the facts of Propositions 17–19, which lead
inexorably – and almost insolently – to the sharply etched disclosures
of Proposition 20. To accomplish this full-scale attack on Aristoxenus,
Euclid unabashedly used the very method that Aristoxenus himself had
invented for locating the moveable notes, a method which Aristoxenus
called “Intervals ascertained by the principle of Concord.”38 Nor was
that all. The genus on which Euclid focused for this purpose was the one
36
37
The whole-tones in question are C–D, F–G, B♭–C, and, an octave higher, C–D
and F–G. They appear in the tetrachords as follows:
Harm. El. I . 24 (Da Rios, 31. 1). Euclid’s point here was apparently to prove
that ascertaining intervals by the principle of concords cannot determine the
enharmonic quarter-tone with any exactitude. Aristoxenus was, as it happens,
fully aware of this problem. For he is quoted by Ps.-Plutarch De mus. Ch. 38,
1145B (Ziegler–Pohlenz, p. 32. 4–7) as saying: “Then, too, there is the impossibility of determining the magnitude [of the quarter-tone] by concords, as can
be done with the semi-tone, the whole-tone, and the rest of the intervals.”
38 Harm. El. I. 23 (Da Rios, 29, 14–16): “That there is a type of melodic composition requiring a ditone lichanos [a lichanos distant from mesē by a Major Third] and
that far from being most contemptible, but indeed probably the most beautiful
Magnitudes and Multitudes
151
which Aristoxenus had proclaimed, against all canonic dictates, to be
the most noble of all the melodic genera – the Enharmonic.
What conferred an especial nobility on the Enharmonic genus was,
in Aristoxenus’ view, the prominence that it gave to the ditone, or major
third, an interval that he felt to be particularly beautiful in the context
of the Enharmonic tetrachordal division.39 To bring this about, that is, to
bring the ditone into moving prominence, it was necessary that parhypatē
be a quarter-tone (diesis) distant from hypatē. Euclid begins his attack,
therefore, in Proposition 17 by showing that while the ditone is formed
of two whole-tones and is mathematically expressible in the ratio 81:64,
there is no way to divide the whole-tone itself into equal halves by the process of tuning by consonances described in Proposition 18. That being the
case, there can be no mathematically secure way of representing the diesis,
or quarter-tone, of the Enharmonic genus. According to Euclid then, the
furthest one can go in dividing the canon accurately is as follows:
style, is not at all evident to most people who concern themselves with music
today; yet, it might become evident to them if they were given examples of it.”
39 These are the ratios arrived at by Plato in Timaeus 36A1–B5. On Plato’s elaboration of the full diatonic scale, see Levin, The Harmonics of Nicomachus, pp. 89–91.
152
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
An added (and unlovely) consequence of these computations is obtained
on the subtraction of two whole-tones (81:64) from the Fourth (4:3),
this being the semi-tone which the Pythagoreans called leimma, the
“leftover” 256:243, approximated by modern acousticians to 19:18.
The Diatonic tetrachord had theretofore to be computed as:40
The Chromatic tetrachord was omitted by Euclid from his calculations
presumably because its two semitones were subject to the same mathematical afflictions as those befalling the Diatonic leimma, and could
speak for themselves in these terms:
40
From the time of Philolaus and Plato on, these unruly ratios provoked an almost
endless array of rationalizations and correspondences for numerologists to ponder. For example, Philolaus extracted from these relations the number 27, a number of great cosmic significance in the Timaeus and the Republic. For 272 is the
number of days and nights of the year. According to Boethius De inst. mus. 278.
11ff.), Philolaus derived the number 27 from his efforts to divide the whole-tone.
Computing the whole-tone as 243 : 216 (= 9: 8), and subtracting 216 from 243
(= 27), Philolaus proceeded to halve 27 and found 13 and 14, which he called
diesis and apotome, respectively. Subtracting 13 from 14, he found the comma (= 1)
and halving the comma, he found the schisma (= ½). He could have gone on to
infinity without finding intervals of equal size, even as Aristoxenus maintained.
Cf. Frank, Plato und die sogenannten Pythagoreer, pp. 263–76.
Magnitudes and Multitudes
153
Finally, in the Enharmonic tetrachord, as detailed by Aristoxenus, the
division of the semitone by the parhypatai and the tritai into two equal
quarter-tones was shown by Euclid to be mathematically anomalous:41
Aristoxenus had two things to say about all such computations as these.
One has already been mentioned but bears repeating here. Speaking of
some of his predecessors, who can only be the Pythagorean mathematicians, he says: 42
For some of these introduced extraneous reasoning and, rejecting the senses as
inaccurate, fabricated rational principles, asserting that height and depth of
pitch consist in certain numerical ratios and relative rates of vibration – a theory
utterly extraneous to the subject and quite at variance with the phenomena.
His second observation seems to have been aimed directly at Euclid
himself:43
It is usual in geometric constructions to use such a phrase as “Let this be a
straight line”; but one must not be content with such language of assumption in the case of intervals. The geometrician makes no use of his faculty
of sense-perception.
As for all else, Aristoxenus simply ignored all computations such as those
of Euclid, not because they were untrustworthy, but because they were
irrelevant. Failing therefore to agree with Euclid and the Pythagoreans
as to how mathematics could be made useful to the study of melody, he
proceeded with the view that it should at least be made harmless.
41
42
43
Harm. El. II. 33 (Da Rios, 42. 13–17).
Harm. El. II. 32 (Da Rios, 41. 19–42.3).
Harm. El. II. 32 (Da Rios, 41. 19–42.3).
5 The Topology of Melody
A solution was still to seek.
Jane Austen
music seems always to have provided philosophers, physicists,
and cosmologists with an ideal image of the universe in action. To
Pythagoras, the whole cosmos was a musical domain, the moving planets
acting as the physical surrogates of musical notes, the spaces between
these notes defined by harmonic boundaries indelibly etched in the fabric
of the heavens. The musical space in this domain was in no sense understood as metaphorical; on the contrary, it was perceived to be as real
as the movements of the planets themselves. In a giant leap from earth
to heaven, Plato made of these planetary notes and the spaces between
them a mathematically realized diatonic scale covering four octaves and
a major sixth. This, he said, was the work of the Demiurge; and this, his
masterpiece, was the World-Soul defined.1
With the Demiurge’s archetypal scale now fixed to a mathematical certainty, the study of the harmonic truths embedded in this scale
had to lead to a direct understanding of the physical structure of the
entire universe. Ptolemy applied these truths to astronomy and astro
logy, thereby wedding his own geocentric planetary system to the
1
See Chapter 1, note 29. As Taylor says in his Commentary on the Timaeus of Plato,
p. 140: “The compass of Plato’s progression is much greater than any which
was employed in contemporary music.” The Immutable System of Music (for
which, see Fig. 1) did not exceed two octaves. But Plato was not constructing
a scale for humans; rather, his was for the “unheard melody” of the universe, a
melody always in evolution, with no real beginning and no certain ending. On
Plato’s method, see Brumbaugh, Plato’s Mathematical Imagination, pp. 227–29.
154
The Topology of Melody
155
numerical ratios determining the musical consonances. As Ptolemy
saw it, if the musical consonances are numerical in origin, then the
astrological symmetry, because it involves the same numerical ratios
as those of the consonances, must itself be a perfect analogue of the
musical domain.2
The proof of Ptolemy’s hypothesis lay in the natural divisions
between the constellations of the zodiac that mark the yearly path of
the sun through the heavens. To Ptolemy, these constellations stood as
signs marking off twelve equal sectors of the ecliptic, or apparent circle
described by the sun, a circle whose plane intersects that of the equator
and forms with it an angle of 23° 30′.3 He was impressed by the fact
that just as the zodiac is divided by nature into twelve equal sectors,
so too is the two-octave Greater Perfect System of music constituted
of twelve whole-tones which, if not exactly equal, are approximately
so.4 To show how the zodiac and the double-octave are comparable,
Ptolemy instructs us to bend the double-octave of musical theory
into a circle by conjoining nētē Hyperbolaion (A1, the highest note of
the system) to proslambanomenos (A1, the lowest note of the system).
For when these two notes are united, the one, proslambanomenos, and
the other, nētē Hyperbolaion, now locked together, are seen to lie diametrically opposite to mesē (A, the middle note of the Greater Perfect
System).5 In this way, Ptolemy showed that the octave, the most perfect
consonance, has properties equivalent to those of the circle, the most
2
Thus Barker, II, p. 274: “He [sc. Ptolemy] traces the ways in which the mathematical relations underlying the structures of audible music also constitute
the ‘forms’ that are the essence and cause of perfection in other domains, in the
human soul and in the movements and configurations of the stars.”
3 On the discovery by Anaximander of the ecliptic’s obliquity, see Heath, Greek
Astronomy, pp. xxxvii–xxxviiii; cf. Dicks, Early Greek Astronomy, pp. 157ff.
4 Ptolemy Harm. III. 9 (Düring, 103. 13–104. 2): “the two-octave perfect system, being approximately equal to twelve whole-tones (δώδεκα τόνων ἔγγιστσ),
the whole-tone interval was adapted to the twelfth part of the circle.” See Fig. 6.
Aries and Libra are usually placed on the diameter; I have given precedence here
to the notes A1 and A1, thus realigning the constellations. For a more conventional representation, see McClain, The Pythagorean Plato, p. 151, Fig. 48.
5 Ptolemy Harm. III. 8 (Düring, 101. 20) observes that mesē, the middle note of
the perfect system, is the source (archē) of the circle’s equality by being at its
very center. This is diagrammed by Barker, II, p. 382.
156
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
perfect geometric figure. Or, as Ptolemy says, the circle, by virtue of its
component parts, bears a marked resemblance to the octave. Ptolemy
says accordingly:6
If one bends the double octave around into a circle in keeping with its function, and attaches the Hyperbolaion [nētē Hyperbolaion] to proslambanomenos,
making the two notes into one, such an attachment will clearly stand diametrically opposite to mesē, and will be relative to it [mesē] in the homophone of an octave. The rationale for the comparison as described consists in
the fact that there occurs a near likeness between the diameter on the circle
and the attributes displayed in the octave.
With the double-octave now bent into a circle, the position of mesē
relative to the conjoined notes, proslambanomenos and nētē Hyperbolaion, is
seen to be on the line with the diameter of this conceptual circle. This
means that a line drawn from mesē through the diameter of this circle to
the opposing point on its circumference, namely, that of the conjoined
notes, can be represented by the double ratio – or, as Ptolemy says:7 “For it
is in the diameter that the double ratio of the whole circle to the semicircle
is contained.”
Following Ptolemy’s line of reasoning then, if the whole circle of the zodiac
be divided into twelve equal segments of thirty degrees each, with every point
on the circumference of the circle representing a sign of the zodiac, each point
(or sign) will stand to its opposite one on the circumference in the same ratio
as that of an octave.8 Thus, the opposition between any two constellations of
the heavens is as that between the two boundary notes of any octave. Space, as
it appears to the senses, and as it is assumed in astronomy, has, therefore, a real
counterpart, namely, the constitutive elements of the double-octave: twelve
6
7
8
Ptolemy Harm. III. 8 (Düring, 101. 12–18).
Harm. III. 8 (Düring, 101. 18–19).
Harm. III. 8 (Düring, 101, 24–26): “Hence the configurations of stars that are
diametrically opposite one another in the zodiac are the most invigorating [or
‘active’, energetikotatoi] of all of them, as are those among the notes that make an
octave with one another” (trans. Barker). As Barker, II, p. 381, n. 61 points out,
this passage shows “that Ptolemy is prepared to treat the movements and configurations of the heavens both from the point of view of scientific astronomy and
astrologically.”
The Topology of Melody
157
approximately equal whole-tones. On this conception, the Greater Perfect
System of music appears to mirror the universe, there being in evidence a preestablished harmony of opposites between all the constellations of the zodiac:
Aries and Libra ; Pisces and Virgo ; Aquarius and Leo ; Capricorn
and Cancer ; Sagittarius and Gemini ; Scorpio and Taurus .9
Figure 6. The Greater Perfect System Projected on the Zodiac
As is shown in Fig. 6, not even Ptolemy could reconcile this perfect
universal arrangement based on twelve equidistant sectors with the
9
These configurations are most conveniently set out by Jocelyn Godwin,
The Harmony of the Spheres, p. 30, both in linear form as well as on the zodiac.
In this way, Godwin shows in graphic detail that the effect of the constellations is strongest when they are to one another as are the notes of an octave.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
158
melodic framework of the Greater Perfect System of music. For although
the Greater Perfect System does add up to twelve approximately equal
whole-tones, its distribution of these elements is not that of twelve
whole-tones in a sequential order, but a sequence of whole-tones and
semi-tones whose order is dictated by the laws of tetrachordal consecution. Therefore, the moment Ptolemy superimposed the Greater Perfect
System with its own distinctive arrangement of intervals on the circle
of twelve equi-distant degrees, he was bound to confront a series of
discrepancies.10 That being the case, Ptolemy resorted to a strictly geometrical division of the circle. For, inasmuch as twelve is the smallest
number which can be a common denominator for the multiple ratios
1:2 (octave), 1:3 (octave and a fifth), and 1:4 (double octave), Ptolemy
was able to locate by means of these ratios the octave, the fifth and the
fourth on the zodiac. He found the octave, the fifth, and the fourth
each represented on the zodiac three times; the twelfth or octave and a
fifth twice; the eleventh, or octave and a fourth, once; the double-octave
once; and the whole-tone once.11
By mapping the double-octave with its twelve approximately equal
whole-tones on the ecliptic, Ptolemy produced an image of one great
10
A
As Ptolemy has stipulated (note 4), the resolution of these discrepancies consisted in treating the Greater Perfect System as the equivalent of twelve nearly
equal whole-tones. He could thereby “adapt” the fifteen separate pitches of the
two-octave scale to the twelve zodiac positions on the ecliptic. This required
sharping two pitches, C and D, to C♯ and D♯, and flatting one pitch, E, to E♭.
With twelve approximately equal whole-tones now in place, lichanos Hypaton
(D) and hypatē Meson (E) are made to share virtually the same pitch (D♯ = E♭);
the same change appears in the higher octave where paranētē Diezeugmenon (D)
and nētē Diezeugmenon (E) are sharing the almost identical pitches (D♯ = E♭).
This meant that the nearly identical pairs in each octave are allotted to the same
constellation, namely, Cancer and Capricorn, which are diametrically opposite
to one another. The series of whole-tones appears as follows with astrological
symbols:
B
C
D
E�
F
G
A
B
C
D
E�
F
This comports with Aristoxenus’ analysis of the octave constituents.
11 These relations are charted by Godwin (note 9), p. 414, note. Cf.
Ptolemy, p. 156.
G
A
Solomon,
The Topology of Melody
159
recurring scale – a scale as cyclical in nature as the rotation of the sphere
of fixed stars around the axis of the earth. For half of this scale – an
octave – like half of the ecliptic, is at any given moment above the
horizon; while the other half – an octave, also – is below the horizon.
Harmonized in this way, the structural boundaries of the universe are
defined in a single scale of stupendous unity, the cross-sections of which
appear as recurring parts of the unified whole.12 Thus, just as geometry
could succeed in reducing the complex activity of the sun, for example,
to a daily motion and a yearly motion, which appear to be altogether
uniform, so too could Ptolemy’s geometrically induced harmonics interpret all scales, whatever their apparent individuality, as segments of one
and the same harmonically unified system. In this harmonious cosmos,
where every end is a beginning, where there is always another proslambanomenos rising on the ecliptic, no primordial contradiction can dispel
the balance of perfection, and no primordial pain can dwell in the heart
of the primal unity.13 For here the laws of harmonia are granite; they reconcile all seeming discordancies as expressions of one immutable law.
12
13
In Chapters 10, 11, and 12 of his Harmonics III (Düring, 104. 18–107. 18),
Ptolemy correlates three types of stellar movements with three melodic phenomena: continuity, genera, modulation: (1) continuity = the longitudinal
(kata mēkos), which is the diurnal orbit of the fixed stars and planets around
the earth, wherein the Sun moves from East to West; (2) genera = the vertical
(kata bathos), literally, motion “in depth,” or planetary epicycles wherein each
planet appears to approach the earth and then to recede from it; (3) modulation
= the lateral movements (kata platos), literally, motion “in breadth” or the planetary declinations as they move through the zodiac from Cancer in the North
to Capricorn in the South, thus moving away from the powerful tonal center
that is the celestial equator. Cf. Godwin (note 9), p. 414, note 18; Barker, II,
p. 384, note 71. Bruce Stephenson, The Music of the Heavens, p. 36: “The sounds
described in all this seem to be essentially a low tone as the planet rises in the
east, ascending to a high tone when the planet culminates, and then descending again until the planet sets in the west.” See also, Liba Chaia Taub, Ptolemy’s
Universe, p. 128.
The reference here is to F. Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy in The Philosophy
of Nietzsche, p. 979: “Language can never adequately render the cosmic symbolism of music, because music stands in symbolic relation to the primordial
contradiction and primordial pain the heart of the Primal Unity, and therefore
symbolizes a sphere which is beyond and before all phenomena.”
160
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Ptolemy’s solution to cosmic truth by way of music produced
a geometrical masterpiece – a complex and elegant edifice of cycles
and epicycles that explained the irregularity of planetary motion to
the satisfaction of astronomers for fourteen centuries, until Nicholas
Copernicus dismantled it in 1543 with the publication of his De revolutionibus orbium coelestium. For Copernicus, just as for Ptolemy, the universe appeared as a system of concentric spheres in which the sphere of
fixed stars contained all the others, but with this difference: the sun,
and not the earth, as with Ptolemy’s system, occupied the center of
the universe.14 Additional facts drawn from observation and confirmed
by experiment, as by Giordano Bruno (1548–1600), Galileo Galilei
(1564–1642), and Tycho Brahe (1546–1601), would ultimately bring
down Ptolemy’s radiant mirror of the macrocosm.15 It was only the
harmonic astronomy of Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) that prevented
it from being shattered under the superincumbent weight of scientific
skepticism.
Kepler’s interest in Ptolemy’s many analogies between music and the
heavens was aroused when he was still a youth in his early twenties. This
was not because of any innate tendency toward mysticism or heliolatry on
14
15
On Ptolemy’s geocentric model of the universe, the Sun is construed to be as
mobile as all the planets: but on the heliocentric model, the Sun is construed to
be as immobile as the fixed stars. Cf. J. V. Field, Kepler’s Geometrical Cosmology,
p. 17. On Copernicus’ spherical universe, see Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution,
pp. 145–50.
Bruno advanced the hypothesis – most remarkable in his day – that the stars
are really Suns and that their extension in the universe is infinite. See Field
(note 14), p. 77. Almost a hundred years after Copernicus displaced the Earth
by placing the Sun in the center of the universe, it was still possible for Galileo
to be condemned to death for confirming with his telescopic observations
the heliocentric hypothesis of Aristarchus (c. 310–230 b.c.) as well as that
of Copernicus. Cf. Merleau-Ponty and Morando, The Rebirth of Cosmology, pp.
63–64. Tycho Brahe, the bon-vivant of Astronomy, employed Kepler as his
assistant at the observatory near Prague. When he died a year later (1601),
Tycho left his vast astronomical observations to Kepler, who became his
successor as imperial mathematician. How Kepler used these observations to
construct his Astronomia nova is a story fascinatingly told by Bruce Stephenson,
Kepler’s Physical Astronomy.
The Topology of Melody
161
his part. Quite the contrary: he was responding to the sheer rationality
that he recognized in Ptolemy’s harmonic theories.16 For, as Ptolemy had
proposed, the distributive motions of the heavens were as orderly as those
of music, and Kepler saw reason enough to agree with him in this instance.
As Kepler saw it, there was indeed a rational basis in the geometrical
relationships between the heavenly bodies that Ptolemy had discovered.
These relationships were made evident in Ptolemy’s alignment of the
musical intervals on the circle of the zodiac, where, in addition to the
diametrical octave-positions that he outlined, other consonances showed
up which themselves corresponded geometrically to certain aspects of the
zodiac.17 Ptolemy showed, for example, that the musical consonance of
a fifth in the proportion of 3:2 arises from that portion of the circle –
namely 1200 – that is, two-thirds of the way around the zodiac from any
given point. Thus, two-thirds from that point is in a trine aspect to that
given point. So, too, the consonance of a fourth in the proportion of 4:3
corresponds to 900, or the quartile aspect. Ptolemy explains it in this
way:18
Those parts of the zodiac that are similarly situated are the first ones in affinity with one another. These are the ones that are in diametric opposition,
comprehending two right angles and six of the twelve parts [of the zodiac]
and 180 degrees; those which stand in a trine position, comprehending one
and a third right angles, four parts of the twelve and 120 degrees; those
which are said to be in quartile aspect, comprehending one right angle and
16
17
18
Stephenson (note 12) has put to rest for all time the notion that Kepler’s
Mysterium cosmographicum of 1596 and the Five Books of the Harmony of the World
(Harmonices mundi libri v) of 1619 reveal a mystical bent on his part. Thus
Stephenson, p. 249: “Kepler was not a mystic. He was, undeniably, an astrologer; but in that age astrology was not yet entirely irrational. His own theories
about why astrology worked (and he did believe that it worked) rested on the
same theoretical foundations in geometry as his theories on the harmonies of
the world.”
Geometry was for Ptolemy the basis of the universe’s whole design. Cf. Mark
Riley, “Theoretical and Practical Astrology: Ptolemy and His Colleagues,”
TAPA 117 (1987), 246, n. 27.
Tetrabiblos, 13.
162
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
three of the twelve parts and 90 degrees; and finally, those that make up the
sextile position, comprehending two-thirds of one right angle and two of
the twelve parts and 60 degrees.
Ptolemy thus recognized four geometrical relationships between the
constellations: opposition (octave), trine (fifth), quartile (fourth), and
sextile (sixth). Kepler himself is said to have discovered several other
aspects of the circle based on other aliquot parts of 360 degrees.19
Inspired by Ptolemy’s geometry, Kepler was eventually able to link the
perfect polygons – triangles, squares, pentagons, and so on, depending on
the degree of commensurability of their sides with the diameter of the
circle – to all the musical consonances. For example, the ratio of the arc on
the circle created by the two sides of a pentagon to the rest of the circle,
being 3:2, becomes a visual embodiment of the perfect fifth. In similarly
geometrical terms, the ratio between the equilateral triangle and the circle, being 3:2, also makes for the fifth. The ratio between the square and
the circle, being 4:3, is productive of a perfect fourth. Working along
geometrical lines such as these, Kepler proceeded to find correspondences
between all the consonantal ratios of music and the circle. In this way,
he elucidated what was implicit in Ptolemy’s account of the heavenly
harmony: the musical correspondences, as is proved by their ratios, do
not always involve the entire circle of the zodiac; the aspects between
the constellations, based upon the common denominator 12 for all the
musical consonances, always involve the entire circle of the zodiac.20 The
consonances, being the most fundamental elements in the formation of
musical scale-systems, thus epitomized for Kepler the startling perfection
of the cosmos in all its classical geometrical complexity.
19
20
Robbins, Tetrabiblos, p. 72, n. 2. It should be noted that Ptolemy’s sextile of
sixty degrees equals two whole-tones, or a major third.
Field (note 14), p. 133 quotes Kepler, Harmonikes Mundi, Book IV, Chapter
5, to this effect: “The consonances do not depend immediately on the circle
and its arcs on account of their being circular, but on account of the length
of the parts, that is, their proportion one to another, which would be the
same if the circle were straightened out into a line.” Field observes: “Kepler
adds that the Consonances do not always involve the whole circle, but sometimes only ratios of parts of it, whereas Aspects do always concern the whole
circle.”
The Topology of Melody
163
Assuming then that there is a consonantal relation between the
movements of the planets, Kepler said:21
Accordingly, perfect consonances are found: between the converging movements of Saturn and Jupiter, the octave; between the converging movements
of Jupiter and Mars, the octave and minor third approximately; between
the converging movements of Mars and the Earth, the fifth; between their
perihelial, the minor sixth; between the extreme converging movements of
Venus and Mercury, the major sixth; between the diverging or even between
the perihelial, the double octave.
But it was apparently Ptolemy’s comparison of the planets’ daily
lengthwise east-to-west motion to actual melodies that inspired Kepler
to reproduce in the fifth book of his Harmonikes mundi the harmonious
constructs that he believed to pervade the universe.
With the harmonic sectioning of the heavens as his guide, Kepler
persevered in studying the physical problems involved in the variations
of the planetary motions, until he was led, at last, to his revolutionary
discoveries: the planets move in ellipses, not in circular orbits; their
speeds – and hence the “songs” they produce – vary with their distance
from the sun. Accordingly, the closer a planet is to the sun – its perihelial
tuning – the faster it travels and the higher the pitch of its “voice”; the
more distant a planet is from the sun – its aphelial tuning – the slower is
its speed and the deeper is the pitch of its “song.” Thus, Mercury, being
closest to the sun, and the fastest-moving planet, sings a high-pitched
ascending and descending melody; the deep bass voices of Saturn and
Jupiter produce a major and minor mode, respectively; Venus, being
more circular in its orbit and more limited in its range, sings on one pitch
only, while Mars produces a portion of an F-Major scale, and the Moon
21
Harmonies of the World (trans. Wallis), p. 1033. Thus Stephenson (note 12), p. 153:
“To summarize all this, Kepler has found, by examining the ‘observed’ harmonies between the converging motions of adjacent planets, reasonably precise
harmonies between the converging motions of Saturn and Jupiter, Jupiter and
Mars, Mars and Earth, and Venus and Mercury; between the diverging motions
of Venus and Mercury; between the aphelial motions of Earth and Venus; and
between the perihelial motions of Mars and Earth, Earth and Venus, and Venus
and Mercury.”
164
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
a segment of the G-Major scale. The saddest song of all the heavenly
bodies is that of the Earth: a semi-tone, an interval verberant with tension.22 Bringing all his calculations within the range of one octave, Kepler
poised himself to say this:23
Accordingly, you won’t wonder any more that an excellent order of sounds
or pitches in a musical system or scale has been set up by men, since you see
that they are doing nothing else in this business except to play the apes of
God the Creator and to act out, as it were, a certain drama of the ordination
of the celestial movements.
The conception as to the harmonic configuration of the universe that
began with Pythagoras’ discovery of the mathematical basis of musical
intervals became the archetype underlying Kepler’s physical astronomy.
For in his astronomy, Kepler verified mathematically the geometric
postulate of an analogy between the infinitely large – the cosmos – and
the infinitely small – musical intervals. By uniting these two infinities mathematically, Kepler progressed through one doggedly painful
analysis after another to his ultimate solution of planetary motion.24
22
Kepler’s planetary songs are given by Elliott Carter Jr. In Harmonies of the World,
p. 1039, in Kepler’s notation with his moveable clefs, and in modern notation as well: Saturn: G A B A G; Jupiter: G A B♭ A G; Mars (approximately)
F G A B♭ C B♭ A G F; Earth: G A♯ G; Venus: E E E; Mercury: C D E F G A
B C D E C G E C; Moon: G A B C B A G. This is discussed by Stephenson
(note 12), pp. 166–68, who explains the basis for Kepler’s different tunings,
p. 168: “Kepler has simply chosen a note that expresses the aphelial motion
of each planet in one of the primary tunings and based its up-and-down melody on that note. The melodies of the different planets are not intended to be
comparable in pitch.”
23 Harmonies of the World (trans. Wallis), p. 1038.
24 Kepler speaks of the problem in locating the intermediate positions within the
intervals traversed by the planets in almost the same terms used by Aristoxenus
in connection with the location of the moveable note, lichanos (Ch. 4, note 39).
Thus, Kepler in Harmonies of the World (trans. Wallis), p. 1039: “They [sc. notes]
do not form articulately the intermediate positions, because they struggle from
one extreme to the opposite not by leaps and intervals but by a continuum of
tunings and actually traverse all the means (which are potentially infinite) – which
cannot be expressed by me in any other way than by a continuous series of
intermediate notes” [italics supplied].
The Topology of Melody
165
Thus, what began with Pythagoras’ conception of harmonia, the union
of opposites, was carried to those scientific heights of commanding
objectivity with which Kepler laid the groundwork of modern astronomy. Kepler’s theory – a “sacred madness,” he called it – was framed
within the context of ancient astronomical thought; it is expressive of
a universe that is as rational and as beautiful as the interplay of forces
in a well-formed melody. Its ruling principle is harmonia, wherein the
affinity between music and mathematics is fully realized. In harmonia
then, all things human and animate are linked together, and through its
offices universal life is made to be nothing less than an endless musical
performance. From the most distant planet to the nearest bird, every
participant in its choreography is designed and proportioned according
to mathematical law to work like an articulate musical instrument. As
Kepler so movingly describes it, this is a universe that is governed by a
Supreme Being whose mind is as that of a musician. Given the grandeur
of his conception, it could not but be that music is of all the arts the most
useful; for of all the arts it held for Kepler the key to universal truth, the
key with which he unlocked the laws of planetary movement.
Kepler’s conception of a harmonically active universe finds intellectual support from a most unexpected quarter: a little-known scholium
of Isaac Newton for his Proposition VIII in Book III of the Principia. The
proposition has to do with gravity and reads as follows:25
In two spheres gravitating each towards the other, if the matter in places
on all sides round about and equidistant from the centres is similar, the
weight of either sphere towards the other will be inversely as the square of
the distance between their centres.
Newton’s scholium for this proposition would remain little known had
Jamie James not introduced it in full into the literature on Pythagorean doctrine.26 It is, as James says, “most startling,” because it “relates directly to
the great theme of the music of the spheres.”27 What Newton states in this
scholium is that the inverse-square relationships between the weights of the
25
26
27
Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (trans. Motte; rev. Cajori), p. 282.
James, The Music of the Spheres, pp. 164–65.
James (note 26), p. 163.
166
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
planets and their distances from the sun is adumbrated in the inverse-square
relationships between the tensions and the pitch of vibrating strings. Not
only did Newton ascribe the discovery of this inverse relationship in vibrating strings to Pythagoras, he also asserted that Pythagoras:28
applied to the heavens [the proportions that he had discovered] and consequently by comparing those weights with the weights of the Planets and the
lengths of the strings with the distances of the Planets, he understood by
means of the harmony of the heavens that the weights of the Planets towards
the Sun were reciprocally as the squares of their distances from the Sun.
In the views expressed by the scientists of classical antiquity, by Kepler
in his Harmonikes mundi and, unexpectedly, by Newton in his scholium to
Proposition VIII, music and the laws of harmonia were acknowledged as offering valuable insights into the mysteries of the universe. As a distinct science,
harmonia mundi was concerned to illuminate the formal aspects of the universe, thereby offering the key to rationality in all of nature. But subsequent
advances in physics have shifted the focus so far from the role of music as a
guide to scientific inquiry that the whole notion of a harmonic universe had
eventually to end up as an antiquarian curiosity, a pseudo-science unworthy
of serious intellectual pursuit. Jamie James has said it best:29
Science has drifted so far from its original aims that even to bother with
the question of its relationship to music might appear to be an exercise in
irrelevancy, like chronicling the connection between military history and
confectionery. Yet every scholar of the history of science or of music can
attest to the intimate connection between the two. In the classical view it
was not really a connection but an identity.
This classically warranted identity between music and the cosmos
has recently reemerged with an urgent promise to throw a blinding
28
29
James (note 26), p. 165. James rightfully observes of this statement
(pp. 165–66): “Pythagoras did nothing of the sort. . . . The Master erroneously
taught that a simple arithmetical relationship existed between the weights of
stretched strings and their tones, just as it did between the lengths of plucked
strings of different lengths and their tones.” Cf. Chapter IV, note 13.
James (note 26), p. 10.
The Topology of Melody
167
light – more properly, an all-pervasive vibration – into those very
edges of knowledge that have heretofore escaped understanding. Most
remarkable, this new theory, called Superstring, which gives priority
to a sounding universe over the visible or material one, was predicted
with uncanny prescience by Jocelyn Godwin, an avowed adherent of the
ancient tradition of a harmonious universe. In his words:30
The first postulate of speculative music immediately sifts the believers
from the profane. It is that sound (or tone, or music) is ontologically prior
to material existence. One way of giving assent to this is through recognizing that underlying the apparent solidity of matter there is nothing but a
network of vibrations. . . . Speculative music often goes further and asserts
that the whole cosmos is audible in its superior modes of existence, just as
heaven and its inhabitants are visible to certain mystics, even when there
are no light vibrations striking the eye.
Godwin wrote these words in 1989, some years before the particle
properties in Superstring theory were beginning to be heralded as the
solution to an unimaginably difficult problem: how to reconcile two
mutually incompatible theories with one another. The one – Einstein’s
theory of general relativity – deals with the nature of the universe
on its most macroscopic level: stars, constellations of stars, galaxies,
and clusters of galaxies. The other – quantum mechanics – treats the
nature of the universe on its most microscopic level: molecules, atoms,
electrons, protons, neutrons, quarks, and, finally, vibrating strings.31
The problem for physicists has been this: when the calculations of the
one theory – the macroscopic – are merged with those of the other
theory – the microscopic – the answer turns out to be infinity. For
physicists, such an answer offers no solution at all.32 Superstring theory,
30
31
Joscelyn Godwin, ed. Cosmic Music, Introduction, p. 13.
Throughout this discussion, I have relied on Brian Greene, The Elegant Universe,
a book which has helped to moderate my ignorance of particle physics and
cosmology. Greene’s lucid explanations of arcane matters have brought me a
modicum of understanding where hitherto there had been none at all.
32 Thus Greene (note 31, p. 129): “Calculations that merge the equations of general relativity and those of quantum mechanics typically yield one and the
same ridiculous answer: infinity. Like a sharp tap on the wrist from an old-time
168
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
it is hoped, will eventually unify these two incompatible theories under
a single incontrovertible principle: harmonia.
What Jocelyn Godwin had perceived independently of particle physicists to be a network of vibrations “underlying the apparent solidity of
matter,” has come to be postulated by the proponents of Superstring theory
as a cosmic symphony of strings that are vibrating under different resonant
patterns. In a book chapter entitled “Nothing but Music: the Essentials of
Superstring Theory,” Brian Greene explains how the properties of elementary particles observed in nature have taken on the musical characteristics
of the type that Godwin had predicted intuitively. Thus Greene:33
With the discovery of superstring theory, musical metaphors take on a startling reality, for the theory suggests that the microscopic landscape is suffused with tiny strings whose vibrational patterns orchestrate the evolution
of the cosmos. The winds of change, according to superstring theory, gust
through an aeolian universe.
According to Superstring theory then, the elementary ingredients of the cosmos – its fundamental building-blocks – are infinitely
small oscillating filaments hidden deep within the heart of universal
matter. These filaments are believed to vibrate so harmoniously with
one another and in so elegant a concinnity as to provide a framework
for uniting the infinitely large with the infinitely small. The arena
in which this intense symphonic activity takes place is thought to
be a spatial region that is as smooth as a continuum and as sensitively
responsive to all cosmic events in the universe as a living membrane
is to life itself. This cosmic space is anything but passive; on the
contrary, it is as dynamically reactive to all occurrences within its
precincts as is the topos of melody to the myriad movements of the
singing voice.34
33
34
school-teacher, an infinite answer is nature’s way of telling us that we are doing
something that is quite wrong.”
Greene (note 31), p. 135.
As Greene (note 31), p. 72 explains, immersed as we are within the threedimensional fabric of space, what we in fact feel is gravity, and “space is the
medium by which the gravitational force is communicated.” On the “cosmic
The Topology of Melody
169
Just as cosmic space is thought by cosmic physicists to respond to
objects such as planets moving in the vicinity of the sun, so do musicians think of the topos of melody as reacting forcefully to the movements of the singing voice. And whereas cosmic space is profoundly
affected by the gravitational force exerted by one body, such as the
sun, on another, such as a planet, the topos of melody is felt to be
similarly excited by the tension that erupts when one melodic note
moves into the vicinity of another. On this analogy, cosmic space and
the topos of melody are linked at the deepest level by the three categories of experience: motion, time, and the forces of gravity. What
is essential to music, therefore, are properties that are truly cosmic.
If physicists and cosmologists are given to finding music in the universe, then musicians must be equally justified in discovering the
universe in music.
In music, the passage of time depends on the speed with which a
melody moves through melodic space. The sharing of melodic motion –
tempo – with time and space thus underlies all musical utterance. As is
commonly understood, speed is a measure of how far an object travels
between two points in a given length of time: and distance is a measure
of how much space is traversed between two points in a given period
of time. Applied to music, however, all such notions are contingent on
a sovereign kind of causality that renders music independent of everything in the visual world. This allows music to set its own pace, make
its own time, and order its own space. Roger Scruton explains the situation in these terms:35
The phenomenal space and phenomenal time of music are matched by phenomenal causality that orders the musical work. . . . The notes in music
follow one another like bodily movements – with a causality that makes
immediate sense to us, even though the how of it lies deep in the nature of
things and hidden from view.
35
symphony” produced by the infinitely small vibrating strings – each being
thought of as an elementary particle – see Greene (note 31), pp. 146–51.
Scruton, The Aesthetics of Music, p. 76. Aristoxenus, as mentioned in Chapter 2,
note 96, thought the how of it to lie hidden deep within the soul.
170
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
The same point is made even more vividly by Wayne D. Bowman,
who says:36
The time music “takes” is a contingent affair, whereas the time music “has”
or “is” is an essential or fundamental aspect of musical experience. The time
in music is musically critical, while the time music is in is incidental.
In discussing time and motion in music, it is important, therefore,
to specify who or what is doing the measuring. If, for example, a singer
is seen striding across a stage while singing a slow-moving adagio, the
observer to the scene is made to experience two kinds of time simultaneously. Although the voice of the singer may be said to be moving
with the singer – like a slow-moving passenger on a speeding train –
the observer – namely, the listener to the song – will have a perspective
of time and distance that differs essentially from that of the witness to
the walk alone. The walk of the singer may abstract from objective or
universal time ten full minutes as measured by a clock; but the melody
being sung makes of time a fusion of the present with its own past
and future. Bowman characterizes this peculiar relativity of time and
motion in music as a dilation of the present:37
When music dilates the present, one is carried along by the inflections of
a “moving” passage. When music broadens present in the direction of the
past (as when vividly recalling and reliving a musical experience) it squeezes
“real” presence and future to one side, making past present again.
Time – the paradigmatic continuum – and music – the temporal art
par excellence – can be measured only while they are moving or passing us by. Nonetheless, there really is a past time and a future time,
also; but it is only the present time that really “exists” long enough
to be measured.38 If music has the power to annul all such temporal
36
37
38
Bowman, Philosophical Perspectives in Music, p. 272. Bowman has quoted in this
passage Thomas Clifton, Music as Heard: A Study in Applied Phenomenology, p. 62.
Ibid.
Thus St. Augustine, Confessions, XI. 16 (trans. Watts): “As for the past times,
which now are not; or the future, which yet are not, who is able to measure
them? Unless perchance some one man be so bold to affirm to me, that that
The Topology of Melody
171
contradictions, it is because music allows us to think of the past and
the future as vividly present before us. The “past” in music is identified
with memory, the “future” with expectation, with the consequence that
memory and expectation are in effect both present knowledge.39 This
present knowledge that is so actively supplied in music is exactly what
St. Augustine was describing when he said:40
If the future and the past do exist, I want to know where they are. I may not
yet be capable of such knowledge, but at least I know that wherever they are,
they are not there as future or past, but as present. For if, wherever they are, they
are future, they do not yet exist; if past, they no longer exist. So wherever they
are and whatever they are, it is only by being present that they are.
According to Aristoxenus, they are in music. In fact, as he sees it,
the only way to deal with music is to follow all three times – past,
present, and future – with the ear and with the mind. In stating this
case, Aristoxenus seems to have been thinking with the very mind of
St. Augustine, whose own relativistic theory of time has always been a
matter of amazement to philosophers. Here is Aristoxenus:41
may be measured, which is not. Therefore, while time is passing, it may be
observed and measured: but when it is once past, it cannot, because it is not.”
39 This present knowledge is in reality a consciousness of necessity, or, as Kant
would have it, a “causality of reason.” It is this that is imposed by the laws of
melodic order upon the notes of melody. Thus Scruton (note 35), p. 76, says:
“A tone is heard as the response to its predecessor, as tending towards its successor, as continuing an action which makes sense as a whole.”
40 Confessions, XI. 18 (trans. Pine-Coffin).
41 Harm. El. II. 38–39 (Da Rios, 48. 11–18). There is reason to believe (and to
lament the fact) that lacunae of unknown length intruded into and succeeded
this important statement. Cf. Macran, p. 269; Da Rios, criticus apparatus. What
has been lost must have had to do not only with the time that music imposes
on its topos, but also with the motion of melody, whose processes cannot be
captured by mathematics. For in speaking of melody as “a process of coming
into being” (ἐν γενέσει), Aristoxenus had clearly in mind something that lies
well beyond the grasp of mathematics. Thus Barker, II, p. 155, n. 37: “The
emphasis on ‘coming to be’ may conceal a thrust against Pythagorean theory,
whose mathematical representations deal only with relations between notes
located at specific pitches.”
172
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
It is clear that the comprehension of melodies consists in following with
both the ear and the intellect things that are transpiring in their every
distinction. For melody, even as all the other parts of music, consists in
a process of coming into existence. The intuitive understanding of music
comes from these two things: perception and memory. For it is necessary to
perceive what is taking place and to remember what has taken place. There
is no other way of following what is occurring in music.
Just as the musical intellect is connected with time, so musical
intuition is connected with the notion of musical space. In fact, it is
really quite impossible to speak of musical time without dealing with
the question of musical space. It is on this latter question – musical
space – that theorists and aestheticians are often at odds not only with
one another, but with musicians also. Thus, Bowman:42
The extraordinary difficulty of describing music’s temporal character without spatial terms shows that musical time and space are experientially inseparable. . . .
However, music’s spaces are very unlike the “objective” spaces we ascribe to visual,
physical, or geometrical forms. Music’s spaces are phenomenal spaces, spaces that
move without going anywhere, that change while staying the same.
The problem with musical space is this: Does music move in space
or does space become an actuality through the motion of music? Is
there in fact a “place” in which music moves? Quoting Geza Revesz,
Zuckerkandl writes:43
The space that becomes alive through sound entirely lacks the essential
spatial characteristics of optical space, such as three-dimensionality, spatial
order, multiplicity of directions, form, and above all occupancy by objects;
it has no direct relation to the world of bodies, is related to neither of the
two sensory spaces which are given [visual space and tactile space], either in
its structure or in its phenomenal elaboration; it knows no geometric relations, and possesses no spatial finiteness.
42
43
Bowman (note 36), p. 273.
Zuckerkandl, Sound and Symbol, pp. 280–81.
The Topology of Melody
173
To Zuckerkandl, Revesz’ argument against the reality of melodic
space is applicable only to noise; for noise and all such disordered
acoustical phenomena are localized, as it were, or fixed in place.
Where there is noise, there is no melodic space to be ordered; in this
case, there can be no music at all. It is in music only that melodic
space becomes “alive.” To make this point, Zuckerkandl seems to
have been thinking with the very mind of Aristoxenus. Here is
Zuckerkandl:44
Even where there is nothing to be seen, nothing to be touched, nothing
to be measured, where bodies do not move from place to place, there is
still space. And it is not empty space; it is space filled to the brim, space
“become alive,” the space that tones disclose to us. Far from being unable
to testify in matters of space, music makes us understand that we do not
learn all that is to be said about space from eye and hand, from geometry,
geography, astronomy, physics. The full concept of space must include the
experience of the ear, the testimony of music.
Others see melodic space in metaphorical terms drawn from the
world of vision. Thus Roger Scruton:45
There is no real space of sounds; but there is a phenomenal space of tones.
It is modeled on the phenomenal space of everyday perception – the space
in which we orientate ourselves. It has “up” and “down,” height and depth;
its single dimension is understood not only geometrically but also in terms
of effort and motion, attraction and repulsion, heaviness and lightness.
It is permeated by a phenomenal gravity, to the law of which all tones
are subject, and against which they must strive if they are to move at all.
. . . Yet, try as we might, we cannot advance from this phenomenal space to
an objective spatial order. The topological character of space, as a system of
places and surfaces, is not reproduced in the acousmatic realm.
44
45
Zuckerkandl (note 43), p. 292. Cf. Chapter 4, the motion in space of the voice.
Scruton (note 35), p. 75. Cf. Lippman, “Spatial Perception and Physical
Location as Factors in Music,” 24–34.
174
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Like Aristoxenus, Rothstein seems to have accepted melodic space as
a given, that is, as a fact of experience that qualifies as a first principle.
He states the case in these words:46
A composition is an exploration of musical “space,” then, which creates its own
topology. It establishes which events are continuous, which discrete; it creates
connections between small events and large . . . . The composer determines
what paths may be taken through a musical space and where they will lead.
To others, such as Nicholas Cook, all such concepts as space, motion and
melodic lines, or continua, can only be understood as metaphors from
the visual world:47
Musical lines have no material existence; they only exist in terms of the
metaphor of space, a metaphor which Scruton considers to be so deeply
entrenched in the experience of music as to constitute one of its defining
properties.
Cook thereupon quotes Roger Scruton to this effect:48
It seems then that in our most basic apprehension of music there lies a
complex system of metaphor, which is the true description of no material fact. And the metaphor cannot be eliminated from the description
of music, because it is integral to the intentional object of musical experience. Take this metaphor away and you take away the experience of
music.
The difference in the theories expressed in the above statements and
that of Aristoxenus derives from this fact: what Scruton, Bowman, Cook,
et al. treat as metaphors, Aristoxenus accepts as reality. In other words,
the spatial metaphors of Scruton, Cook, and Bowman express concepts
or mental reflections of objects in which one kind of thing – melodic
space – is understood in terms of another – visual space. To Aristoxenus,
46
47
48
Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, p. 126.
Nicholas Cook, Music, Imagination, and Culture, p. 24.
Ibid.
The Topology of Melody
175
however, melodic space is real in itself by virtue of being natural to
the domain of music. As such, it requires no construal from any source
outside of music in order to be understood.
What musical space does need, as Aristoxenus so keenly realized, is
a logical analysis that is compatible in every respect with the testimony
of the ear, an analysis that would “save the phenomena,” as astronomers
understood the case. To “save” the phenomena of music, such an analysis
would have to conform to the rule of greatest simplicity: musical space,
being the topos of melody, is what it seems to be. It has been described
in the following ecstatic terms by Proust:49
. . . the field open to musicians is not a miserable stave of seven notes, but
an immeasurable keyboard (still, almost all of it, unknown), on which, here
and there only, separated by the gross darkness of its unexplored tracts, some
few among the millions of keys, keys of tenderness, of passion, of courage, of
serenity, which compose it, each one differing from the rest as one universe
differs from another, have been discovered by certain great artists who have
done us the service, when they awaken in us the emotion corresponding
to the theme which they have found, of showing us what richness, what
variety lies hidden, unknown to us, in that great black impenetrable night,
discouraging exploration, of our soul. . . .
Little wonder, then, that Pablo Casals could say so authoritatively of
musical space:50 “The most difficult aspect of music is not the notes, but
the spaces between them.”
To the musically cognizant ear, musical space is not identical with
space in the material world; it stands over against that space as something unmistakably music’s own. It is the topos in which every kind
of melodic change occurs. All such changes – or motions, as they are
49
Marcel Proust, Remembrance of Things Past (trans. C. K. Scott-Moncrieff). I,
p. 268.
50 David Blum, Casals and the Art of Interpretation, p. 19, quotes Casals: “ ‘Each
note is like a link in a chain – important in itself and also as a connection
between what has been and what will be.’ When he [sc. Casals] played, these
links became living art. Every phrase was borne upon a movement of energy
which flowed from one note through the next, going towards a point or coming
from another, ever in flux, ever formulating a contour.”
176
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
understood by Aristoxenus – result from the forces of certain tonal
functions (dynameis); but the forces produced by these tonal functions
are not identifiable by anything that geometry can represent.51 Like
musical space itself, tonal functions stand apart from physical functions in the material world as things which belong to music alone.
They are functions that set limits to each and every melodic change
that occurs in musical space. But musical space itself does not arise,
because composers construct it out of points of pitch as though they
were the only substantial elements of music; rather, points of pitch can
be posited only through a synthesis in which the form of melodic consecution originates. According to these teachings of Aristoxenus then,
it is in the concept of musical functions and their invariability that
the potential for this strictly musical synthesis subsists. That being
the case, no melodic configuration and no succession of musical notes
can contradict what is embodied in the general procedure of spatialization or in the synthesis of melodic consecution and remain music.
Multiform and coherent, this synthesis of form and function is secreted
in the material quality of sound. It is impervious to definition;52 but
51
52
On the contrary, they are identified by the musical intellect, according to
Aristoxenus Harm. El. 33 (Da Rios, 42. 11–13): “For we judge the sizes of
the intervals by ear, but we contemplate their functions with our intellect
(dianoia).” Commenting on this important statement, Lippman, Musical Thought
in Ancient Greece, p. 149, says: “It is possible, then, for the infinitude of pitches
comprised in the locus of any moveable tone to be recognized by the intellect as
discharging a single function.” While Barker, “Music and Perception: A Study
in Aristoxenus,” 13, finds the passage disappointingly vague, he allows this
much to be said: “The role of dianoia is to identify the sequences not merely as
sequences of intervals, which would be musically meaningless, but as forming
or implying structures within which the notes stand in functional relationships
to each other.”
This strictly melodic phenomenon, the experience of which has been likened
to a “dynamic knowledge” by Zuckerkandl (note 43), resists definition, but
invites discussion by theorists and aestheticians. Thus Zuckerkandl (p. 313):
“What makes the tone an element of musical order is not its pitch but its
audible relation to other tones; differences in direction and tension, not differences in pitch, are the constituents of the musical order of tones. And this characteristic of tone sensation, its dynamism, is, unlike pitch, closely connected
with the spatial component of tone sensation.” Dynamis is a state of space that
The Topology of Melody
177
the musically cognizant ear knows how to follow every nuance in the
domain of music, which has been referred to as “le domain si malléable,
illimité, de la musique.”53
The domain of music, or the “topos” of melody, as Aristoxenus understood it, is malleable in that it is acutely responsive to all the motions
of the singing voice; it is illimitable in that it is theoretically capable
of infinite extension and infinitesimal diminution;54 it is also a homogeneous continuum in that it imparts no difference to the melodies that
move in its precincts, for what can occur at one point or pitch range in
the melodic topos can also occur at every other point or pitch range.55
This attribute of the melodic topos makes all and any transpositions possible.56 These notions of spatial homogeneity, malleability, and infinitude are prominently featured in Aristoxenus’ theory and, as he insists,
they are all derived from one source only: the special knowledge of the
is implicated in the tensions and resolutions that arise in melodic progressions
and, as Scruton (note 35), p. 266 observes, “is of inexhaustible interest, and has
inspired some of the most important ventures in music theory.” Cf. Chapter 3,
note 46.
53 Léon-Paul Fargue, Maurice Ravel, pp. xxv–xxvi.
54 Thus Arnold Schoenberg, Theory of Harmony, p. 129: “The analogy with infinity could hardly be made more vivid than through a fluctuating, so to speak,
unending harmony . . .”
55 The changes imparted to scales and the melodies formed on those scales arise
from differences between pitch-keys or tonoi, one of the most disputed issues
in ancient theory, one that produced a considerable mass of scholarly writing.
See, for example, Barker, II, pp. 17–27. The question of the relation between
the tonoi and the modal scales is complicated by the fact that the Greeks’
notion of pitch was not, as is ours, that of a comparison with an external
standard.
56 In Harm. El. I. 7 (Da Rios, 11. 19–12. 8), Aristoxenus seems clearly to be speaking of keys of transposition: “Since each of the scales (systēmata), when placed
in a certain region (topos) of the voice, is sung, the scale when taken by itself,
admits of no difference, while a melody, composed in that scale, takes on no
accidental difference, but the greatest difference. Therefore, it is necessary for
one who would deal with the subject before us to speak of the topos of the voice
in general and in detail so far as is appropriate, that is, so far as the nature of the
scales themselves signifies.” On Aristoxenus’ view of the tonoi, see Mathiesen,
Apollo’s Lyre, p. 318; for musicians’ similar view, see Zuckerkandl, Sound and
Symbol, pp. 310–11.
178
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
musically intuitive ear. The problem that challenged Aristoxenus was
to find a musically logical formalism capable of dealing with the three
major problems raised by these notions: (1) how to reconcile the concept of a homogeneous continuum with the fact that it is constituted
of indivisible notes when, according to Aristotle, what is continuous
cannot be constituted of indivisibles;57 (2) how to deal with the fact
that the melodic topos, however perfect and homogeneous it may appear
to the ear, is contradicted by the mathematical laws of Pythagorean
harmonics;58 (3) how to determine the true size of any musical interval
and how to arrive at the true location for any melodic note in a tonal
continuum that is infinitely divisible.59
As Aristoxenus saw it, if any solution to these problems was still to
seek, three well-defined areas had to be avoided: (1) geometry (which is
the stronghold of Pythagorean harmonics);60 (2) the properties of musical
57
58
59
60
See Chapter 3, note 34.
See Chapter 4, note 41.
As noted in Chapter 3, note 59, the infinite divisibility of the tonal continuum stems from the characteristics of the square-root of two, the number
obtained on the division of the whole-tone. The square root of two is irrational (alogos), for its constituents can be written with unending, nonrepeating
decimal parts. As such, it is a natural inhabitant of the world of the continuum and, as a root of the polynomial equation x2 – 2 = 0, can submit to
being counted. Thus, John D. Barrow, Pi in the Sky, p. 211: “The continuum
is made up of all the rational numbers, which are countably infinite, plus
the irrational – those quantities like the square root of 2 – which cannot
be expressed as the ratio of two natural numbers.” As mentioned earlier, in
Chapter 4, the Pythagorean harmonicians dealt either with whole numbers,
like 1, 2, 3, and so on, or with the harmonic fractions, like 1/2 (octave), 2/3
(fifth), and 3/4 (fourth), all being numbers which are yielded by dividing
any whole number by another whole or rational number. And since they
could not express the square root of 2 as the ratio of any two whole numbers,
they found the octave itself impossible to measure out precisely. Cf. Bélis,
Aristoxène, pp. 65–66.
In arguing against the geometrical method of the Pythagoreans, Aristoxenus
makes the point that musicians are, in no sense of the word, craftsmen. Unlike
carpenters, lathe-turners, or other kinds of craftsmen, they are not trained
to discriminate the straight line, the circle, or any other figures. Rather, the
objects of their perception (which must be acute) are magnitudes of intervals
and their functions. Cf. note 51.
The Topology of Melody
179
instruments;61 (3) musical notation.62 The search had to be conducted instead
within the natural boundaries of what Aristoxenus called “attunement” (to
hērmosmenon). He thought of this attunement as something utterly different
from the Pythagorean concept of harmonia – the “fitting together” of opposites that is encapsulated in the geometrically-secured formula, 6:8 : 9:12.
For Artistoxenus, attunement was a topological framework from whose unifying principles the phenomena of music could be rationally deduced and
in whose statutes the testimony of the ear would be honored. Attunement
had to do solely with those musically logical sequences of intervals that
would offer composers the freedom to launch melodies into a musical space
of wonderful flexibility and adaptability. There, melody would be able to
live independently of the laws of mathematics.63
61
As Aristoxenus expressed himself in Harm. El. II. 39 (Da Rios, 49. 3–7), he
saw little value for the student of melody in the study of musical instruments.
For in his view, musical instruments and their physical properties, as studied in
isolation from music, would lead one as far from the truth about attunement as
does geometry. His argument seems so eerily directed against everything that
Schlesinger maintained in The Greek Aulos (as though time does not exist), that
there is little wonder why she had vigorously to refute Aristoxenus. Cf. Barker,
II, p. 154, note 33, who explains: “Armed with her complex and original theories about auloi and their scales, Schlesinger was often prepared to explain away
claims made by Aristoxenus about them, arguing that he was largely ignorant
of the instrument.” In truth, Aristoxenus was a leading authority on auloi. Cf.
Bélis, Aristoxène, p. 105, who explains Aristoxenus’ position on instruments by
saying “the auloi are ‘inanimate instruments’ which require being attuned by
the ear of the musician.” Cf. p. 26.
62 In criticizing those who considered notation to be the goal of harmonic science,
Aristoxenus had this to say in Harm. El. II. 39 (Da Rios, 49. 6–9): “So far from
being the limit of harmonic science, notation is not even a part of it, unless writing down metres is also a part of the science of metre” (trans. Barker). On the
notation of Phrygian melodies, see Chapter 2, note 91. Bélis, ibid., makes this
important point on the question of notation: “The notation of which Aristoxenus
speaks is a notation of intervals and not of notes; the sign used thus defines a
succession of intervals, whose size alone is important . . . notation is done to
oblige the uninitiated, the ignorant.” Moreover, as Aristoxenus states explicitly
in Harm. El. II. 40 (Da Rios, 50. 4ff.), notation fails to distinguish the differences
in functions (dynameis) of the various tetrachords. Cf. Barker, II, p. 156, n. 42.
63 Musical space, or the topos of melody, admitted of three conditions according to Aristoxenus, none of which can be defined by mathematical
180
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
The moment Aristoxenus probed deeply into the nature of this
topological framework – either experimentally or theoretically – he
saw that no mathematical formula could describe or predict the natural course of those intervallic sequences that are countenanced by the
mind’s ear. The Pythagoreans had proved to a mathematical certainty
that many of the intervals conceived of as melodic by composers could
not be represented by ratios of whole numbers – intervals such as semitones, quarter-tones, and other micro-intervals that characterize the
melodic genera and nuances (chroai). This, as the formulas of Euclid
and Archytas demonstrated, is because musical space is irrational mathematically speaking and no amount of geometric approximations can
do away with its innate incommensurability. The geometers working
with divisions of a straight line were therefore of no help at all since, as
Aristoxenus argued, there could be no agreement between their abstract
calculations and the real world of melody.64
Being an authority on the construction of musical instruments,
Aristoxenus knew that if the properties of strings and winds are integrated with anything, they are not with attunement, but most emphatically with the laws of geometry. For the design makeup of strings and
winds alike is a matter of geometrical measurements and proportional
processes. These procedures entail the estimation of major ratios like
those of body-containing rectangles, for example, or the proper alignment
formulae: (1) the place where the intervallic motion of the singing voice occurs;
(2) the place to which the moveable notes of the tetrachord are confined; (3)
the sonorous space, or tessitura, extending between high and low pitch, whose
divisions by the voice or instruments are apprehended solely by the ear. For as
Aristoxenus understood it, there is nothing in music that is not a fact of our
perception. Cf. Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 134–35.
64 The real world of melody is, as Bowman (note 35), p. 138, explained it, “always
and unavoidably a world of the ear.” He describes Aristoxenus’ orientation in these
words: “Attend to the sounds, he [sc. Aristoxenus] urged: music’s significance
must be explained in terms of these sounds, their relationships, their functions
within a musical system – not extra-musical affairs like mathematical proportions.
Music consists, he in effect argued, not in isolated acoustical ‘data’, but in tendencies, connections, and functions within a musical system. A truly musical theory
cannot be built from acoustical information about discrete tones or intervals, but
must address the ways these function within musical practices.”
The Topology of Melody
181
of finger-holes. The question of attunement does not enter into the case
at all. In his typically no-nonsense style, he says:65
In general terms, the greatest and most egregious of errors is that which
refers the nature of attunement to musical instruments. For it is not because
of the properties of musical instruments that attunement has the sort of
character that it has.
He goes on to argue that attunement is something that exists in the musical
mind, even if he could offer no proof of its existence other than its presentation in an actually existing melody. Of this he was certain: attunement,
as he understood the term, is not a property of musical instruments:66
For as there is no attunement in the strings save that which the skill of the
hand confers upon them, so there is none in the finger-holes save that which
has been introduced by the same agency. That no instrument puts itself into
attunement, but that it is sense-perception which is the principal authority
over this operation is obvious and requires no discussion.
Aristoxenus’ remarks on musical notation are precious: they are the
earliest reference in Western literature to the art of casting music into
written form. He speaks of musical notation as already a long-standing
institution in his own day, but at the same time he repudiates it as a
source of musical knowledge. As he sees it, musical notation can make
the sizes of intervals discernible to the eye, but it can never succeed
in explaining the musical properties of such intervals as they are presented to the ear in melody. That being the case, the mere perception
65
66
Harm. El. II. 41 (Da Rios, 52. 5–9).
Harm. El. II. 43 (Da Rios, 53. 13–18). Commenting on Aristoxenus’ refutation of all musical theories that refer melodic attunement to the constitution
of musical instruments, Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 61–62, says: “The key idea of
the text is that one cannot take for a goal, for an aim and a criterion, a simple
medium, a common instrument: for, Aristoxenus says, the aulos and the lyre are
the object of a judgment (τὸ κρινόμενoν) and cannot be an authority and a goal
(κύριόν τε καὶ πέρας); in fact, the strings of the lyre and the perforations of the
aulos are not tuned by themselves; the tuning of an instrument requires a manipulation by a musician, whose ear hears and judges of the sounds produced.”
182
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
by the eye, or even by the ear, of the magnitudes of intervals does not
constitute musical knowledge. In his words:67
Regarding what is accounted the final goal of the study called Harmonic,
some people say that it is in the writing down of melodies, asserting that it
[notation] is the end-all of our understanding of every kind of melody. . . . But
the fact is that notation is not the end-all of harmonic knowledge, nor is it
even a part of it. . . . For the person who knows how to write down a Phrygian
melody does not necessarily know best what a Phrygian melody is. It is clear
then that notation should not be the end-all of the study in question. That
what has been said is true should be clear to those who study the subject:
notation is necessary only for making the sizes of intervals discernible.
In Aristoxenus’ view then, musical notation does not in and of itself
constitute musical knowledge; it is, rather, a necessary, but not a sufficient skill for the composition of music. In the centuries succeeding
him, many composers would make the same point about the knowledge
of notation and the understanding of music, perhaps no one more powerfully than Beethoven:68
I carry my thoughts about with me for a long time, often for a very long time,
before writing them down. I can rely on my memory for this and can be sure
that, once I have grasped a theme, I shall not forget it even years later . . .
67
Harm. El. II. 39 (Da Rios, 49. 1–18). As Bélis, Aristoxène, p. 105, points out:
“Rarely does Aristoxenus show himself to be so virulent as he does towards
these professors of writing: he taxes them with ignorance and describes their
ideas as absurd . . . . He explains in substance that one can know very well how
to notate a melody that one hears, without knowing however in what it consists
(understand: without knowing the rules of the art); the notation of meters is no
more a part of metrics than is the notation of intervals a part of the science of
harmonics.” The most important fact to be learned here is that the notation of
which Aristoxenus speaks is that “of intervals and not of notes; the sign used
thus defines a succession of intervals, of which only the magnitude matters.”
68 From a written conversation with Louis Schlösser (1822 or 1823), for which see
Morgenstern, Composers on Music, p. 87. For Beethoven, then, notation was simply a necessary chore, a written record for the purpose of publication. His genius
lay not therefore in his capacity to write down what he heard in his mind’s ear,
but, rather, in his ability to develop, in the absence of notation, monumental
forms from the germinal bits and pieces that had taken root in his mind.
The Topology of Melody
183
since I am aware of what I want to do, the underlying idea never deserts me.
It rises, it grows, I see and hear the image in front of me from every angle,
as if it had been cast [like sculpture], and only the labor of writing it down
remains, a labor which need not take long, but varies according to the time
at my disposal, since I very often work on several things at the same time.
Yet I can always be sure that I shall not confuse one with another.
And Robert Schumann makes the case in these purely Aristoxenian
terms:69
He is a good musician who understands the music without the score, and
the score without the music. The ear should not need the eye, the eye should
not need the outward ear.
The Pythagorean harmonic method was derived from the most fundamental and original mathematical model of continuity – the simplest geometric figure – the straight line. Born of this mathematical
model of continuity, Pythagorean harmonics had to yield results that
are mathematically true.70 But, as Aristoxenus discovered, these results
were not always musically true. Nonetheless, he could ill afford to
ignore them so long as they stood opposed to his goal: a standardized
system of attunement that would not only be practical, but also reliable
and convenient for all musical purposes. The task he faced was forbidding. He had first to ameliorate the hostility between the geometry
of the straight line and the perceived symmetrical continuity of the
melodic topos. Euclid and the Pythagoreans had proved that the most
perfect interval, the octave, is in fact asymmetrical in that it cannot be
69
70
Morgenstern (note 68), pp. 148–49. The passage in full reads as follows: “As
Eusebius observed a young student of music diligently following a rehearsal
of Beethoven’s Eighth Symphony, score in hand, he remarked: “There is a good
musician!’ – ‘By no means,’ said Florestan. ‘He is a good musician who understands the music without the score and the score without the music. The ear
should not need the eye, the eye should not need the (outer) ear . . .’.”
Music, by its very nature, or physis, does not conform to the precision of mathematical concepts such as obtain for the straight line. Euclid had demonstrated
as much himself when he proved mathematically that octaves are always something less than six whole-tones and whole-tones themselves are not divisible
into two equal semitones. Cf. Chapter 4, note 27.
184
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
r econciled mathematically with its internal components. For the ratio
of the octave (2:1) – the macrocosmos, as it were – when merged with
the ratios of its innermost interval – the microcosmos – yields infinity
in the form of .66666666....71 In practical terms, this meant that the
process of fixing the locus .of the interior or moveable notes of any tetrachord could never be completed because, at any stage of the process,
it could always be continued.72
Aristoxenus came upon this problem the moment he attempted
to locate by conventional mathematical means such interior notes as
lichanos in the two lower-pitched tetrachords – Hypaton and Meson –
and paranētē in the three higher-pitched tetrachords – Synnemenon,
Diezeugmenon, and Hyperbolaion. For example, in mapping the interval
from E (hypatē Meson) to A (mesē), he found by a process of dividing
magnitudes that there was no position at which the magnitudes thus
yielded could not be potentially redivided. This was because at every
stage in his process of division, there was always a remaining interval
which was itself capable of being divided. Therefore, if, as Aristotle had
observed, “every magnitude is divisible into magnitudes,” how could
a lichanos be assigned an exact location between hypatē Meson (E) and
mesē (A) in any one of these three genera, let alone in any one of the
three differentiae or nuances (chroai), if the possible sites for a lichanos
71
72
The problem of infinity arises in the relationship between octaves and fifths.
Creating fifths on the monochord twelve times, as Pythagoras is reputed to have
done, will yield a series of fifths that is about one-ninth of a whole-tone sharper
than a note produced by an octave series. This discrepancy is expressed mathematically by the ratio 531,441:524,288, an interval known as the Pythagorean
comma. To judge from what Aristoxenus tells us on this subject, he seemed to
feel that such an interval as a comma and such an unmanageable interval as the
fifth were nature’s – that is, musical nature’s – way of informing us that we are
doing something wrong. Cf. note 59. See Helmholtz, On the Sensations of Tone,
p. 548; Isacoff, Temperament, pp. 102–5.
What is implicated in this problem is the geometrical criterion for the incommensurability of two line segments. It is stated by Euclid Elements, Book X,
Proposition 2: “If, when the lesser of two unequal magnitudes is continually
subtracted in turn from the greater, that which is left never measures the one
before it, the magnitudes will be incommensurable.”
The Topology of Melody
185
were potentially infinite? In other words, the limits of the tetrachord,
being a perfect fourth, can be calculated on the Pythagorean standard
as 4:3; but by the same standard, the precise locations of the various
notes intervening between the limits of the tetrachord cannot be fixed
by measuring continuous magnitudes.73
Using the conventional method of dividing magnitudes, Aristoxenus
discovered a linear array of an actually infinite collection of discrete
notes such that between any two notes there could be yet a third.
This made it altogether impossible to locate lichanos in the pyknon, the
“dense” ensemble of the two smallest intervals of the tetrachord.74 For
the pyknon called for the most delicate variations in the pitch of lichanos, each of which lent a recognizable and distinct tonal color to the
73
74
As Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 43ff. reminds us more than once, much of Aristoxenus’
teachings are lost. But from what remains, this much emerges: Aristoxenus
was determined to deal with the infinite, the apeiron – not with the immeasurably large, but with the immeasurably small. The task he undertook had to do
with number and not, as was the case with the Pythagoreans, with geometry.
Thus, Aristoxenus showed intuitively that at the start of the process in seeking the movable notes there is always a remainder, and that this remainder
continues until it becomes so small that the operation of pin-pointing a note
such as lichanos becomes so limited as to compel one to stop altogether, or to
settle for an approximation. Similarly, no matter how many sides a polygon
may have, it will never fit into a perfect circle; it can only approximate a perfect circle.
This characteristic density of intervals occurs in the Enharmonic genus, in
which the sum of the two quarter-tone intervals is less than the remainder of
the tetrachord, as, e.g.:
E E+FA
pyknon
second occurrence of the pyknon is heard in the Chromatic genus, in which
the sum of the two smaller intervals is a whole-tone, this – the pyknon – being
less than the remainder of the tetrachord by a semi- tone, as, for example:
E F G♭ A
A
Cf.
pyknon
Michaelides, s. v.
186
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
t etrachord.75 In seeking a place for lichanos, Aristoxenus, as he tells us,
came upon infinity:76
In the first place, if we seek a specific name for each increase and decrease
of the notes forming the pyknon, it is obvious that we will need an infinite number of names; since the locus of lichanos is divisible into infinite
parts.
A series of such infinite lichanoi could not but give an impression
of vagueness wherein there must be a general obliteration of distinctions. There must be a “fog,” as it were, of lichanoi such that no one
lichanos can be distinguished from another, let alone from its immediate
neighbor. This enigma of the lichanoi, as posed here by Aristoxenus,
recalls the paradoxes of Zeno the Eleatic (c. 490 b.c.), whose notions of
continuity, unity, and infinity have vexed the mind of man since their
inception. For the paradoxes of Zeno, being based on the geometry of
the line, to the exclusion of the factor, time, demonstrate outstandingly that there is no “next point” or “next instant” that can possibly be
75
In the examples given in note 74, the note F is lichanos in the Enharmonic
genus; the note Gb is lichanos in the Chromatic genus. Neither of these notes
can be located using the standard Pythagorean method. The chroai (literally,
“colors”) present even greater difficulties, since they answer to the most subtle
shiftings of pitch imaginable. As Barker, II, p. 142, note 93 explains: “the placing of the two moveable notes at any definite position within the ranges proper
to a genus constitutes a shade (chroa) of that genus.” For a complete analysis of
the genera and shades, see Fig. 7.
76 Harm. El. II. 48 (Da Rios, 59, 9–60.3). As Aristoxenus explained earlier in
Harm. El. I. 26 (Da Rios, 34. 3–7): “We must regard the lichanoi as infinite in
number; for wherever you station the voice in the topos of the lichanos as designated, the result will be a lichanos, the topos of the lichanos not being an empty
space, that is, not a space that is not capable of admitting a lichanos.” To this
statement, Aristoxenus adds what must be considered the greatest understatement of his treatise (Da Rios, 34. 7–8): “So that the matter we are arguing
is one of no small importance.” On the contrary, the matter being argued by
Aristoxenus is of the greatest importance: namely, that while the individual
movable notes such as lichanos are themselves finite, they are, as a class, infinite.
Aristoxenus’ recognition of this fact places him among the great thinkers of the
millenia. Cf. note 78.
The Topology of Melody
187
specified.77 So, too, Aristoxenus revealed the potentially infinite lichanoi
through the same procedure: the geometry of the line, to the exclusion
of the ear and the voice. And this led him to a similar result: there is no
lichanos immediately succeeding a preceding note, parhypatē, that can be
accurately specified in theory or in practice. The problem raised here by
Aristoxenus had been anticipated a century or so earlier by the philosopher, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae (c. 500–c. 428 b.c.), who observed:78
“In the case of the small, there is no smallest thing, but always something smaller.”
All these things being true of the straight line, a line that has the
characteristics of a physical continuum, Aristoxenus came to realize that
by relying solely on the geometry of the line, he could never resolve
the problem of potentially infinite lichanoi. This meant that there
could be no way to establish a system of attunement whose elements
would be related to one another by chains of logical implications such
that each member of the system would imply every other member.
To be sure, mathematics had succeeded in securing the boundaries of
the consonances: octave, fifth, and fourth. But when it came to fixing
the locations of the notes intervening between these linear boundaries, the mathematical method not only produced discontinuities in
the numerical proportions defining the consonances, but also irrational numbers arising from the division of the consonances. Indeed, as
77
78
Thus, Richard Sorabji, Time, Creation and the Continuum, p. 322: “Aristotle
takes Zeno to have supposed that an infinity of sub-distances would require
an infinite time. To that he gives the right answer, that we must distinguish
between infinite divisibility and infinite length. The distance is infinitely divisible, not infinitely long, and therefore the time available is adequate, because it
is infinite in the appropriate way, that is, infinitely divisible.”
Vors., 59B3 (D-K, 33. 14–18). See Rothstein, Emblems of the Mind, p. 64, who
observes that Anaxagoras anticipated Georg Cantor in this statement. As
Rothstein explains, Cantor, in studying the problem of infinity, dramatically
changed the way in which we think of lists of things. What Cantor has made
us realize is that “space or time itself is so dense with points that any area surrounding a given point contains an infinite number of other points, which, in
turn, connect ‘smoothly’ with one another.” Aristoxenus, in his turn, makes
us realize that if any lichanos, or point on the line of pitch, approaches another
point of pitch in the infinite topos admitting such a point, it must also be
included in the continuous collection of pitches known as lichanoi.
188
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Euclid had proved, intervals of the superparticular variety – fourths,
fifths, and whole-tones – are not divisible rationally at any point whatever, despite all that the ear records to the contrary.79 In sum, then,
where Aristoxenus intuited a seamless melodic continuity, he met with
theoretical imprecision, ambiguity, and incompleteness in the form of
infinite pitch possibilities; and where he perceived by ear and memory a “wondrous order” in the logical succession of melodic notes and
intervals, he came upon mathematical discontinuities in the form of
incommensurable magnitudes.80
Long before Aristoxenus’ time, musicians dealt with problems such
as these by the simple expedient of ignoring them. With only their
innate musical instincts to guide them, they tuned their winds and
strings by ear and often produced music of such surpassing beauty as
to drive incommensurable numbers like √2 out of the mind’s ear. One
such performer prompted the composer Telestes (c. 420–c. 345 b.c.)
to speak of his Lydian airs as the work of the “King of the auloi.” The
music reduced Telestes to this rapturous outpouring:81
79
80
81
Macran, Aristoxenus, p. 248, says accordingly: “But the ear ignoring the mathematical differences attends to the common features in the impressions which
these divisions make upon it, and constitutes accordingly three genera, the
Enharmonic, Chromatic, and Diatonic . . .”
The term “incommensurable” reflects the Greeks’ geometric view of number.
This is made explicit by Plato in the Theaetetus, the dialogue which he dedicated to the memory of the young hero who fell in battle in 369 b.c. As Plato
tells it (147D3–6), Theaetetus credits the mathematician Theodorus of Cyrene
(born c. 460 b.c.) with the full explanation of incommensurability: “Here,
Theodorus was describing something about the sides of squares [square roots,
or dynameis], showing that the sides of squares of three or five feet are not commensurable in length with those of one foot, and in this way he kept taking
up one after another until he reached seventeen feet. At this point he stopped.”
As Thaeatetus surmised (147D7–9), Theodorus stopped because he came upon
square roots “that appeared to be infinite in number, so that one had to try
to collect into a single term one by which all these infinite roots could be
spoken of.” Incommensurable in length thus means that no common measure
exists between these entities. See B. L. van der Waerden, Science Awakening I,
pp. 141–42. Cf. A. Wasserstein, “Theaetetus and the History of the Theory of
Numbers,” CQ, n.s. 8 (1958), 165–67.
Athenaeus, Deipnosophists xiv. 617b.
The Topology of Melody
189
Or that Phrygian, king of the sacred, fair-breathed auloi, who was the first
to attune a shimmering Lydian air that rivalled the Dorian muse, interweaving on his reeds the lovely-winged strain in the melodious voice of his
life’s breath.
Others of Aristoxenus’ predecessors were equally outstanding, not only
as performing artists but, also, like Aristoxenus himself, as leaders of
their own pedagogical or theoretical schools. Of these, the best known
is the celebrated theorist, Damon of Athens (mid-fifth century b.c.),
who was fortunate in having had Plato to represent his views on music’s
powers to change the human soul for better or for worse.82 Also well
known is the composer, dithyrambic poet, and virtuosic aulete, Lasus
of Hermione (sixth century b.c.). Among his many accomplishments
in the field of acoustics and musical theory were his innovations in the
technique of aulos playing, some of which were considerable enough to
have brought about a veritable revolution in the performance of music.83
Equally interesting is the virtuoso harpist, Epigonus of Ambracia (sixth
century b.c.), whom Aristoxenus characterizes as a master-teacher of his
own school, his many accomplishments on the harp having been prodigious enough to win him the epithet: Virtuoso (mousikotatos).84
82
83
84
On Damon and his ethical theory of music, see Chapter 1, note 71. His enormous influence on the musical ideas of Plato has been the focus of intense study,
as, for example, by Lasserre, Plutarque, pp. 80–84; Richter, Zur Wissenschaftslehre
von der Musik, pp. 22–26; Moutsopoulos, La musique dans l’oeuvre de Platon, pp.
67–80. This influence, as treated by Aristotle, is considered by Bélis, Aristoxène,
pp. 56–60.
Lasus’ innovations on the aulos are described by Ps.-Plutarch De mus. Ch. 29.
1141C (Ziegler-Pohlenz, 23. 13–17): “Lasus of Hermione, by adapting the
rhythms to the dithyrambic movement, and by using more notes obtained
by dividing them fractionally (διερριμμένoιϛ), brought the music that existed
before his time into an altered state.” My translation, “by dividing them fractionally,” is influenced by Lasserre, Plutarque, p. 37, who renders the passage,
“par l’adjonction de sons obtenus par fractionnement.” This translation suggests that Lasus was seeking a way to accommodate within the limits of a
tetrachord more notes than mathematical theory would allow. See, however,
Barker, I, p. 235, who translates: “(and so making use of more notes, widely
scattered about).” The italics are mine.
Epigonus was of the same era as Lasus (sixth century b.c.). According to
Athenaeus Deipnosophists xiv. 637–38, he, too, was seeking to enlarge the
190
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
These and other theorists mentioned by Aristoxenus all seemed
to have had one thought in common with him: how to reconcile
the inherent problems of musical space with the evidence of the ear
and the limitations of their instruments. Lasus and the followers of
Epigonus, for example, apparently tried to ameliorate these difficulties by assigning “breadth” to individual notes so as to have them fill
up the spaces denied them by mathematics but allotted to them by
the demands of melody.85 This practice is not unlike that of singers
who, when singing with instrumentalists, deliberately “torque” their
intonation as a way of intensifying the ambient colors of the pitches
being sung. Aristoxenus disdained all such tactics, on the grounds
that they violated the concept of notes as dimensionless points, whose
single occupancy of every melodic space is a function of their fixed
or moveable position in the attunement. The theorists who provoked Aristoxenus’ sharpest criticisms, however, were the Harmonikoi
(so-called by him), who based their theories solely on the evidence of
their ears and the attributes of their musical instruments.86 Eratocles
85
86
melodic capacities of the harp, whether by adding strings, or by increasing the
size of the sound-box, the result of his efforts having been the introduction of
new and beautifully colored (euchroa) variations into his playing.
Aristoxenus Harm. El. I. 3 (Da Rios 7. 19–21) emphatically warns against this
practice if the distinguishing features of musical notes are to be ascertained:
“Anyone who does not want to be forced into the position of Lasus and certain
of the followers of Epigonus, who thought that a note has breadth [platos] must
say something rather more precise about it: and once this has been defined,
many of the subsequent issues will become clearer.” (trans. Barker). Barker, II,
p. 128, n. 12, explains Aristoxenus’ position by stating his “idea that the
moveable notes have ranges of variation which abut, but do not overlap, so that
though each is dimensionless, it is the sole occupant of a determinate region of
pitch.”
One of the most important papers on the subject of Aristoxenus’ position
with regard to his predecessors, the harmonikoi, is that by Andrew Barker,
“`OI KALOUMENOI `ARMONIKOI”: “The Predecessors of Aristoxenus,”
PCPS 24 (1978, 1–2). As Barker points out (p. 5), the criticisms which
Aristoxenus leveled against the harmonikoi are in general to the effect that
they presented no principles, or aitiai, to support their conclusions, many
of which were based on the structures of their instruments. Most important, as Barker argues, Aristoxenus took it upon himself to criticize “all the
fumbling, relatively unscientific attempts to establish the basic outlines of
The Topology of Melody
191
(fifth century b.c.), a leading exponent of this strictly empirical
school, was roundly denounced by Aristoxenus, not only for being
totally unsystematic in his approach, but, even worse, for violating
the phenomena of music.87
Theorists like Eratocles are the very sort whom Socrates singles out
in the Philebus as proof that music is a matter of guesswork and, hence,
is not worthy of being considered a superior art. As Socrates explains to
Protarchus, musical skills are imprecise at best, and at their worst, are a
matter of industrious drills by rote:88
First of all, music is full of it [guesswork], tuning the consonance not by
measurement but by the lucky aim of a practiced hand; and all of this
[guesswork] is in the art of the aulos, too. In the art of the cithara, a hunt
goes on to guess at the exact measure of each string as it sounds its note, so
that there is little certainty, but a great admixture of unreliability.
that science of which Aristoxenus sees himself as the Newton or Darwin.”
Aristoxenus was in fact quite right in his assessment of his own contributions
to the field.
87 Eratocles is not known from any other source than that of Aristoxenus.
Barker, “Music and Perception: A Study in Aristoxenus,” JHS 98 (1978),
11, makes a number of important points in connection with Aristoxenus’
criticism of Eratocles’ methods, one of which is that the phenomena that
Eratocles was violating are “the facts of experience ascertainable by ear,
which the Pythagorean system cannot readily accommodate.” Another is
that the points raised by Aristoxenus take us “beyond musicology and into
philosophy. Aristoxenus is not simply investigating agreed phenomena in
standard ways: he is expressing, and vigorously arguing for, a particular
conception of what music is, and in what the science of the study of music
properly consists” (p. 10). Eratocles’ interest in the cyclical ordering of the
octave in the Enharmonic genus amounted in Aristoxenus’ estimation to
little more than mechanical manipulations. Cf. André Barbera, “Octave
Species,” Journal of Musicology 3 (1984), 229–41. Aristoxenus’ own aim
was far more profound and expansive, as Da Rios, Aristosseno, p. 55 states
so well: “he constructed a homogeneous and regularly-connected system
of tonalities (“construì un sistema di tonalita omogenee e regolarmente”)
that would provide a grand and uniform possibility for modulation.” See
Fig. 4.
88 Plato Philebus 56A3–7. See, however, the view expressed in Chapter 1, note 28.
192
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
The musicians who were performing these tasks liked this sort of
guesswork as little as did Socrates. In fact, they had long been struggling
for a way to base their attunements on something in music to which the
ear bears testimony, something so fundamental that without it, all possibilities of attunement vanish.89 Using their ears then, to the exclusion of
any instruments of measure, they tried to isolate what could not be identified mathematically: the smallest unit-interval into which the melodic
topos could be divided. This mathematically elusive interval is the diesis,
or enharmonic quarter-tone. These strivings after musical accuracy provoked Socrates to say in the Republic that they were “wasting their time
in measuring the audible consonances and notes against one another.”
Glaucon, Socrates’ interlocutor, concurred, with the following revealing
words:90
Yes, by the gods, it is ridiculous how they speak of quarter-tone groups
and such like, bending their ears alongside their instruments as though
they were hunting after their neighbors’ conversation. Some of them claim
that they hear still another pitch in the middle and that this is the smallest
interval which ought to be measured as the unit-interval. Others argue that
the notes sound alike. Both prefer their ears to their minds.
Aristoxenus agreed completely with this position, stating more
than once that no theory could ever be successful if it is uniquely
determined by the empirical evidence. As he put it, a theory “must
rest instead on an appeal to the two faculties of hearing and intellect
89
90
For references to this crucial principle, see Barker, II, p. 129, n. 24.
Plato Rep. 531A4–9. The quarter-tone groups of which Glaucon speaks are set
forth by C. F. Abdy Williams, The Story of Notation, p. 34, Fig. 2. As he points
out (p. 33), it is just this sort of “scheme of pycna” or katapycnosis at which
Aristoxenus scoffed (see note 92). Barker, “Music and Perception,” p. 15, thus
notes that, according to Aristoxenus, what is indeed needed for musicians is
a metron, a standard of measurement to which musicians can refer the melodic
intervals as they are heard. But, as Aristoxenus realized, the enharmonic diesis,
or quarter-tone, could not under any circumstances fulfill the requirement of
a principle, or starting point (archē), for definition. This, as Aristoxenus carefully explained in Harm. El. II. 55 (Da Rios, 68. 10ff.) is because the ear relies
to begin with on those intervals which it can most easily discern: concords.
See Barker, II, p. 168, n. 110.
The Topology of Melody
193
(dianoia).” Thus, for example, where Eratocles and his followers
were attempting to systematize the progressions of tetrachords,
Aristoxenus saw only an impromptu affair unguided by any logical
principles:91
They neither assert any logical reason for their method, nor do they investigate how the other intervals are combined with one another or whether
there is a rational principle of synthesis that delineates every interval from
every other one.
And when the Harmonists (harmonikoi) made diagrams of quarter-tone
sequences in an effort to plot the various scales in use onto some sort of
symmetrical framework, Aristoxenus was too clear-sighted not to perceive the musical inadequacy of these katapyknoseis, or “close-packed”
formations. As he put it:92
We must seek continuity not as the Harmonists do, who attempt to render
it in their “close-packed” diagrams, showing that among the notes that are
successive with one another, it happens that they are separated from one
another by the smallest interval. For it is impossible for the voice to sing
twenty-eight quarter-tones in succession.
However much Aristoxenus had to say against these procedures, they
may in fact have provided him with the wellspring for his own innovative and revolutionary harmonic system. For the Harmonists permitted
Aristoxenus to see that the topology of melody is made up of groups,
91
92
Harm. El. I. 5 (Da Rios, 9. 18–22). As Barker, II, p. 129, n. 24, observes:
“Aristoxenus is firmly committed to the view that these matters are orderly,
subject to fixed principles.” The most important of these fixed principles is that
enunciated by Aristoxenus in Harm. El. I. 29 (Da Rios, 37. 8–13). See note 89.
Harm. El. I. 28 (Da Rios, 36. 1–7). Commenting on the makers of enharmonic
diagrams, Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 95–96 has this to say: “Aristoxenus does not
willingly cite the name of his adversaries, and when he does, it is always to
denigrate their theories; he seems, however, to consider Eratocles with a little
more indulgence, because Eratocles, alone among them all ‘tried to enumerate the different forms of a single system in a single genus: the enharmonic
octave.’”
194
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
not unsingable or haphazardly composed groups, but well-organized
structures, which together form a closed world of relations.
In presenting his harmonic theory, Aristoxenus seems to have fallen
victim to his own genius, for he reminds the reader at almost every
turn how novel, how original, and how penetrating are his insights.
All of this provoked even Henry Macran, that most generous scholar,
to speak of his “endless repetitions, his pompous reiterations of ‘Alone
I did it’,”93 And Andrew Barker was similarly moved to observe of
Aristoxenus that he apparently saw “himself as the Newton or Darwin
of harmonic science.”94 However much Aristoxenus’ arrogant posturing may offend scholars and critics, one thing is certain: his doctrine of
harmonics is all that he thought of it and everything that he said of it.
In particular, his belief that a theory of harmonics must rest ultimately
on the doctrine of limits, and his demonstration of this belief, set him
so far afield from his predecessors and contemporaries that he marks
himself as a man per se. Indeed, he had to have had the genius to which
he fell prey.
That his theory has not reached us in complete form is evident from
his numerous references to its presentation in prior and in subsequent
works.95 But what does lie before us tells sufficiently of the new ground
he was breaking. In the end, he would prevent music from degenerating
into pure empiricism and, at the same time, he would preserve music
from being absorbed into the field of acoustical physics. For Aristoxenus
believed that music merits a science of its own, the key to which he
offers in the following statement.96
93
94
95
96
Macran, Aristoxenus, p. 87.
Cf. note 86.
This is especially true of the second book, the loss of its ending, which must
have contained much analysis, being most cruelly felt. Cf. Bélis, Aristoxène,
p. 43 on the end of Book II: “Here, the break between the plan and the explanation leaps before the eyes; similarly, on considering that the pages which
concerned keys, modulation and melodic composition, have disappeared, it is
hard to reconcile our texts of plan 2 [analysis]; moreover, it is tempting to
resolve the problem by making of this book 2 another version of book 1.”
Harm. El. I. 19 (Da Rios, 24. 7–11). It is this principle that guarantees that a
melody be melodious; for despite the immense variety of forms which melody
can assume, there is an immutable law that governs the successions of sounds
The Topology of Melody
195
For the present, let it be said in general that while attunement admits of
many different possibilities in its synthesis of intervals, there is nevertheless
something of such sort which we shall assert to be one and the same in every
attunement, something that embodies so important a function that when it
is taken away, the attunement disappears also.
This “something” that must underlie every truly melodious attunement is presented by Aristoxenus as a logical principle of similitude. By
implementing this principle, he was able to work towards two goals:
the elimination of the Pythagorean principle of proportion from the
substructure of harmonic science; the combination of the ear’s evidence
with that of the deductive powers of the mind. His aim being to purge
harmonic science of any fallacious or slipshod reasoning, he began by
believing in the relativity of infinitesimals, as his revelation concerning
the infinite series of lichanoi demonstrates. For he realized that these
infinite series had no sound basis in mathematical fact. He also believed
in the homogeneity of the melodic topos, but this led him into vagueness and Eleatic-type conundrums, the result being that the moveable
pitches such as lichanos and paranētē could not be demonstrable logically. For if, as he observed, the number of lichanoi, for example, could
not be obtained by counting, then they could not be identified each by
a separate name.
Aristoxenus had somehow to find a way of producing a well-ordered
series of consecutive notes between any two of which no other note
could be inserted. That is, he was trying to make certain that every note
which could not be specified by rational coordinates could be specified in some other way, namely, as the limit of a progression or series
of notes whose own particular coordinates are rational. As he intuited,
every note in this progression would be an upper limiting point on the
one hand, and a lower limiting point on the other.97 These notions of
97
in all truly melodious utterances. This is the law of consonances, the enunciation of which is lost from Book II.
An example of this delimiting process is given by Aristoxenus in Harm.
El. 56–57 (Da Rios, 70. 14–71. 4): “When these progressions have been
set up, we must refer to the ear’s recollection of the outermost limits of
the notes that have been defined; if they seem discordant to the ear, it will
be obvious that the fourth is not two and a half tones; but if they sound
196
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
limit and continuity are, on Aristoxenus’ formulation, not mutually
exclusive. For the continuity of which he speaks is not that of a fog
whose minuscule particles of moisture have become imperceptible; it is,
rather, the kind of continuity that can, by proper mathematical means,
be reduced to the continuity of uniform progressions. To accomplish
this task, Aristoxenus had to devise a completely new and specialized
convention that would facilitate the treatment of continuous magnitudes – magnitudes whose indivisible elements – notes – are intuited to
be discrete. The convention adopted for this purpose by Aristoxenus is a
highly sophisticated mathematics of inequalities that is based on a concept of continuously varying magnitudes which can approach certain
values in the limit. It is rooted in the difference between magnitudes
(megethē) and multitudes (plēthē), and is considered to be the invention
of Eudoxus of Cnidus (c. 408–355 b.c.), the greatest mathematician in
the era of the Academy.98
to the ear as the consonance of a fifth, it will be obvious that the fourth is
two and a half tones. For the lowest of the notes under consideration was
attuned to form a consonance of a fourth with the upper note that is the
note delimiting the lower ditone, the result being that the highest of the
notes under consideration forms with the lowest of them the consonance of
a fifth.” Thus, for example:
As
98
Barker, II, p. 169, n. 114, points out, for all this to be possible, all of the
elements – namely, semi-tones – must be equal.
In speaking of the remarkably sophisticated mathematics of Eudoxus,
Owen, The Universe of the Mind, p. 40, observes most pointedly: “Although
the historical accounts of his [sc. Eudoxus] contributions to mathematics
are not as extensive as one might wish, they suffice to suggest that the
theory of proportion in Euclid V are his. The mathematics of inequalities, introduced here, is highly sophisticated. Of the importance of this
contribution no more need be said than that its definitions of equal ratios
are the same as those in the theory of Dedekind, more than two thousand
The Topology of Melody
197
If the most remarkable thing about Eudoxus’ theory is its applicability
to incommensurable as well as to commensurable quantities, then the
genius of Aristoxenus derives from his application of this remarkable
theory to the science of harmonics. He was in fact the first to do so. By
adapting this theory to the incommensurable intervals that appear in all
melodious attunements, he accomplished something whose importance
cannot be overstated: he freed the science of harmonics from the bonds
of the Pythagorean theory of proportions, the numerical theory that
is applicable only to commensurables. The method that Aristoxenus
adapted to harmonic science is one that involves plēthē, multiplicities
that are countable, as opposed to megethē, magnitudes that are measurable.99 As practiced by Eudoxus, Aristotle, and Archimedes, this method
has been called a “careful manipulation of finite magnitudes.” In reality,
it is a logically rigorous way of setting limits to what would otherwise
be an infinite and, hence, unspecifiable series of terms. A theory of proportion that is wholly independent of commensurability, it is treated by
Euclid in the Seventh Book of his Elements with respect to multitudes.
In all probability, it was Aristotle who familiarized Aristoxenus with
its particulars.100
years later, and that its structure is identical to Weierstrass’ definition of
equal numbers.”
99 As Aristoxenus defined it in Harm. El. I. 15 (Da Rios, 20. 16–17), “a note
(phthongos) is the incidence of the voice on a single point of pitch (tasis).” He
also determined, as seen in note 97, that a note is either the locus of a potential division of an interval (magnitude), or an end-point of an interval after
the division of an interval into smaller intervals. Thus, the single point of
division becomes two points – the respective limits of two parts. Continuing
along this line of reasoning, Aristoxenus began to think of intervals as defined
multitudes rather than as measurable magnitudes. From that point on, he
could treat intervals as collections of units, thus avoiding the problem of
incommensurables.
100 Cf. Sir Th. L. Heath, Euclid’s Elements, Vol. II, p. 280, on Definition 2: “A number is a multitude composed of units.” Thus Heath: “Aristotle has a number
of definitions which come to the same thing: ‘limited multitude’. . . ‘multitude (or combination) of units’ or ‘multitude of indivisibles’. . . . The definition that is most apposite to Aristoxenus’ concerns is “multitude measured
by one” (Metaphysics 1057a3), the measure being unity (Metaphysics 1088a5).
198
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Thus armed, and with his ear as a guide, Aristoxenus ignored the incommensurability of such intervals as the fourth, the fifth, and the wholetone; instead, he arithmetized all such magnitudes as these by making
each interval between the notes he heard open to equivalent consideration.
The result of this operation was that there was no longer a discontinuity between what is numerable (plēthē) and what is measurable (megethē),
but only a symmetrical array of notes. To arrive at this point, Aristoxenus
treated the potentially infinite collections of notes as a totality whose limits
are set by the natural laws of melody. Attending, therefore, to the common
features of all well-attuned melodies, Aristoxenus discovered the constant
limits between notes of well-attuned (emmelēs) melodies to be those of the
consonances: the fourth and the fifth. As he says:101
Let it be assumed that when notes are arranged in a melodic series in any
genus, each note will form either a consonance of a fourth with the fourth
note distant from it, or a consonance of a fifth with the fifth note distant
from it, or both; any note of which this is not the case is unmelodic by forming a dissonance relative to the other notes.
By counting the notes intervening between the limits of the fourth
and fifth, Aristoxenus was in effect establishing a one-to-one correspondence between each note and each number in the sets: 1, 2, 3, 4 and 1,
2, 3, 4, 5, respectively. When he could no longer continue this set of
correspondences, that is, when the process exceeded the capabilities of
the human voice, he stopped the process, which could otherwise have
been extended to infinity. In this way, Aristoxenus produced sets of
notes whose amount was as large as the amount of numbers in the set
of the first four and the first five natural numbers. Such countable sets
are said by mathematicians to be denumerable.
Having done this much, Aristoxenus refined his concept of length and
continuity even further by establishing correspondences between all the
interior, or moveable notes of the tetrachord and the points at which they
divide the melodic topos. He then computed each of these points as a rational number. In this way, he effaced the distinction between rational and
Aristoxenus thus posited a unit of measure such that “not one single unit of
those among myriads differed from any other.” Cf. Plato Philebus 56E2–3.
101 Harm. El. I. 29 (Da Rios, 37. 8–13).
The Topology of Melody
199
irrational, such as the infamous √2. This in turn enabled him to avoid all
such mathematical problems as the knotty semitone or leimma computed
by Plato and the Pythagoreans to be 256 : 243. In sum, Aristoxenus treated
every note on the line of pitch equivalently and, by doing so, he was able
to specify the location of any note in any genus or nuance of attunement.
He began by assuming that what his ear told him was true: the octave
consists of 6 equal whole-tones or their equivalent, that the fourth consists
of two equal whole-tones and a semitone or their equivalent, and that the
fifth consists of three equal whole-tones and a semitone or their equivalent.
This meant that the full complement of semitones in the fourth is 5, that
in the fifth it is 6, and that in the octave it is 12. He thereupon adopted as
his quantum model the number 12 and in the end succeeded in reducing
the geometrical idea of a magnitude (megethos) to the arithmetic idea of a
collection (plēthos) of discrete units.102
Without the assistance of mathematics, and with his ear alone to
guide him, Aristoxenus had discovered that musical space is incommensurable with the acoustical laws of attunement. He did this by tuning
his lyre or cithara using perfect fourths and fifths, thus demonstrating to
himself that the six whole-tones that seem so equal to the musical ear do
not really fit into the space of an octave. Something, however minimal,
always remains left over. The Pythagoreans and Euclid had proved this
truth mathematically, and tried to resolve it by forcing musical space
to conform to the laws of mathematics. Aristoxenus’ master-stroke was
to distribute the acoustical flaw in the heart of the octave throughout
102 What
Aristoxenus intuited was that the two classes of notes and their reciprocal intervals can be put into a one-to-one correspondence whereby the positive
whole numbers are in a one-to-one correspondence with their reciprocals:
1 2 3 4 5 6........12
1 –12 –13 –14 –15 –16..........12
–1
Hence, these two classes have the same number of elements in them. The number that represents the quantity of elements in these two classes is 12. Twelve
thus means something: it calls to mind the group of elements for which this
number denotes the quantity. Aristoxenus arrived at the number 12 by a rational approximation whereby he had the square root of two define altogether new
numbers; he then added these new numbers to the set of rational numbers of
harmonic theory. Such a procedure is described by Alistair Macintosh Wilson,
The Infinite in the Finite, pp. 379–80.
200
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
all its parts so evenly that the ear would accept this approximation to
the truth for what it is: a “sweet division.” Aristoxenus was doing for
harmonics nothing less than what mathematicians had been doing for
geometry since the days of Anaxagoras, Eudoxus, Theodorus, Theaetetus,
and Archimedes, to mention only a few: express the values of transcendental numbers like π and irrational numbers like √2 as accurately
as possible. In approximating the value of π, for example, Archimedes
proved that the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter is
less than 3–17 but greater than 310
– , a minimal difference. And to approxi71
mate the value of √2, mathematicians had arrived at 75–. Consequently,
when this approximation, being that of the diagonal of the square, is
continued, the diagonal of the square turns out to lie between 1.414213
and 1.414214, a fraction so minimal as to be imperceptible.103 To arrive
at this degree of imperceptibility is what motivated Aristoxenus to
compute the whole-tone as embracing twelve equal parts. The number 12 therefore means something: it calls to mind the group of notes
for which this number denotes the quantity. Thus, the number 12, on
Aristoxenus’ standard of measurement, does not denote an interval per
se in melody; rather, it denotes the quantity of a whole-tone. In speaking of such a thing as a twelfth of a tone, he explains:104 “Such elements
are not melodic: for we mean that an element is unmelodic which does
not per se have a position in a scale-system.”
The beauty of Aristoxenus’ solution to the problems of musical
space lies in its simplicity. It is in fact so simple a solution that it has
gone unappreciated by almost everyone but the master of acoustical
science, Hermann Helmholtz. Helmholtz did more than appreciate Aristoxenus’ efforts; he cited him for having laid the foundations
for Equal Temperament. He mentions the two critical steps taken by
Aristoxenus that led to this discovery: (1) the tuning by fourths and
fifths that revealed the excess of twelve fifths over seven octaves, this
being the small interval called comma by the Pythagoreans; (2) distributing this acoustical flaw over the twelve fifths, making for a division
of the octave into twelve equal semitones. With that accomplished,
103 Cf. Heath (note 100), p. 119: “This gives the means of carrying the approxima-
tion to any degree of accuracy that may be desired.”
El. I. 25 (Da Rios, 33. 4–5).
104 Harm.
The Topology of Melody
201
Aristoxenus could state that the fourth consists of two whole-tones and
a semitone and, as Helmholtz pointedly observed of that statement,
“[It] is exactly true only in equal temperament.”105
By dividing the octave into twelve equal semitones, Aristoxenus
distributed the acoustical flaw among the various genera and nuances
of melody so that no interval in any pitch range or topos would sound
too far out of tune. This division offered musicians free modulation
from one scale-system to another, from one genus to another, and from
one key (tonos) to another. In selecting 12 as the number denoting
a whole-tone, Aristoxenus was anticipating how acousticians would
temper the octave centuries later: that is, finding the twelfth root of
2, or 1.05947631. For, as they calculated, on increasing the frequency
of any note whatever by the factor 1.0594631, the pitch of that note
will be raised a semi-tone. Had Aristoxenus gone on to multiply
1 by 2 twelve times, he would have arrived at 12√2 = 1:1.0594631,
which modern acousticians approximate to 84:89. Carrying the number 12 even further, modern acousticians divide the interval between
each pair of notes into 100 equal parts, these intervals now having
the common ratio 1200√2 = 1:10005778. These parts are called
cents.106 This Archimedean principle of dividing entities into smaller
and smaller parts, thereby achieving a closer and closer approximation
to the truth, is what governs Aristoxenus’ harmonic mapping of the
octave.
Denoting the whole-tone by the number 12, the quantity of the
semi-tone will be 6, that of the fourth which limits the tetrachord will
be 30, and that of the octave will be 72. With these quanta in place,
Artistoxenus was able to compute the exact proportions of the tetrachordal divisions in the three genera and the chroai or nuances using
whole numbers:107
105 Herman Helmholtz, On the Sensations of Tone, p. 548.
106 Commenting on this procedure, Helmholtz (note 105),
p. 431, says: “The
object of temperament (literally, ‘tuning’), is to render possible the expression of an indefinite number of intervals by means of a limited number
of tones without distressing the ear too much by the imperfections of the
consonances.”
107 See Macran, Aristoxenus, p. 249, for a concise table of the genera and nuances. Cf.
Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 157–58. See Fig. 7, in which the notes are placed on a graph.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
202
Genera:
Diatonic:
½ tone
6
½ tone
1 tone
12
½ tone
Enharmonic:
6
¼ tone
3
6
¼ tone
3
Soft Chromatic:
1
1
4
¾ tone
4
¾ tone
4½
½ tone
4½
¾ tone
Chromatic:
1 tone
12
1and ½
tone
18
ditone
24
Chroai:
Hemiolic
Chromatic:
Soft Diatonic:
∕3tone
6
∕3tone
9
1 and 5∕6
tone
22
1 and ¾
tone
21
1 and ¼
tone
15
Figure 7. Six Meson Tetrachords Distributed Over Thirty Equal Parts
The Topology of Melody
203
Aristoxenus’ terms bear an interesting relation to what Nicomachus later
identified as consecutive, or regularly occurring, numbers.108 Nicomacus’ most
important observations relate to the properties of such (Aristoxenian) groups
of three consecutive numbers taken from the natural series, as, for example,
1, 2, 3 = 6 (Nicomachus’ second triangle), which equals Aristoxenus’ semitones: 1, 3, 5 = 9 (Nicomachus’ second square), which equals Aristoxenus’
Soft Diatonic –34 tone, and 3, 4, 5 = 12 (Nicomachus’ second pentagon), which
equals Aristoxenus’ whole-tone. This operation with the number 12 also
yields Aristoxenus’ Soft Diatonic 1 and –41 tone (= 15, or 4, 5, 6) and his
Enharmonic ditone (= 24, or 7, 8, 9). In other words, this amounts to a special kind of decimal terminology initiated by Aristoxenus.
108 Nicomachus
Intro to Arithmetic, II. 21 (Hoche, 120. 5. 20–121. 6. 24). See
D’Ooge, Nicomachus of Gerasa. Introduction to Arithmetic, p. 131. Cf. Heath,
History, I, pp. 114–15.
6 Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs
of Cyrene
Rara avis in terris
nigroque simillima cycno
Juvenal Satire 6. 165
It has been maintained by scholars critical of his t heory
that Artistoxenus replaced the deductive and speculative method of
the Pythagoreans with the empirical and experimental method of
practicing musicians. But, as I argued in Chapter 5, this interpretation of Aristoxenus’ accomplishments does not stand close scrutiny. For
Aristoxenus’ writings show clearly that there can be no empirical method
for musicians without there first being speculative concepts and intuited forms of order.1 What also becomes apparent in Aristoxenus’ theory is that there is no speculative thinking whose musical concepts do
not reveal, on close examination, the empirical material from which they
stem. Aristoxenus obtained this material by means of his ear (aisthēsis),
by experiments with tunings, and by close observation of the conclusions
1
As argued elsewhere (cf. Levin, “Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory,” TAPA [1972],
211ff.). Aristoxenus’ epochal contribution to the theory of music was based
upon the notion of synesis, a musical intuition, or competence, comprising one’s
implicit musical knowledge. This a priori notion of musical synesis stood for
Aristoxenus “not in the thing that is adjudicated, but in the thing that does
the adjudicating.” (Harm. El. 41; Da Rios, 52. 3–4). As Aristotle would have
put it, synesis was the efficient cause of music. Aristotle’s dictum, as expressed
by him in Nicomachean Ethics 1140A12–14, was not lost then on Aristoxenus:
“All art is concerned with creation, and to practice an art is to contemplate how
to create something that admits of existence or non-existence, and the efficient
cause of which is in the maker, but not in the thing made.”
204
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
205
he collected. He sought afterward the means to make these conclusions
demonstrable.
Aristoxenus was bent on finding a correct standard for musicians.
His goal was not simply to assert a higher ideal against Pythagorean
theory; it was, rather, to vindicate the nature of music against the excessive demands of mathematics in Pythagorean harmonic theory. His
own theory is not, therefore, as has been claimed, a slip-shod desertion
of a traditional harmonic ordinance; it is, instead, a serious and systematic effort to impose an altogether new one. At the core of the matter is
the presence of irrationality in mathematics: whereas the Pythagoreans
tried endlessly to solve the problem of irrationality, Aristoxenus began
by admitting its insolubility as a fact of musical life. What he had
grasped with his naked ear (aisthēsis) and what he had parsed with
his rational mind (dianoia) led him to his master-stroke: the inclusion in his system of numbers those irrationals that had so plagued
the Pythagoreans. He did this by inventing a new number: twelve.
By dividing the whole-tone into twelve equal parts, he split up the
musical universe in such a way as to leave no distinction between rational numbers and irrational numbers. For by defining each division as
a separate number, he discovered that he could avoid all the knotty
mathematical problems involved in the standard method of dividing
the whole-tone.2
Having made each point between the limits of the whole-tone open
to equivalent consideration, Aristoxenus in effect homogenized the
whole system of numbers and created what can truly be called a continuum: a smooth array whose center can be stipulated by one means only –
the demands of melodic consecution. Thus, whereas the Pythagoreans
2
As Louis Laloy and Annie Bélis have both demonstrated to a certainty, the influence of Aristotle is felt everywhere in the writings of his disciple, Aristoxenus.
This is especially the case in Aristoxenus’ inclusion of irrationals among the
rational numbers, this leading to a line of numbers between which there are no
gaps but only a seamless magnitude. The fundamental feature of this method
is the postulation of magnitudes that are as great as need be for practical musical purposes and as divisible into whatever sizes one might wish for strictly
melodic reasons. Here, Aristotle’s doctrine, as expressed in Nichomachean Ethics
1094bllff., of seeking only that measure of accuracy which the subject-matter
allows as acceptable comes very much into play.
206
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
had focused only on the discontinuity of musical space, Aristoxenus
trained his thought on the perceived continuity of musical space and in
his own innovative way succeeded in reconciling it with the mathematical facts of discontinuity. In so doing, he laid bare the source of music’s
ineffable energy: the creation of continuity out of discontinuity, or what
Edward Rothstein so aptly calls “a sort of inversion of the calculus.”3
The compulsion of pure musical thought is that on which Aristoxenus’
theory of music is centered; it not only defined the polemic tone of his
writing; it also put him into direct opposition with all the mathematical formulations of the Pythagoreans and with all the empirical ideas of
those professors of music, the Harmonikoi. He did not have a mathematician’s passion for exactitude as an end in itself, but a musician’s desire
to penetrate to the ultimate melodic ground for every musical event.
He regarded his quantum model, therefore, as an objective discovery,
one which allowed him to reduce the geometrical idea of a megethos
(a magnitude or interval) to the arithmetical idea of a plēthos (collection)
of discrete units or notes.4 The number twelve denoted for him the
quantity of a whole-tone. On his conception then, given the quantum
3
Rothstein, Emblems of Mind, p. 102. As Rothstein observes (p. 70), “The notion
of continuity . . . was so hard to formulate mathematically because intuitively
it seemed so transparent and obvious to the senses.”
4 As will be discussed in the chapter to follow, the one theory, that of the
Pythagoreans, describes a discontinuous geometrically quantified reality; the
other, that of Aristoxenus, a smoothly undulating continuum of melodious
motion. The first is vividly manifest in the harmonic series, a phenomenon of
acoustical nature; the second is recognized by the ear as equal temperament.
When the geometry of the line, which encompasses the harmonic series, is integrated with a melodic topos that has been equally tempered, a most mysterious
element is produced: melodic gravity. The greatest mystery about this element
is that it is not itself smooth and continuous, but comes to us in discrete packets
of tension and resolution, which Aristoxenus called epitasis and anesis, respectively. Cf. Chapter 5, note 50, on Casals’ identification of these gravitational
phenomena in melody. These are the mysterious phenomena that create a triangulation of forces whose combined effect produces magnetic fields of energy
and invests melody with a third dimension. They are described rhapsodically
by Bowman, Philosophical Perspectives on Music, p. 274, “as surfaces with varying degrees of relief, opacity, and translucence, and, indeed, even into three
dimensional masses that may be penetrated, carved, and sculpted by silences.”
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
207
twelve, every possible melodic interval is a finite multiple of the minimum quantum – twelve.5
The outcome of Aristoxenus’ manipulation of finite numbers is a
perfectly symmetrical melodic topos, the basis for a perfect harmony of
parts. But the balance between this – Aristoxenus’ invention of melodic
symmetry – and the material world – the mathematical specifics of an
imperfect geometry – is a delicate one. Aristoxenus’ critics treated his
method, therefore, as a flawed creation, a precipitate fall from the grace
of mathematical truth. No one, it seems, appreciated the sophistication
of Aristoxenus’ method or the thoroughly modern concept on which
it is framed: that one can make the difference between the original
form – the whole-tone, for example – and the spaces filling up that
form as small as one pleases. To be sure, Ptolemy saw far enough into
Aristoxenus’ method only to dismiss it as simply a way of “doing something with number and reason.”6 He pointedly objected, therefore, to
the Aristoxenian method, because it focused on intervals and not on the
notes themselves. As he said:7
They [sc. The Aristoxenians] do not, in this way even define the differences,
because they do not relate them to the things to which they belong [i.e., the
notes]; for there will turn out to be infinitely many of them in each ratio if
the things that make them are not defined first . . . (trans. Barker).
In a most useful note, Solomon, Ptolemy states the grounds for the criticism against Aristoxenus from the time of Ptolemy down through that
5
On the cosmic implications of the number 12 in musical thought, see Chapter 5,
Fig. 6. On the basis of this quantum, Aristoxenus could compute the diesis, or
Enharmonic quarter-tone, with the whole number, 3. This meant that intervals
such as the eklusis (= 3 dieseis) and the ekbolē (= 5 dieseis) could be computed by
the simple addition of quarter-tones. Aristoxenus’ own computation of these
intervals is lost. They are defined, however, by Bacchius Introduction to the Art of
Music I. 37 (Jan, 300. 17–20) and I. 42 (Jan, 302. 3–6). Bacchius thus explains
in I. 37 (Jan, 300. 18–20) why they occur only in the Enharmonic genus. For
discussion, see Solomon, “EKBOLE and EKLUSIS in the musical treatise of
Bacchius,” 113–14. On the accessibility of the number 12, cf. Georges Arnoux,
Musique Platonicienne, p. 38.
6 Ptolemy Harm. I. 9 (Düring, 20. 8–9).
7 Ptolemy Harm. I. 9 (Düring, 20. 23–24).
208
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of Mountford, Winnington-Ingram, and Schlesinger to the present day.
As he makes clear, no one of Aristoxenus’ critics saw anything rigorous
in his method:8
Ptolemy finds both inexcusable and incomprehensible the Aristoxenian
method of intervals. They regard them spatially (essentially dividing the
scale by an imaginary unit of measurement – the 1/12 tone) and not as
ratios, i.e. differences, of string lengths.
What Ptolemy found both inexcusable and incomprehensible was
Aristoxenus’ disregard of all irrational ratios. But, as no one seemed to
appreciate, Aristoxenus, by appealing to his own musical intuition, saw
the problem of irrationals as a simple matter of calculating limits. By
defining a certain limit – as of the lichanos, for example – Aristoxenus
was in effect specifying a point beyond which all the member notes of
the series would be within that small distance of the limit. Once he
defined this notion of the limit, it was possible for him to view irrationals in a completely new way. Thus, the irrational whole-tone was
treated by him not as something outside of the musically rational universe; it had simply to be calculated differently. This involved arranging
whole numbers as points on a line, and, consequently, as treating the
irrationals as just so many other points on a line. The whole-tone therefore contained twelve such points and the tetrachord thirty such points.
Aristoxenus’ method of limits was in all reality, therefore, a systematic
and rigorous attempt to come as close as possible to the irrational – to
the square root of two – even though he was never to reach it. For the
bitter truth about irrationals such as the square root of two and pi is
that they always lie beyond the reach of boundaries. Thus, Aristoxenus
did as Eudoxus before him, and as Archimedes after him: he settled for
approximations.9 His approximations in the divisions of the tetrachord
turned out to satisfy the ear, thus “saving the phenomena.”
8
9
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 29, n. 149.
The method used by Eudoxus and Archimedes is characterized by Dijksterhus,
Archimedes, p. 130, as an “indirect passage to the limit” instead of the more
usual “exhaustion method.” Of the more common expression, Dijksterhuis
says: “for a mode of reasoning which has arisen from the conception of the
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
209
In his Introduction to Harmonics, Cleonides treated Aristoxenus’
tetrachordal divisions as self-evident knowledge. He did not understand the intellectual process by which Aristoxenus had arrived at
these divisions; he simply accepted them for the immediate perception of notes and their relations whose existence was guaranteed by
his ear. Cleonides had no difficulty, therefore, in computing the “Soft
Diatonic” tetrachord, for example, as consisting of 6 + 9 + 15 units;
nor did he find the “Soft Chromatic” any less difficult to represent
in the Aristoxenian addition of 4 + 4 + 22 units.10 Like Cleonides,
Aristides Quintilianus was also convinced that the Aristoxenian divisions depicted true melodic forms, his only alteration of the master’s
computations being his own doubling of the quanta. He thus represented the tetrachord as consisting of sixty units of measure (instead of
Aristoxenus’ thirty) and thereby filled up the intervals with segments
even smaller than those computed by Aristoxenus. Aristides’ doubling
of the quanta yielded these results:11
Diatonic:
Chromatic:
Enharmonic:
Soft Chromatic:
Hemiolic Chromatic:
Soft Diatonic:
12 + 24 + 24
12 + 12 + 36
6 + 6 + 48
8 + 8 + 44
9 + 9 + 42
12 + 18 + 30
Aristides’ doubling of the units of measure had the obvious advantage
of making the three-quarter tone interval of the Hemiolic Chromatic
easier to compute with the whole number, 9, than with Aristoxenus’
inexhaustibility of the infinite, this is about the worst name that could have
been devised.”
10 Cleonides, Introduction to Harmonics, Chapters 6 and 7 (Jan, 189.9–193.2). These
Aristoxenian numbers are thus genetic assemblages such that each is a form
(eidos) comprising unique eidetic units, or monads. Cf. note 29.
11 Aristides Quintilianus De Musica I. 9 (Winnington-Ingram, 17. 21–18. 4).
These divisions are tabulated by Mathiesen, Aristides, p. 85, n. 101. As
explained by Barker, II, p. 419, n. 111: “Aristides doubles the figures, as does
Ptolemy sometimes [for example, Harm. I. 11; Düring, 29. 12ff.] so as to make
them all whole numbers.”
210
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
fraction 4–12.12 But his representation of the facts, like that of Cleonides,
betrays no idea of how Aristoxenus came to replace classical mathematical reasoning with the quantum concept by which he succeeded in
probing the finer structures of melody.
Aristoxenus had found in his system of correspondences a link between
arithmetic and geometric sequences whereby he replaced the multiplication of string-length ratios with the addition of whole numbers; and
he replaced the inverse operation, that of the division of string-length
ratios, with the subtraction of whole numbers. This enabled him to
define certain organized structures of melodic elements whose relations
to one another had theretofore escaped reliable specification by classical Pythagorean harmonic analysis. Aristoxenus accomplished this by
splitting up the mathematically indivisible whole-tone in the ratio of
9:8 into twelve separate and equal parts. This was in effect to split up
the square root of two – the canonic measurement of the semi-tone (3:2
√2) – into six equal parts. By intermingling these parts on the same
line of pitch with the rational numbers derived from string-length proportions, Aristoxenus ingeniously defined each melodically determined
point on the line of pitch with a rational number. Thus, for example, in
the Enharmonic tetrachord, parhypatē was assigned the number 3 (12
–3 of
a whole-tone) and therefore a quarter-tone distant from hypatē; lichanos
was accordingly assigned 6 (12
–6 ) of a whole-tone, being a semi-tone dis13
tant from hypatē:
12
13
Cf. Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 41, n. 201.
Da Rios, Aristosseno, p. 37, n. 2, thus explains: “The tetrachord, or fourth, is
formed of two whole-tones and a half and, therefore, of thirty twelfths of a
tone.” This permitted the loci of the moveable notes, lichanos and parhypatē,
to be ascertained with some degree of accuracy. According to West, Ancient
Greek Music, p. 167, Aristoxenus’ success in this enterprise was not the result
of a rigorously thought-out theory: “In effect he [sc. Aristoxenus] is operating with a tempered tone of 200 cents and a tempered fourth of 500 cents.
He does not understand that that is what he is doing; he is simply working
by ear.” On the contrary, as is being argued here, Aristoxenus was attempting, first, to reconstruct as far as was possible a precisely demarcated attunement which is given to, or realizable in, perception; and, second, to show that
this attunement has a property that is mathematically consistent. Aristoxenus’
was a mental achievement, therefore, and not simply a hit-or-miss “working by
ear.” It depended on the notion of tetrachordal continuity (synecheia) which, as
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
E
hypatē
E+
3
parhypatē
F
6
lichanos
211
A
This system amounted to much more than just “doing something
with number and reason,” as Ptolemy had put it. It was, rather, a new
way of dealing with an actual set of intellectual intuitions – the very
backbone of human knowledge. The principle that lies at the root of
this system is the natural law of melodic consecution, a rational synthesis wherein every note on the line of pitch is open to equivalent consideration and where every note on the line of pitch has a corresponding
note a fourth or a fifth above it or below it. It is a rational synthesis
that depends on treating the infinite collection of tonal elements as a
whole, or as a totality; the result of this treatment is the imposition
of consonantal bonds on the infinitude of the melodic topos. This gave
Aristoxenus the clue to harmonic symmetry, which would guide him in
all melodic circumstances.14
Ptolemy, despite his criticism of Aristoxenus’ approach, actually
tried to reconcile Aristoxenus’ calculations with his own strictly canonic
measurements. In fact, he went to great lengths to do so, as he apparently saw in Aristoxenus’ system a serious attempt to preserve the musical phenomena, not to contradict them. But, as Ptolemy’s efforts show,
he failed at the outset to grasp the full implications of Aristoxenus’
principle of rational synthesis. What he did is best described in his own
words:15
Aristoxenus showed, is a function of equality in temperament. Cf. Vogel, Die
Enharmonik der Griechen, I. pp. 43–44 on Aristoxenus und die gleichschwebende
Temperatur. Aristoxenus’ quantum, 12, can thus be grasped only in thought; on
his reckoning, it is itself indivisible in virtue of its purely noetic character.
14 To apprehend this symmetry, the ear alone was insufficient; the musical mind
(dianoia) had also to come into play. For, as Aristoxenus understood, it is the
mind that defines all the musical elements, not simply according to their positions on the line of pitch, but according to their functions (dynameis) in melodic
contexts. Cf. Henderson, “Ancient Greek Music,” pp. 343–44.
15 Ptolemy Harm. II. 13 (Düring, 69. 29–70. 4). Barker, II, p. 345, n. 112,
explains those respects in which Ptolemy’s representations of Aristoxenus’ divisions are misleading. As he points out, the numbers that Ptolemy assigned
212
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
In order that the distance covered by the fourth below the disjunction
[i.e., the fourth descending from A to E] may span thirty parts, the number proposed by Aristoxenus, and in order that when we take his divisions
in the larger context we may still understand the segment consisting of
a tetrachord through the same numbers, we have posited that the length
from the common limit to the lowest note of the octave set out consists
of one hundred and twenty segments, and the note higher than this by a
fourth is ninety, in epitritic ratio [4:3], so that the note a fifth higher than
the lowest is eighty, on the basis of hemiolic ratio [3:2], and the highest
note of the octave is sixty, in duple ratio [2:1]. The intermediate, moveable notes take their numbers in accordance with the ratios of each genus.
(trans. Barker)
The larger context within which Ptolemy adapted Aristoxenus’
tetrachord of thirty units is the two-octave Greater Perfect System
consisting of four tetrachords and hence computed to be an extent of
120 segments. The octave thus consists of sixty segments, the fifth of
eighty segments, and the fourth of ninety segments. This means that all
the consonantal relations established by string-length proportions are
maintained as given on the canon:16
Octave: 120:60 = 2:1
Fifth: 120:80 = 3:2
Fourth: 120:90 = 4:3
In sum then, Ptolemy’s calculations, which turn out to be like those
of Aristides Quintilianus, completely bypass Aristoxenus’ concept of
melodic intervals as equal distances on the line of pitch. Instead, Ptolemy
tried to make the results that Aristoxenus had obtained by ear and by
16
to the Aristoxenian interval-boundaries “either fail to capture Aristoxenus’
intentions, or cannot be mapped directly on to the kanonion in the manner
required.”
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 97, n. 236, observes that Ptolemy’s choice of the number 60, denoting a sixtieth part of a unit, may be attributed to the influence
of Babylonian astronomy. He thus says: “This serves to corroborate what little
evidence we have that Ptolemy came to the study of harmonics after his astronomical education was well established.”
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
213
reason agree with those yielded by the string-length proportions on the
canon.
Throughout his Harmonics, Ptolemy adhered to the Pythagorean principle that gave priority to the epimoric, or superparticular ratios such as
3:2 and 4:3. He did so on the basis that such ratios, by being the closest
to the equality of the duple ratio (2:1), were bound to yield intervals that
would sound melodic to the ear.17 To be sure, this principle is contradicted by the ratio of the octave and a fourth, an interval which sounds
melodic to the ear, but whose ratio is neither duple nor epimoric, and
hence appears to break the rule of mathematically determined concordancy. Ptolemy circumvented this discrepancy neatly by arguing that
8:3, the ratio in question, is in reality put together from the epimoric
and the duple (4:3 x 2:1) and therefore does not contradict the testimony
of the ear.18 In other words, as Ptolemy’s analysis has it, if the numbers
be true, the intervals produced will sound melodic to the ear. The proof
that this is so comes from the canon; for if the moveable bridge divides
the string as dictated by the numerical ratios, the sounds produced will
be accepted by the ear as the consonances: fourth, fifth, octave, and the
octave plus a fourth or a fifth. It is only when the moveable or intermediate notes of the tetrachord are introduced that mathematics and the
ear become disputants. That the operations of mathematics are infinitely
superior to anything that we can hear or even think about the moveable
notes is the doctrine that lies behind Ptolemy’s conclusion to the thirteenth chapter of Book II of the Harmonics:19 “In the case of the moveable
notes in between, they assume their numbers in accordance with the
ratios of each genus.”
17
18
19
Ptolemy Harm. I. 7 (Düring, 15, 29–16. 2). As Barker, II, p. 289, n. 66,
observes: “There are of course other pairs of ratios that divide 2:1 more nearly in
half (e.g., 17: 12 x 24:17), but they are not epimorics.” Ptolemy’s Pythagorean
principle is made explicit by Euclid in his Sectio Canonis (see Ch. 4). It holds
that the number in question actually becomes the being (in this case, a consonance) of the thing to which it belongs.
Ptolemy Harm. I. 7 (Düring, 16. 10–12). Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 23, captures
Ptolemy’s logicist’s certainty on this point: “Now, that this interval is not
superparticular nor multiple does not trouble us at all, since we proposed nothing of the sort beforehand.”
Ptolemy Harm. II. 13 (Düring, 70. 3–4).
214
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
In the next chapter, Ptolemy preserves the computations of all those
mathematicians and theorists who agreed that musical intervals could be
expressed only by numerical ratios (as of string-length proportions), who
agreed also that the octave was less than the sum of six whole-tones, and
that the whole-tone itself could not be divided into equal parts.20 The computations preserved by Ptolemy are those of Archytas, the Pythagorean;
of Didymus, a musician who lived at the time of Nero; of Eratosthenes of
Cyrene, a man of immense learning who was appointed head of the library
at Alexandria about 235 b.c. by Ptolemy III Euergetes; and of Ptolemy
himself.21 The numbers given by Ptolemy correspond to the lengths of
string on the canon, the smallest number (60) assigned to the highest
pitched note (nētē Diezeugmenon), the greatest number (120) assigned to
the lowest pitched note (hypatē Meson). Each of Ptolemy’s three tables
or kanonia contains the ratios for the Enharmonic genus; the Chromatic
genus (also called tonic Chromatic) and its nuances or shades (soft or
flat Chromatic and hemiolic Chromatic); the Diatonic (also called tense
or syntonic Diatonic) and the soft or flat Diatonic. To these kanonia of
Archytas, Didymus, Eratosthenes, and those of his own making, Ptolemy
adds the computations of Aristoxenus that are listed by Ptolemy in all of
the same tetrachordal divisions as those named earlier.22
Outstanding among all these calculations are the differences in mathematical language between Aristoxenus’ formulations and those of all the
other theorists. The ratios of everyone but Aristoxenus are clearly and
unambiguously defined in such a way that each term means the same
20
Thus Ptolemy Harm. I, 11 (Düring, 25. 18–26. 2): “If, however, we construct
six tones in succession by ratio [or ‘reason,’ logos], the extreme notes will make
a magnitude slightly greater than the octave; and it will always be by the same
degree of difference, that is, double the difference between the leimma and the
half-tone, which, in accordance with the first of our postulates, comes very
close to being in the ratio 65:64” (trans. Barker).
21 On Ptolemy’s sources here, see Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 8, n. 38, where all the
pertinent references are brought together.
22 The tables of divisions are set out by Ptolemy Harm. II. 14 (Düring, 70–73) and
are translated by Barker, II, pp. 347–50 and by Solomon, Ptolemy, pp. 99–103.
See also Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 468–72. As Mathiesen, op. cit., p. 467,
observes, “The Aristoxenian parts cannot be accurately represented in this
system of string lengths, although the intervals that result are close to those
described by Aristoxenus.”
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
215
thing to each theorist named – to Archytas, to Didymus, to Eratosthenes,
and to Ptolemy himself.23 And this thing, so clearly and unambiguously
defined, is the meaning contained in the original Pythagorean tetraktys: 6 :
8 : 9 :12. Thus, 6, for example, in the language of the Pythagorean harmonicians, defines one limit of the fourth (6:8 = 3:4), of the fifth (6:9 = 2:3),
and of the octave (6:12 = 1:2). These are the incontrovertible facts that are
revealed on the canon, the instrument of acoustical precision, facts which
Ptolemy and all the other theorists except Aristoxenus accepted as axiomatic. Aristoxenus, however, was not slow to detect the inadequacy of this
mathematical language when it came to the imperatives of melody. As
he stated most emphatically, these facts that were accepted as axiomatic
by the mathematical harmonicians could never succeed in defining the
infinite gradations of melodic change. Aristoxenus was thus compelled
to find a new way to express the subtleties of melodic thought. This new
way was a true blend of empiricism and reason, and it made for an explosive combination. It is reflected in Aristoxenus’ use of the number 6; for as
used by Aristoxenus, the number 6 comes from another world entirely –
that of the finite within the infinite. In this world the number 6 means
only one thing: the quantity of the semitone.
Because the observational values of intervals such as thirds of tones,
which occur in the hemiolic Chromatic, could be measured by traditional
mathematics with only limited accuracy, Aristoxenus thought it sufficient
to give approximately the quantities to be calculated.24 His conviction grew
23
24
Eratosthenes’ computations for the Enharmonic and the tonic (or intense)
Chromatic stand out from all the rest for being identical to those of Aristoxenus,
even though they are given in ratios. The inference is that Eratosthenes took
Aristoxenes’ quanta of twelve units seriously enough to rationalize them in
terms of string lengths. Thus, Aristoxenus’ Enharmonic tetrachord computed
in units of twelve is: 3 + 3 + 24 = 30. This was worked out by Eratosthenes to
be: 40:30 x 39:38 x 19:15 = 4:3. And Aristoxenus’ Chromatic tetrachord computed in units of 12 is: 6 + 6 + 18 = 30. This was worked out by Eratosthenes
to be: 20:19 x 19:18 x 6:5 = 4:3. Eratosthenes’ rendition of the Diatonic, if
he in fact succeeded in computing it, has not come down to us. As Barker, II,
p. 346, n. 117, observed of Eratosthenes’ computations: “there is no place in
any known form of Greek harmonic theory for ratios of that sort.”
The terms hemiolic (hemi = half and holos = whole) refer to the most characteristic interval of the Chromatic genus: the tone-and-a-half (as between a lichanos
Meson, Gb and a mesē, A).
216
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
that his results would be more exact the smaller the segments he used;
and even that every preassigned accuracy – as for moveable notes like
lichanos and parhypatē – could be achieved by using a sufficient number of
segments. Aristoxenus was centuries ahead of his time. For his approach
grasps the very essence of real numbers, the infinite decimal fractions of
which form the domain of real or continuous numbers.25 Drawing on the
numbers from this domain, Aristoxenus computed parhypatē to be distant
from hypatē Meson by 12
–4 or –13 of a whole-tone; and he computed lichanos
Meson to be twice that distance from hypatē Meson or 12
–8 , namely, –31 of a
21
whole-tone. The remainder of the tetrachord is on this computation 12
–,
26
or, 1 and ¾ tones. Speaking for all traditionally minded harmonicians,
Winnington-Ingram observed of Aristoxenus’ efforts in this instance:27
There is in fact no musically probable interval that can be held to be represented by the top interval of this tetrachord and yet distinguished from
that of the hemiolic chromatic. I suggest that Aristoxenus, favouring the
equal division of pycna, and knowing his third-tone (28
– ) to be a true musical
27
interval, assumed that by doubling it he could obtain a satisfactory lichanos, and so produced a completely factitious nuance.
In an exactingly detailed and methodically argued passage,
Aristoxenus determines the closest approximation to what the ear
assumes as evident: the lowest chromatic lichanos, which is one-third
25
As Aristoxenus has it, the function of the number 12 is not only the relationship
it expresses, but also its single fixed value in the context of these relationships.
The number 12 thus forms a well-ordered set and as such can be regarded as
what mathematicians call a “real” number. It is Aristotle’s thought, particularly his concept of the infinite that is set forth in the third book of his Physics,
that lies behind Aristoxenus’ vision here. For, as Aristoxenus had learned from
Aristotle, the only way to deal with an infinite structure, such as obtains within
the limits of an octave, is to treat of a finite portion of it. On Aristotle’s doctrine
of the infinite, see White, The Continuous and the Discrete, pp. 133–37.
26 These computations define the loci of the moveable notes, parhypatē and lichanos,
in the malakos, or soft Chromatic genus, as detailed by Aristoxenus Harm.
El. II. 50 (Da Rios, 63. 4–7). Such loci are virtually impossible to ascertain by traditional mathematics. For example, the calculations of Archytas turn out to be:
32:37 x 243:224 x 28:27 = 4:3. Cf. Barker, II, p. 348; Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 101.
27 Winnington-Ingram, “Aristoxenus and the Intervals of Greek Music,” 204.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
217
of a whole-tone above parhypatē, or 12
–4 of a whole-tone, is itself higher
by 12
–1 of a whole-tone than the enharmonic lichanos, which is –14 of a
whole-tone above parhypatē, or 312
–3 of a whole-tone.28 This is in effect
to isolate the quantum, or unit of measure, as –12 of a whole-tone. In
28
The lowest chromatic lichanos occurs in the Soft Chromatic, whose fine tunings of thirds of tones cannot be rendered in musical notation. Computed in
Aristoxenian units of twelve, the intervals in question may be compared in
tetrachord Meson (E–A):
Cf.
Chapter V. Thus, West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 168: “According to him
[sc. Aristoxenus] the two inner notes of the tetrachord can be pitched anywhere
within a continuous band, and it is necessary to lay down boundaries to demarcate one genus from another.” See Fig. 7, a presentation in graph form.
218
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
e stablishing this element as a unit of measure rather than as an interval
in its own right, Aristoxenus says:29 “Such intervals do not exist melodically; for we mean by the words, ‘not exist melodically,’ an interval that
is not assigned a place in its own right in a scale.”
What Aristoxenus intends here is an element so unheard-of theretofore
that he had to invent a word for it, a word newly minted by him for this
specific purpose: to designate a unit-interval by means of which intervals
are counted, a unit-interval used solely for counting intervals. Aristoxenus’
word for this unit-interval is ἀμελῴδητoν. Thus, Aristoxenus was putting
into practice where music is concerned the distinction that Aristotle had
drawn between number and what is numerable. For as Aristotle saw it, a
number is not what is being counted, but is used, rather, to count what is
countable. As he said:30 “As we ascertain the number by using as a unit
the thing that is to be counted, e.g., the number of a group of horses by
using the single horse.” And since Aristoxenus was counting intervals, he
used as a unit a single interval: one twelfth of a whole-tone.31
29
Harm. El. I. 33 (Da Rios, 33. 3–4). The infiniteness and homogeneity of
the melodic domain allowed Aristoxenus to combine units into assemblages
of monads, or numbers of units, in whatever way he thought practical and
musically logical. The mathematical rationale of such a procedure is lucidly
explained by Jacob Kline, Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra,
pp. 51–55.
30 Aristotle Physics 220b19–20 (trans. Ross). And Richard Sorabji, Time, Creation
and the Continuum, p. 89, refers to something about time that is applicable to
Aristoxenus’ mode of setting limits within continuous magnitudes: “Time is
continuous, but number (whole number) is discrete. How, then, can time be a
number? . . . it [sc. time] is infinitely divisible, in the sense that we can divide it
at stages as close together as we please, and its infinite divisibility is precisely a
mark of its continuity.” It is this, namely, the Aristotelian concept of infinite by
division, that underlies Aristoxenus’ method of defining the sum of an infinite
series of pitches as a limit within a continuous magnitude.
31 As Aristoxenus apparently understood it, the whole-tone, like the circle, is a
finite magnitude, and, as such, may be conceived as the sum of its parts: third,
quarter, eighth, sixteenth, and so on. In other words, Aristoxenus intuited the
contemporary notion of a limit as a mathematical sum that actually identifies a
limit with the sum of an infinite series. On this notion as applied to the circle,
see White, The Continuous and the Discrete, pp. 142–44.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
219
To drive home his point about the value of a permanent and unchanging quantum, Aristoxenus refers to the need for a fixed unit of measure
when dealing with rhythm:32
Again, in matters of rhythm we find many similar examples. Without
any change in the characteristic proportion constituting any one genus of
rhythm, the lengths of the feet vary in obedience to the general rate of
movement; and while the magnitudes are constant, the quality of the feet
undergoes a change; and the same magnitude serves as a foot, and as a combination of feet. Plainly, too, unless there was a permanent quantum to deal
with, there could be no distinction as to the methods of dividing it and
arranging its parts. (trans. Macran)
Aristoxenus thus took great pains to demonstrate that his hypothesis of
a twelfth part of a whole-tone is not refuted by the fact that we do not
actually hear such micro-intervals as a twelfth of a whole-tone. Strictly
speaking, such a demonstration is impossible; but it is in the struggle
with this problem that Aristoxenus’ originality is demonstrated with
particular force.
Aristoxenus was not concerned with logic in general, but only with
the logic of melody, that is, with logic in the sense of a formulation of the
32
Harm. El. II. 34 (Da Rios, 43. 16–44. 1). The permanent quantum (lit. “the
magnitude that remains fixed”) is in Aristoxenus’ theory of rhythmics the pro–1 of a whole-tone, is itself nontos chronos, and like the harmonic quantum of 12
composite (asynthetos) or indivisible. In a fragment from Aristoxenus’ work, On
the Primary Chronos, preserved by Porphyry Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics
(Düring, 79. 21–28), for which, see Pearson, Aristoxenus. Elementa Rhythmica,
pp. 34–35, Aristoxenus says: “We must understand that the same reasoning
obtains in the case of harmonic science. For this also has become clear to us:
that as regards all intervals, their magnitudes happen to be infinite; but of
those densely-packed infinite magnitudes one particular magnitude will be
selected when singing in this scale in this nuance (chroa); in the same way,
also, from the infinite magnitudes that come after that one, a particular magnitude will be selected, this one being commensurate with the pyknon that
was assumed; I am referring to the interval that comes after that, for example,
between mesē [A] and lichanos [F].” The magnitude selected by Aristoxenus – 12
–1
of a whole-tone – thus measures the interval in question – F-A – by the whole
number, 24.
220
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
principles employed in the activity of melodic construction. His first act
was to perceive that the sequences of pitch involved in the melodic topos
could be continued ad infinitum. His next move was to discover by ear
that such a continuous image or continuum lacked only the logical connectedness that comes with organized structures of melodic consecution,
structures that form a closed world of relations. These relations were fixed
by the limits of the tetrachord. Aristoxenus thereupon put his hypothesis
to the test by breaking up the epitritic interval of a fourth into thirty
parts, thereby neutralizing the discontinuity between what is numerable
(plēthē) and what is measurable (megethē). Aristoxenus thus arithmetized
what is measurable and in the process mapped onto the melodic topos the
unit-interval 12–1 of a whole-tone. In this way, he facilitated the treatment
of continuous magnitudes as constituted of indivisible elements that are
intuited to be discrete.
But Aristoxenus’ arithmetization of the epitritic interval of a fourth
was what made it impossible for Ptolemy and the other harmonicians
to accommodate his melodic divisions into their system of ratios in all
the genera. For Aristoxenus, through his strictly musical hypothesis,
had in effect ended up treating the square root of two as if it obeyed all
the laws of mathematics that are applicable to rational numbers. This
was to violate the very principle upon which Ptolemy had built up
his harmonic system: the priority of epimoric or superparticular ratios
and their proper treatment – proper, that is, mathematically speaking.
Ptolemy states the case in these words:33
To find the positions and orders of the quantities, we adopt as our primary postulate and rational principle the thesis that all the genera have
the following feature in common: that in the tetrachords too, the successive notes always make those epimoric ratios in relation to one another
which amount to divisions into two or three that are nearly equal. (trans.
Barker)
33
Ptolemy Harm. I. 15 (Düring, 33. 5–9). Like Euclid, Ptolemy subscribes
here to the view that “equality” between notes corresponds to equality or
“near-equality” between the terms of the ratios involved. Thus, as Barker, II,
p. 285, n. 49, points out: “Then one (epimoric) ratio is ‘nearer to equality’
than another where the difference between the terms is a larger simple part
of each.”
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
221
As Ptolemy goes on to explain, the proper division of the epitritic fourth
is dictated not by the assumptions of the musicians, but by the accepted
norms of mathematics:34
With these principles laid down, then, we first divide the epitritic ratio of
the concord of the fourth, as many times as is possible, into two epimoric
ratios: such a thing, once again, occurs only three times, when we adopt in
addition the three epimoric ratios in succession below it, the ratios 5:4, 6:5,
and 7:6. For the ratio 16:15 added to the ratio 5:4 fills out the epitritic, as
does the ratio 10:9 added to the ratio 6:5, and the ratio 8:7 with the ratio
7:6; and after these we cannot find the ratio 4:3 put together from just two
epimorics. (trans. Barker)
Implicit in Ptolemy’s reckonings is his acceptance of the inescapable
and intractable fact of harmonic theory: mathematical equality can never
be achieved on the division of epimoric ratios. Therefore, if intervals
between moveable notes of the tetrachord are to be melodically acceptable to the ear, the divisions of the tetrachord into two or three parts can
only be parisos, or “nearly equal.” They will never be truly equal then,
no matter what sort of mathematical divisions are used, so long as the
principle of epimoric ratios obtains. With mathematical equality out of
reach, Ptolemy nonetheless improved upon the traditional Pythagorean
division of the tetrachord – 9:8, 9:8, 256:243 – by allowing that the
whole-tones be unequal, there now being major whole-tones (9:8) and
minor whole-tones (10:9). The remaining semitone is thus the epimoric
16:15, and the ratio added to that which will yield a perfect fourth is
another epimoric 5:4, a ditone which evidently sounded more melodious
to the ear than the Pythagorean 81:64. Ptolemy’s efforts to divide the
34
Ptolemy Harm. I. 15 (Düring, 33. 28–34. 4). The anatomy of just intonation
has been set forth clearly by Stuart Isacoff, Temperament, pp. 97–100 and graphically represented on a keyboard spanning one octave (pp. 98–100). As he notes
(p. 97): “the idea behind it [sc. just intonation] is at least as old as the second
century a.d., where it appeared in the writings of the astronomer and philosopher Claudius Ptolemy.” Taking note of its shortcomings, Isacoff observes (p.
100): “When all the proportions are calculated, it turns out that the distance
between do and re, for example, is not the same as that between re and mi.” This
is all evident in Ptolemy’s computations.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
222
epitritic fourth into smaller intervals, while maintaining the epimoric
principle is a tour de force; it produced the true or “just” scale whose
intonation is still considered by many musicians to be most harmonious
and especially receptive to modulations. The two disjunctive tetrachords
in Ptolemy’s tuning ascend as follows (8:9 = major whole-tone; 9:10 =
minor whole-tone; 15:16 = semitone):
15:16
8:9
9:10
E-F
F-G
G-A
8:9
15:16
8:9
9:10
A-B
B-C
|
disjunctive whole-tone
C-D
D-E
The kanonia that are preserved by Ptolemy all evince the same regard
for the rules of mathematical rationality as those of Ptolemy himself. To
take one example – the diatonic tetrachord – the computations of the harmonicians and of Ptolemy himself appear on comparison as follows:35
Archytas:
Didymus:
Eratosthenes:
Ptolemy:
9:8,
9:8,
9:8,
10:9,
8:7,
9:8,
10:9,
9:8,
28:27
256:243
16:15
16:15
When to these sets of ratios the reckonings of Aristoxenus are added, the
difference in mathematical idiom becomes striking indeed, for Aristoxenus’
divisions of the same diatonic tetrachord are:
12 + 12 + 6 = 30
As is evident, not only does Aristoxenus express himself here in a different mathematical language, but his thoughts themselves appear to
35
Ptolemy Harm. II. 14 (Düring, 73). Cf. Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 102. Eratosthenes’
calculations turn out to be identical to the archetypal Pythagorean scale as
configured by Plato in Timaeus 36A2–B5 and as echoed by various other sources.
As Barker, II, p. 349, n. 125, remarks: “No doubt the simplicity of its construction recommended it to Eratosthenes.” Yet, the arch-Pythagorean, Nicomachus,
singled out Eratosthenes for unspecified criticism and even compared him with
Thrasyllus (Tiberius’ astrologer), whose twelve part canonic division specifically
did contradict the Pythagorean method (Nicomachus, Manual of Harmonics, 11;
Jan 260. 12–17). On Nicomachus’ criticism, see Levin, Manual, pp. 165–67.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
223
run on different rail lines from those of Ptolemy and the other harmonicians. This is because the harmonicians such as Ptolemy, Archytas, and
the others describe musical intervals in terms of their measurements on
the canon, whereas Aristoxenus describes them in terms of their effect
on the ear. To put it another way, Ptolemy speaks and thinks in the
objective terms of the canon; Aristoxenus thinks and speaks in terms of
the assumptions of musicians.
One of the more obvious results of this is that Aristoxenus’ computations cannot be successfully cast in the mathematical language of
the mathematically objective harmonicians. For the truth is that no
equation involving an unknown (x – especially if the x stands for the
moveable note, lichanos) admits of a solution unless the class of numbers
to which x belongs is stated first. The class of numbers with which
Aristoxenus was dealing do not derive, as do the ratios of the harmonicians, from measurements on the canon; they derive, rather, from his
reduction of the geometrical idea of a magnitude to the arithmetical
idea of a collection of discrete points. The number that represents the
quantity of discrete points in these collections is for Aristoxenus the
number 12, the number which denotes the quantity of a whole-tone.
Thus, 12 calls to mind one thing only: the whole-tone.36 But in the
language of the mathematical theorists, 12 denotes one limit of the
octave in the ratio 12:6 = 2:1. In order to compare Aristoxenus’ divisions of the tetrachord with those of Archytas, Didymus, Eratosthenes,
and his own, Ptolemy resorted to the sort of mathematical heroics of
36
The problem he faced is described by Aristoxenus in these words (Harm. El.
III. 69; Da Rios, 86.19–87.2): “It is clear from what has been said, and from
the situation itself, that if one were to try to ascertain the melodic routes of the
intervals, not with reference to one single nuance of one single genus, but with
reference to all the nuances of all the genera together, he would fall down into
infinity (apeirian).” To deal with this situation, Aristoxenus did not choose the
number 12 arbitrarily. Rather, he found it to function as the upper boundary
for a finite sum of magnitudes and, in this way, it acted as a replacement for
what cannot be known: infinity itself. In other words, Aristoxenus eliminated
from his analysis the infinitely small magnitudes of the shades and their genera and replaced them with limits. His is thus the sort of logistic that is concerned with a permanent quantum that is grasped only in thought and defies
all partition.
224
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
which he alone was capable. He did so by arriving at a compromise of
his own making that would account for the virtually limitless number
of generic divisions that arise in melodic discourse. As he says:37
And since it happens that the numbers comprising the differences common
to the genera run into the tens of thousands, we have used the nearest divisions of whole, entire units right up to the first sixtieths of a single unit, so
that our comparisons never differ by more than one-sixtieth of one part in
the division of the kanonion.
Using the number 60 as his unit of measure, Ptolemy fashioned
tables (kanonia) of numbers indicating those segmental boundaries on
the canon that correspond to each set of ratios into which the octave
is divided. In this way, Ptolemy made every effort to accommodate
Aristoxenus’ divisions to his own measurements, but as his kanonia demonstrate, the language of string-length proportions can never succeed in
representing Aristoxenus’ intervals as equal tonal distances. Barker has
explained the situation in the clearest terms possible:38
Ptolemy represents Aristoxenus’ divisions in terms that require equal differences of number (within any one tetrachord) to represent equal intervals.
It follows that the numbers he assigns to the boundaries of the Aristoxenian
intervals either fail to capture Aristoxenus’ intentions, or cannot be mapped
directly on to the kanonion in the manner required.
The basic problem is, of course, that the octave, the perfect consonance,
like the perfect geometric figure, the circle, does not yield up its mysteries to mathematical analysis.39 In the case of the circle, such analysis
37
38
39
Ptolemy Harm. II. 13 (Düring, 69. 24–29). Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 97, understands synechontas (which Barker translates as “comprising”) to denote “continuous numbers” or “integers,” (synecheis?). This provocative reading suggests that
Ptolemy was treating the tens of thousands of numbers in question here as continuous numbers. If so, Ptolemy can be thought of as approaching Aristoxenus’
intuition that such numbers could be well-ordered and, as such, uniformly continuous. Beyond Solomon’s reading, however, nothing can be taken as certain.
Barker, II, p. 345, n. 112.
Isacoff, Temperament, pp. 16–17, has described the case in these dramatic
terms: “Music’s invisible building-blocks – the magic numbers defining
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
225
led to the transcendent infinity of pi; in that of the octave, it led to the
infinite irrationality of the square root of two.40 And just as Archimedes
invented a method for bringing pi as close to equality as possible, so,
too, did Aristoxenus pioneer a method for approximating equality in his
system of tunings. Like Archimedes, he did this without trigonometry,
without logarithms, and without decimals or any other positional notation. His method for approximating equality in his tuning system is his
alone and, as such, is idiosyncratically “Aristoxenian.” For this reason,
neither Ptolemy, nor anyone else, whether it was Didymus, the musician,
or Eratosthenes, the polymath, could ever arrive at an accurate representation of Aristoxenus’ octave divisions in the language of string-length
proportions. For Aristoxenus’ tunings, which embody the Archimedean
concept of “almost equal to” or “as closely as possible to,” are calculated
on wholly different bases from those of Ptolemy and the other harmonicians. They are calculated on a fourth, an epitritic ratio, divided into
thirty equal parts. In other words, the constant on which Aristoxenus
based his computations is the thirtieth root of the ratio, 4:3.41
sonic beauty – were increasingly like great, ethereal forms that had lost their
bearings. It was as if the stately pyramids had been transplanted to hilly terrain, their bases toppling over helplessly, their points obtruding at odd, ugly
angles.”
40 Irrational numbers, such as Pi, which cannot be roots of an algebraic equation,
are called transcendental; but because the infinitely irrational square of two is
a solution of the algebraic equation x2 – 2=0, it does not qualify as a transcendental number. Cf. Chapter 3, note 2.
41 No mere rough-and-ready method could have led Aristoxenus to this approximation, a device by which he replaced multiplication and division in geometry
by addition and subtraction in arithmetic. His approximation here shows an
intimate understanding of the correspondence between arithmetic and geometric progressions. The quantum at which he arrived is a minimal one in
the sense that it is itself geometrically indivisible, but inseparable from other
such quanta by the intuited melodic topos. Cf. Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, p. 467,
n. 205, who cites this calculation from an unpublished document, “Ancient
Greek Tunings in Cycles per Second,” by Malcolm Litchfield. Aristoxenus was
in effect seeking the smallest transfinite ordinal number, the smallest fixed
number, as the limit to which the variable number, the √2, aspires. To achieve
this limit, Aristoxenus saw the necessity of distinguishing between an interval
such as the semi-tone as an object of sense and, hence, infinitely divisible, and
a unit such as 12
–1 of a whole-tone as an object of thought (dianoia) and, hence,
226
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Eratosthenes apparently took Aristoxenus’ quantum units of 12 seriously enough to attempt their representation by equal distances on the
string of the canon. What is more, he succeeded ingeniously in working
out their ratios for the lower tetrachords of the Perfect System, but in the
Enharmonic and Chromatic genera only. Thus, where Aristoxenus computes the Enharmonic tetrachord as 3 + 3 + 24 (= –14 tone, –14 tone, ditone,
or Major Third), Eratosthenes translates these units into the ratios 40:39 +
39:38 + 19:15 = 4:3.42 And where Aristoxenus computes the Chromatic
tetrachord as 6 + 6 + 18 (= semitone, semitone, tone and a half, or minor
third), Eratosthenes translates these units into the ratios 20:19 + 19:18 +
6:5 = 4:3.43 That is as far as Eratosthenes could carry his representations.
Most important, as Barker points out, Eratosthenes’ divisions are not only
ungainly, but they are also decidedly non-Pythagorean. As such, they are
further evidence of Aristoxenus’ unprecedented mathematical innovations.
Ptolemy drew freely on the work of his predecessors, but apart from
citing the authors of the various kanonia that he preserved, he almost
never mentioned his sources by name. He refers but once to Pythagoras
and only twice to Aristoxenus (apart from his kanonia), whom he fails to
distinguish by his usual epithet, “The Musician.” When Ptolemy does
use this epithet, it is to single out Didymus.44 The work by Didymus
impartible and indivisible. On this critical distinction, see Klein (note 29), pp.
39–41.
42 Barker, II, p. 346, n. 117, observes accordingly: “Certainly he [Eratosthenes]
was trying somehow to represent Aristoxenian intervals in the terminology of
ratio theory, a fact that helps to explain the ungainly and un-Pythagorean character of his highest enharmonic interval, 19:15. Since the arithmetic differences
between terms in Pythagorean ratios were quite different forms of quantity from
the ‘distances’ between Aristoxenian pitches, the attempt is quite incoherent.”
43 André Barbera, “Arithmetic and Geometric Divisions of the Tetrachord,”
The Journal of Music Theory 21 (1977), 302, points out, however, that
Eratosthenes’ lowest chromatic interval (20:19) is equivalent to the bottom
two intervals or pycnon (40:39 x 39:38) of his Enharmonic and that these computations bring him within reach of Aristoxenus’ –14 tone + –14 tone = –12 tone. Cf.
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 100, n. 249.
44 Barker translates Ptolemy’s epithet for Didymus as “the music-theorist”;
but Solomon’s “The Musician” seems more fitting, if only because Didymus’
writings bespeak the knowledge of practicing musicians (as opposed to that
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
227
that won him Ptolemy’s obvious esteem was entitled On the Difference
Between the Aristoxenians and the Pythagoreans.45 In the two fairly long
extracts from this work that are preserved by Porphyry, Didymus makes
a strong argument for the preservation of the phenomena by harmonicians, his authority on this critical point being Aristoxenus himself.
With the text of Aristoxenus’ Harmonic Elements clearly in evidence
before him, Didymus observes:46
For it will be possible for a geometer, who has treated the arc on his
drawing-board as a straight line, to bring his theorem to a successful conclusion without compunction, since he is not concerned with persuading his
eyes about the straightness of the line; the subject-matter of his inquiry is
reason (logos).
Like Aristoxenus, Didymus was a consummate musician, an expert
in vocal and instrumental music, as well as an authority on all aspects
of Pythagorean harmonics. He was also a man of sufficient critical
mind to undertake the refutation of the Pythagorean conclusions
where music was concerned. The line he draws between the two doctrines – the Pythagorean and the Aristoxenian – is in fact so sharp
as to allow for their having little theoretical thought in common.
According to Didymus then, musicians rely solely on their perceptual instincts in their decision making; the Pythagoreans trust solely
in the objectivity of reason. As Didymus argues, therefore, it is one
of musical theorists). When, however, Ptolemy refers in Harm. I. 12 (Düring,
25. 5) to the most skilled of musicians (musikotatos), the inference of the scholiast is that Ptolemy has in mind none other than Aristoxenus himself. Cf.
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 35, n. 178.
45 The details of Didymus’ modifications of the canon, these focusing mainly on
improvements in the placement of its moveable bridge (hypagōgē), are discussed
by Ptolemy Harm. II. 13 (Düring, 67. 20ff.), and most likely came from this
lost work by Didymus.
46 This is preserved by Porphyry Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics (Düring, 28.
12–15). Didymus’ reference is clearly to Aristoxenus Harm. El. II. 33 (Da Rios,
42, 15ff.) where Aristoxenus compares the geometrician, who can dispense
altogether with his faculty of sense-perception, with the harmonician, whose
power of sense-perception is the origin of his knowledge.
228
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
thing to trust in reason, but it is quite another to allow reason to dictate, uncontrolled by perception, the acoustical preferences of melody.
Thus, Didymus:47
Generally speaking then, of those who came to the study of music, some
paid attention solely to perception (aisthēsis), disregarding reason (logos)
entirely. I do not mean that they treated the perceptive judgment as something completely divorced from reason and as something not in conformity
with certain rational factors in musical practices, but that as far as was possible for them, they had no proofs to offer, nor did they refer anything to
reason or show any concern at all for a coherent theory, but were content to
rely exclusively on the perceptual method to which they had become accustomed. Such in particular were the instrumentalists and the voice trainers
and, quite simply, all those who even today are commonly said to engage
in a non-rational activity. On the other hand, however, those who took a
path opposite to these musicians, championed reason as their arbiter and
no longer paid attention to perception in that manner, but heeded it only
as a sufficient point of departure from the objects of perception, so that
reason might make its observations from that source. These latter are the
Pythagoreans. For, adopting certain sparks of light in each circumstance
and constructing theorems that have been put together from them by the
office of reason acting on its own, they no longer pay attention to perception. That being the case, it sometimes befell them that when a logical
consequence was sustained by reason alone and perception contradicted it,
they were not discomfited in the least by such a discrepancy, but put their
trust in reason and repudiated perception as aberrant. And they accept the
facts that are favored by those who frame their thoughts on experience only
when they do not contradict reason.
As Didymus has it then, the practicing musicians, whom he puts
in a class of their own, were satisfied to use what Winnington-Ingram
had charged against Aristoxenus: a “rough-and-ready” or “hit-andmiss” method of attunement that was not governed by any definite and
comprehensible laws. This failure on the part of the instrumentalists
and voice-teachers to discern what is rational in music, let alone to
47
Porphyry, Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics (Düring, 26. 6–25).
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
229
demonstrate it with examples, is in fact what Aristoxenus had found
so deplorable in the work of his predecessors. It is also why Didymus
accused the musicians of his own day of engaging in a nonrational
(alogos) enterprise. Didymus thus realized that it is not enough to have
an innate sense of melodiousness, that is to say, an aesthetic instinct
based on the simple act of hearing. The art of music requires much
more. It required what Aristoxenus had made demonstrably clear: an
intuitive sense of the melodic and a rational understanding of the musical.
Didymus put it this way:48
Music is not only a rational knowledge, but is at the same time perceptual and
rational; hence it is necessary for the truly systematic student not to neglect
either one of the two, even while having what is evident to perception take
the lead, since it is from there that reason must make its beginning.
At the other extreme, Didymus explained, were the Pythagoreans,
who dispensed with the ear’s knowledge altogether once it fired the
engine for the construction of abstract theorems of mathematics.
Between these two extremes is the approach of Aristoxenus who, by
according an equal status to perception and reason could treat music
as inseparable from the special form in which it is presented to the ear.
Didymus thus explains that whereas the Pythagoreans seemed always to
be striving after independence from mere perception in order to arrive
at a system of pure reason, Aristoxenus saw in music so close a union of
reason and perception that a single effect made itself known to the complex faculty of perceptual reason, an effect akin to a feeling for music in
thought itself.
In using Didymus, one of the few authorities on schools of harmonic
theory whom he mentions by name, Ptolemy established a direct link
between himself and Didymus’ own source: Ptolemy’s like-named
musical theorist and philosopher, Ptolemaïs of Cyrene. It is Porphyry,
however, to whom we owe the name of Didymus’ source, as well as
the preservation of four fragments from her book, which Didymus had
48
Porphyry, Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics (Düring, 28. 9–12). Didymus’
argument here is based upon that of his source, Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, whose
identification of reason and perception as equal in power is referred explicitly
by her to Aristoxenus himself. See Chapter 7.
230
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
consulted: The Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music.49 By including in his Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy those citations from
the work of Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, Porphyry honored this otherwise
unknown scholar with knowledge’s most coveted reward: he perpetuated her words. It can only be regretted that Porphyry did not quote
from her work at greater length. Nonetheless, Porphyry accorded her
still another honor, one hardly less significant, by omitting to mention
that the author of the few words he quoted was a woman. His reference
to Ptolemaïs is matter-of-fact; he evinces neither surprise nor incredulity
at finding the work of a woman in his library of authors. Yet he would
have been entitled to register both, if only because female philosophers
and musical theorists were as much a rarity in his day as they have been
at all other times.50 Were it not in fact for the grammatical gender
required by the Greek language in which he wrote, we would not even
notice that the author was a woman. What we do notice is that she was,
to judge from Porphyry’s citations, a woman of high social standing, for
Porphyry’s mode of address – Πτoλεμαΐϛ ἡ Kυρηναία – is more befitting
49
50
Porphyry introduced these fragments in connection with his commentary
on Ptolemy Harm. I.2 (Düring. 5.11–6.13), where Ptolemy discusses the
virtues of the precision instrument, the harmonic canon. In the chapter to
follow, Porphyry’s commentary, together with the fragments of Ptolemaïs,
are translated and examined for the light they shed on the doctrine of
Aristoxenus.
To be sure, learned women were not unknown in antiquity. Indeed, such
women as the brilliant Aspasia, and the celebrated poets, Sappho, Corinna,
Erinna, and Aristodama, stand out for their exceptional accomplishments.
For these women, and others, see Sarah B. Pomeroy, Goddesses, Whores, Wives,
and Slaves, pp. 89ff. Moreover, a list of illustrious women associated with
Pythagorean studies was compiled by Iamblichus De Vita Pyth. 267 (Deubner,
146.17–147.6), fragments of whose writings have been collected by Holger
Thesleff, The Pythagorean Texts of the Hellenistic Period. Among these writings, Thesleff has included the fragments of Ptolemaïs with the observation
(p. 229): “Of the other accounts of Pythagorean matters which may, or may
not, be dated in the Hellenistic age, only the fragments of Ptolemaïs have
been printed here, because they have so far received little attention.” Since the
writing of these words, Ptolemaïs has been accorded considerable attention
by Barker, II, pp. 239–42. To these names of female scholars must be added
that of the celebrated mathematician and philosopher, Hypatia, for whom,
see Maria Dzielska, Hypatia of Alexandria.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
231
a princess of the Egyptian royal house than merely a member of the
aristocracy.51 Equally noticeable is what her writings demonstrate: the
mind of a scholar who was learned in Greek philosophy as well as in
Aristoxenian theory and Pythagorean harmonics. She is unique in the
annals of ancient intellectual history for three reasons: hers was a pursuit that was otherwise unexampled among women of antiquity; her
name is a dynastic one that cannot have been given to anyone before
the time of Ptolemy I Soter (c. 367/8–283 b.c.); though she wrote on
Pythagorean theory, she favored the approach of Aristoxenus.
All that we know of Ptolemaïs has been summed up by Andrew
Barker in these words:52
About Ptolemaïs of Cyrene . . . we have no information at all outside
Porphyry’s work, and he says nothing about her, not even remarking on
the fact that she is a woman. (The fact is striking: few female scholars, and
no other female musicologists, are known to us from classical antiquity.)
Even her date is a matter of conjecture, and might conceivably lie anywhere
between the third century b.c. and the first century a.d.
If anything, Barker’s words invite one to attempt an identification
of Ptolemaïs or, if not that, then a reasonable time in which she may
be thought to have lived and worked. One might begin by saying
of Ptolemaïs that, like the eponymous goddess of her Cyrenian land,
Hypseus’ fair-armed daughter, she “loved neither the pacings back and
forth before the loom, nor the pleasures of dining with her hearthbound companions.” Rather, she would wrestle alone with the abstractions of aesthetic theory even as Cyrene, the huntress-maiden, once
51
52
Unlike Ptolemaïs, the other writers cited by Porphyry (and they are numerous) are identified according to their specialty, as, for example, Adrastus the
Peripatetic, Aelian the Platonist, or Euclid the teacher of the Elements; other
celebrated authorities are identified by Porphyry according to their national
origin, these being Dionysius of Halicarnassus and Archytas the Tarentine.
Porphyry’s conferral of the national appellation – Cyrenian – on the otherwise unknown Ptolemaïs suggests that she, too, is a celebrated personage
whom Porphyry expects his readers to know or recognize as such. On the
types of address indicating people of high estate or royal standing, see Basil L.
Gildersleeve, Syntax of Classical Greek, I, p. 29, para. 58.
Barker, II, p. 230.
232
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
did with a lion. We might well ask then, as Apollo did of Cheiron:
“What mortal begot her? From what manner of race was she wrenched
away to live in the hollows of Cyrene’s overshadowing mountains?”53
History has thus far offered no answer; but it does provide a misē en scène
that could confer on Ptolemaïs of Cyrene an appropriately royal antecedent in the person of the like-named mother of Demetrius the Fair,
King of Cyrene and grandson of Ptolemy I Soter: Ptolemaïs, Princess
of Egypt.54
The name Ptolemaïs is truly operatic: like the more celebrated
name, Thaïs, it rings with enough romance and political intrigue
to inspire the sensibilities of any composer of operas.55 It is also
a very rare name, the princesses of the royal house having been
more commonly called Berenice, Arsinoë, and Cleopatra. And it
specifies legitimacy, for the Ptolemies never gave dynastic names
like Ptolemaïs to illegitimate children.56 Ptolemaïs, the daughter
of Ptolemy I Soter and Eurydice of Macedonia, was, of course, no
match for the Cleopatras, the Arsinoës, and the Berenices, those
princesses and queens who rivalled their consorts and siblings in
political sagacity or, as the case may be, in political crimes.57 Hers
53
54
55
56
57
See Pindar Pythian IX. 17ff.
The Princess Ptolemaïs was born perhaps about 318 b.c. into the house of
Ptolemy that included an older brother, Ptolemy, later celebrated for his viciousness as Keraunos (the “Thunderbolt”), and a sister, Lysandra. Their mother was
Eurydice, the daughter of Antipater, Regent of Macedonia, her marriage to
Ptolemy I in 322 b.c. or thereabouts having served the mutual interests of
Macedonia and Egypt against the ambitions of Perdiccas, a senior officer under
Alexander. On the offspring of this political marriage, see Edwyn R. Bevan,
The House of Ptolemy, pp. 52–54.
Massenet’s Meditation from Act II of his opera is in and of the name,
Thaïs, italicizing it, as it were, upon the mind. On the famous hetaira of
Ptolemy I, see, for example, Pomeroy, Women in Hellenistic Egypt, pp. 13f ;
pp. 53–55.
See Grace H. Macurdy, Hellenistic Queens, p. 102.
The women of the three chief Hellenistic dynasties – Macedonian, Seleucid
Syrian, and Ptolemaic Egypt – are notable for their strength of character and
political intelligence. As is observed by W. W. Tarn, Hellenistic Civilization,
p. 98: “If Macedonia produced perhaps the most competent group of men the
world had yet seen, the women were in all respects the men’s counterparts;
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
233
is but a shadowy figure on the historical stage, and when she does
appear, ever so briefly, it is more as a victim than as an influence on
the circumstances of her life. Yet something of her life can be recovered that allows for her having been touched by developments in
Cyrene through her marriage to the incredibly handsome war-lord
and adventurer, Demetrius Poliorketes, the “Besieger of Cities.”58 It
was, however, his son by Ptolemaïs who was to win an epithet for
his incomparable looks. He came to be known as Demetrius the Fair
and was, as the ruling monarch of Cyrene (mid-third century b.c.),
the central figure in a drama of passion and political intrigue that
ended in his assassination through the machinations of the Cyrenian
Princess Berenice. This contact between Ptolemaïs of Egypt, the
mother of Demetrius the Fair, and the court of Cyrene is enough
to evoke the name that is so imposing in the text of Porphyry:
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene.
In addition to being even more handsome than his father, Demetrius
Poliorketes, Demetrius the Fair seems to have been a man of developed intellect. For he is found as a youth studying in Athens with
no less than Arcesilaos, the head of Plato’s Academy, the scholar to
whom Eratosthenes himself was drawn. Demetrius would probably
have continued in the near-total obscurity that surrounds the first
thirty-odd years of his life had not his half-brother, Antigonos II
Gonatas, selected him as a political pawn against the growing power
of Ptolemy II Philadelphus of Egypt. Demetrius was to be king of
58
they played a large part in affairs, received envoys and obtained concessions for
them from their husbands, built temples, founded cities, engaged mercenaries,
commanded armies, held fortresses, and acted on occasion as regents or even
co-rulers.”
Demetrius was the son of Antigonous, the “One-eyed,” one of the three continually warring successors of Alexander (the others being Seleuceus and
Ptolemy). From 312 b.c. on (after suffering a major setback at the battle of
Gaza), Demetrius went on to establish his credentials among his father’s allies
and chieftains as Poliorcetes. Plutarch pairs Demetrius with Antony, since, as
he says (Dem. I. 7): “Both were similarly concupiscent, fond of drink, warlike,
liberal spenders, extravagant and vainglorious.” Like Antony, Demetrius was
also handsome beyond the capacity of painters to achieve his likeness (Plutarch
Dem. II. 2).
234
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Cyrene and the instrument of Gonatas’ will.59 With the throne would
come the hand of the Princess of Cyrene, Berenice, daughter of Magas,
King of Cyrene, and of his now-widowed queen, the Seleucid Apama.60
This union made for a three-way alliance of power that would contain the world in a triangle of steel: Berenice representing Egypt as
grand-daughter of Ptolemy I; Demetrius representing Macedonia as
half-brother of Gonatus; Apama inclining toward Syria as the daughter
of the formidable Antiochos I.61
The plan might have worked out as intended by Gonatas, had
Demetrius not fallen in love with his mother-in-law to be, Apama. This
could not but incur the wrath – in truth, a Medea-like vengeance – on
the part of Demetrius’ intended bride, Berenice. For what apparently
began with the consciousness of a common point of view between two
people of the same age (Apama being perhaps only a few years older
than Demetrius), developed into the sort of commitment that asks neither forgiveness nor seeks condonation. The third party to the affair,
Berenice, the bride-to-be of Demetrius, although still quite young,
must have loved the worst. Indeed, nothing could have been worse than
the punishment which Berenice had premeditated for Demetrius and
Apama: he was to die and she was to live on with the image of his death
forever before her. It is a story worthy of grand opera: the libretto has
been provided by Justin, according to whom Berenice was not as yet wed
to Demetrius. And she was so outraged at Demetrius’ preference for her
59
On the history of Demetrius the Fair, see W. W. Tarn, Antigonos Gonatas, p. 290,
note 36; 293; 334. Cf. H .J. W. Tillyard and A. J. B. Wace, “The History of
Demetrius the Fair,” Annual of the British School at Athens, pp. 113–19.
60 On these developments in Cyrene and the role of Demetrius the Fair, see Bevan,
The House of Ptolemy, pp. 73–75.
61 The lives that interact within this political coalition have produced some of the
most dizzyingly complex genealogies in the Hellenistic era. Thus, for example,
Apama, the widow of Magas of Cyrene (he being the son of Berenice, the second wife of Ptolemy I) was named after her grandmother, Apama, the wife of
Seleucis I. Her mother, the wife of Antiochos I, was Stratonice, the daughter
of Demetrius, “the Besieger,” and Phila, the sister of the first wife of Ptolemy I,
Eurydice. This means that Ptolemaïs, Eurydice’s daughter, whom Demetrius
married around 286 b.c., was his own niece. See Macurdy, Hellenistic Queens,
p. 103. Cf. Fig. 8.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
235
mother over herself that she sought help from the pro-Egyptian party
who had favored her marriage to Ptolemy III Euergetes in the first place.
As Justin tells it:62
She [sc. Berenice] devised a treacherous entrapment of Demetrius. After he
had retired to the bed of his socrus [mother-in-law to be], assassins were despatched there to attack him. But when Apama heard the voice of her own
daughter, who was standing at the door to the bed-chamber, give orders to
the assassins to spare her mother, Apama threw her own body over that of
the man she loved and managed to shield him for a brief while. By having
Demetrius killed, Berenice, without suffering her own piety to be sullied,
not only exacted vengeance against her mother for her sin, but also followed
her father’s wishes in her selection of a husband.
The inconsistencies in Justin’s account – both internal and external –
are many. For one thing, he refers to Berenice as a virgo at the time of
Demetrius’ assassination, this implying that the marriage between the
two had not yet taken place. If so, there would be no basis for Justin to
call Apama socrus, when she was not yet a mother-in-law, but still only
a mother-in-law-to-be. In the second place, Demetrius was reported
to have ruled over Cyrene for ten years, a position he could not have
sustained without a legal and binding marriage. If Apama had been
his queen, Demetrius would have been secure on his throne, as he
seems in fact to have been.63 And, as king, he would have become a
62
63
When it comes to trustworthiness, Justin (c. 3rd century a.d.), the primary
source for these proceedings, is far from the equal of a Plutarch. According to
Tarn, Hellenistic Civilization, p. 292, Justin is a prime example of those writers
who worsened the state of historical writing by boiling down from the greater
writers and repeating from one another. Justin seems also to have hated the
people (particularly the women) about whom he was writing. The worse the
story, the better he liked the telling of it. Cf. Macurdy, Hellenistic Queens, p. 2.
In the present case, it is Justin’s own bias that lends credibility to the story of
Berenice, Demetrius the Fair, and Apama.
Demetrius’ position as king of Cyrene is established by an inscription from
Mantinea. This is discussed by H.J.W. Tillyard, Athens 11 (1904–05), 111–12.
To this evidence may be added that of the great chronographer, Eusebius Chron.
236
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
s ubstantial obstacle to the rising ambitions of the princess, Berenice – a
king who had to be removed from power. Unfortunately, the accounts
of Demetrius’ tragic history and its consequences are so confused and
muddled in the details that a case can be made for almost any fairly reasonable conjecture. Only one thing stands out as certain from the welter
of deranged evidence: Demetrius was betrothed to Berenice, but it was
Apama whom he truly loved.
To continue a story based upon appearances, Demetrius may be seen
ascending the throne of Cyrene in the vicinity of 259/58 b.c. His marriage to Apama (if there was one) would have been in the same year. And
the child born of this marriage would have entered the stage in 257 b.c.
at the earliest. But the story, as we know it to have been played out,
has Berenice succeeding in her plan by marrying Ptolemy III Euergetes
and becoming Berenice II, Queen of Egypt. Ironically, by her deed of
murder, she became celebrated as a heroine, the subject of a famous
poem by Callimachus, Berenikes Plokamos, which has come down in a
Latin version by Catullus: Coma Berenices.64 Thus the death of Demetrius
left Berenice free to marry her cousin, Ptolemy III, as her father Magas
had desired and, after what must have been an uncomfortable delay in
the marriage ceremony, to become Ptolemy’s queen.65 Gonatas in turn
lost his diplomatic hold on the Cyrenaica which, through Berenice’s
marriage, passed once again into Egypt’s territory. And the once-proud
Apama, condemned by the cruel mercy of Berenice to live on bereft and
64
65
I. 237, who says that Demetrius not only consolidated his power over all of
Libya and Cyrene, but also ruled as monarch for ten years.
Catullus 66. 23–28 expresses the deepest sympathy for Berenice: Quam penitus maestas exedit cura medullas!/ Ut tibi tunc toto pectore sollicitae/ Sensibus
eruptis mens excidit! At te ego certe/ Cognoram a parva virgine magnaniman./
Anne bonum onlita es facinus, quo regium adepta es/ Conjugium, quod non
fortior ausit alis? “How deeply the sorrow wore away at the grief in the very
marrow of your being! As then in your anguish, your mind wrenched apart,
your feelings ripped away from all your heart! Yet I have known you to be
heroic from the time when you were a little girl. Have you forgotten the noble
deed by which you won a king for a husband? A braver deed no other would
dare.”
The marriage of Berenice to Ptolemy III Euergetes (her first cousin) did not
take place until 245; thus the marriage was delayed some thirteen or fourteen
years. Cf. Bevan, The House of Ptolemy, p. 74.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
237
abased, was never to be heard from again. Yet the silence into which
the vagaries of historiography have cast the persons of Demetrius and
Apama makes all the more significant the single and uncontested fact
of a Ptolemaïs of Cyrene.
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene ought to have been the legitimate daughter of
Demetrius the Fair and Apama of Syria. That is to say, in order to have
become the scholar she indeed was, she should have been all that her name
aspires to and, on that account alone, qualified by birth for the training to
which her writings bear ample testimony. Had she in fact been a half-sister
to Berenice, or even someone of comparable estate, her admittance to the
royal court of Alexandria would have been guaranteed. Once there – her
life spared, let us suppose, by the same clemency that Berenice granted
to Apama – she would have been brought up in company with the children of the king’s household, being numbered, appropriately, among the
paides basilikoi, those well-connected boys and girls who were privileged
to be reared with the princes and princesses of the court.66 Indeed, if anything was to make her intellectual deliverance complete, it would have
been present there. For there the palace of Ptolemy III gave easy access to
the most brilliant center of learning outside of Athens – the celebrated
Museum and great Library of Alexandria.67
The cultivated woman of Hellenistic Alexandria is exemplified
in the writings of Ptolemaïs of Cyrene.68 She is also the only woman
known thus far to have dealt with harmonic theory.69 The all-too-few
66
67
68
69
On the education of the nobility, see Bevan, The House of Ptolemy, p. 123. On
the education of upper-class women, see Pomeroy, Women in Hellenistic Egypt,
pp. 59ff.
This remarkable institution was in reality a complete university, not unlike
the schools of philosophy at Athens. It came into being under Ptolemy I Soter
(perhaps at the suggestion of Demetrius of Phalerum, who was familiar with
Aristotle’s own great library at Athens), and it attracted the most brilliant
minds of the Hellenistic era. See Bevan, The House of Ptolemy, pp. 124–27. For
a most recent study of the library and its history, see Lionel Casson, Libraries in
the Ancient World, pp. 31ff.
On the cultivated women of Egyptian society, see Pomeroy, Women in Hellenistic
Egypt, pp. 41ff.
Ptolemaïs’ name has been mentioned by numerous scholars, but thus far, her
writings have occasioned little commentary. To be sure, Lukas Richter, Zur
Wissenschaftslehre von der Musik bei Platon und Aristoteles, pp. 178ff, and Ingmar
238
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
lines of her work that survive, thanks to Porphyry, offer more than faint
glimpses of a sober intelligence in easy command of an intricate and a
divisive field. But however complex and technical the subject-matter,
her style remains simple, direct, and intelligible. Her words bristle
with authority, and she speaks with a mind of her own. She seems in
fact to have inherited not a little of the indomitable spirit that provoked
the ambitious Macedonian princesses of Egypt to such different purposes.70 She could therefore attack Pythagorean doctrine at its very core
on grounds that would have satisfied Aristotle himself. However few
then are the words that Porphyry chose to transmit from her writings,
they do tell us something of what she knew and how she was disposed
to think. This much can be ascertained: she was sufficiently trained in
music to understand the assumptions of musicians; her knowledge of
canonic theory, for which she had to have had mathematics, was such
that Porphyry could consult her as an authority; she was thoroughly
grounded in the principles upon which the Pythagoreans based their
doctrine of harmonics; her understanding of Aristoxenus’ theory of
music exceeded that of many specialists whose writings have survived
more or less intact; she had a firm grasp of the theoretical priorities
that divided the Pythagoreans and the Aristoxenians; she knew how the
principle of “saving the phenomena,” which underlies all of Greek natural research, applied to harmonic theory. Most important, she seems to
70
Düring, Ptolemaios und Porphyrios Über Die Musik, pp. 143–45, have drawn some
important insights from her position with respect to the Pythagoreans. See also
Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 514–17, who summarizes the content of her work.
Apart from these contributions, the most significant work on Ptolemaïs is that
of Barker, II, pp. 239–44, who has translated her writings into English for the
first time and assessed their meaning.
In sum, if Demetrius the Fair, King of Cyrene and grandson of the resplendent Ptolemy I Soter, had had a daughter by Apama, herself the daughter
of the Seleucid Antiochos I Soter and Stratonice (daughter of Demetrius I
and Phila), such a daughter would conceivably have been called Ptolemaïs of
Cyrene. On the conventions of naming children of the royal house, see W.W.
Tarn, “Queen Ptolemais and Apama,” CQ 23 (1929), pp. 138–41. Because
the weight of evidence favors 259/58 b.c. for the accession of Demetrius the
Fair to the throne of Cyrene, the princess, Ptolemaïs, would have been born
at the earliest in 258/57. Pomeroy, Women in Hellenistic Egypt, p. 61, thus has
Ptolemaïs coming from Cyrene to Alexandria some time around 250 b.c.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum and Ptolemaïs of Cyrene
239
have had access to more of the writings of Aristoxenus than is available
to us today, for she adds a fragment of his thought that has not as yet
found its way into his extant writings.71
If the name Ptolemaïs of Cyrene urges thoughts of past intrigues and
endeavors too mad for understanding, her words rouse a far different
world: one that persists undisturbed by the dreary intercourse of political foes or society’s self-infatuated degradations. Thus, while Berenice
of Cyrene, instrument of her own mother’s ruination, was living only to
be poisoned by her own son, Ptolemy IV Philopater (c. 244–205 b.c),
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene was delving into things that will never end. And
while it was Philopater, the murderous voluptuary and vicious dilettante,
who had as his private tutor the towering scholar, Eratosthenes of Cyrene
(c. 275–194 b.c), it took a Ptolemaïs of Cyrene (c. 257–c. 211?) to do
justice to the teachings of such a master. An acknowledged expert in the
principles of harmonics, Eratosthenes could conceivably have taught his
countrywoman, Ptolemaïs, to penetrate as deeply as she in fact does into
the intricacies of harmonic theory. More than anything else, however, it is
what she has to say on the subject that makes such a possibility thinkable.
Quite apart from Eratosthenes, who may indeed have been her mentor, it
was Ptolemaïs herself who placed the knowledge she had absorbed into the
service of reason. In this regard, she made herself exceptional. For not only
did she prove Aristotle wrong in his estimation of women’s deliberative and
rational faculties, she did so on his own grounds: she reasoned critically,
dialectically and, what is more, as a true Aristotelian.72 As such, she pitted
herself against Pythagorean and Platonic mathematical conceptions the
better to champion Aristoxenus’ Peripatetic philosophy of music.
In his Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy, Porphyry makes four citations from The Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music by Ptolemaïs
71
72
See Chapter 7, note 45.
Interestingly enough, there were no female peripatetic scholars at all. For
Aristotle made it quite clear in the Politics 126a25ff. that women lacked the
necessary rational element for deliberative thinking. Aristotle did concede
that women formed half of the human race, but he could not help quoting
Sophocles Ajax 293 to the effect that “for a woman, silence is an ornament.”
On Aristotle’s position with respect to women, see Pomeroy, “TECHNIKAI
KAI MOUSIKAI: The Education of Women in the Fourth Century and in the
Hellenistic Period,” American Journal of Ancient History 2 (1977), 58.
240
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of Cyrene. Taken as a whole, these passages are of sufficient length and
continuity to communicate something of the writer’s intellectual energy
and range of knowledge. Porphyry characterizes the work as an Isagōgē,
or Introduction, and takes note also of the question-and-answer method in
one of the passages. He informs us further that the work was a source
for Didymus. For Didymus, he says, not only followed Ptolemaïs in several places of his own work; he also elaborated on various of her statements. Inasmuch as Didymus was himself a source for Ptolemy, Ptolemaïs
must have antedated them both. Porphyry quite possibly had the work of
Ptolemaïs before him in its entirety. For apart from the context for which
he extracted her words, this being his commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics
I. 2, he had occasion to refer once again to her as an authority on a different
subject: the classification of consonances. Here, he singles out Ptolemaïs as
a representative example of what he says was an ancient tradition, one that
Ptolemy had altered by basing his classification of consonances on kinds
of sounds and not, as in Aristoxenus, on vocal movements.73 The inference
is that Ptolemaïs not only antedated Ptolemy, but did so to a considerable
degree. On the other hand, however, Ptolemaïs’ reference to the canon,
which was invented around 300 b.c., and to the theory based upon it as one
of long-standing institution with the Pythagoreans, suggests that even if
she lived well before Ptolemy, she also lived some time after 300 b.c. That
being the case, she might well have studied with Eratosthenes, who was
an acknowledged expert in the principles of canonic theory.74 For what she
has to say on the subject suggests that her training in the field was more
than adequate to her purpose. Whoever her mentor was and whatever the
circumstances that helped her to extend her knowledge, it was Ptolemaïs
herself who used this knowledge well to explain Aristoxenian theory.75 She
began by introducing a new term into the field, one by which the field has
since been designated: Kanonikē.
73
74
75
Porphyry Commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy (Düring, 114. 5–7) includes
Ptolemäis here with “other ancients” who classified consonances as she did.
As West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 239, has observed: “It would be interesting to
know the relationship between Eratosthenes and Ptolemäis, a female musicologist of uncertain date who came from Cyrene.”
Cf. Barker, II, p. 239, n. 134.
7 Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
The heart is the capital of the mind,
The Mind is a single State.
The heart and the Mind together make
A Single continent.
Emily Dickinson
In the fourteenth century, a Viennese scribe, the copyist of
Porphyry’s Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics, known to us only as T, referred
to Ptolemaïs’ definition of the canon as that of Ptolemaïs the Cyrenian
Musician (ὃρος κανόνος παρὰ πτολεμαΐδος τῇς κυρηναίας μουσικῇς).1 The
knowledge and mastery of the material displayed throughout by T in his
various interpretive corrections and refinements of Porphyry’s text lend
an uncommon authority to his characterization of Ptolemaïs as mousikē.2
To be sure, T may have been using mousikē here in the general sense of
“cultivated,” thus to designate a person educated “under the auspices
of the Muses.”3 And this reading – “the Cyrenian Savante” or “woman
1
2
3
Düring, Porphyry Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics, p. 22, criticus apparatus,
line 25.
In his introduction to Porphyry’s text, p. xv, Düring identifies T as the sixtyninth of the seventy manuscripts that have come down to us, its provenance
being Vindobenensis, and its production being that of a learned man (p. xix).
A “musical” man was not understood in all cases to be a musician, but, as often
as not, an especially cultivated and educated member of society – one trained
to be a philosopher and a leader of the people. For, as Plato has it, philosophical
knowledge presupposes a musical education. A “musical” man is, according
to Plato Rep. 401D8-E, one who has attained the grace of body and mind that
comes from a properly “musical,” or well-attuned, upbringing.
241
242
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
of letters” – would comport with one other rare mention of Ptolemaïs,
that by Gilles Ménage, in whose Historia Mulierum Philosopharum of
1690 Ptolemaïs of Cyrene is acknowledged as a scholar and philosopher.4
Observing Ptolemaïs at work, however, and watching the results of her
constant venture into the “Battle of the Criteria”5 – Aisthēsis and Logos–
lead to a certain conclusion: she was mousikē, a musician in the narrower
sense of the word. When, therefore, T called Ptolemaïs mousikē, he must
have had the same thing in mind as Porphyry did when he called Didymus
mousikos, namely, a musician.6 Indeed, T was evidently too clear-sighted
not to perceive that in the debate between the Aristoxenians and the
Pythagoreans, Ptolemaïs spoke as a musician.
The debate between the Aristoxenians and the Pythagoreans concerned the criteria – aisthēsis and logos – and their respective roles in
the acquisition of musical knowledge and the formulation of a musical
theory. This debate had been set into motion long before by Aristoxenus
when he broke with the Pythagoreans over the position that mathematics
was to occupy in the science of harmonics. Both he and the Pythagoreans
were agreed in starting from the same point: the phenomena perceived
by the ear (aisthēsis), these representing what was to be interpreted by
4
5
6
Of all the scholars who studied her words, only Ménage expressed doubt as to
Ptolemaïs’ being an orthodox Pythagorean. For, as he said, however extensive
her knowledge of Pythagorean mathematical theory, he had to admit that she
did not adhere to Pythagorean doctrine in all respects: Quare cum Ptolemaïda
Cyrenaeam Sectae Pythagoricae adscripsimus, non omnibus Pythagoricam fuisse dicere
voluimus (Historia Mulierum Philosopharum, p. 123). This work was translated
into English by Beatrice H. Zedler, The History of Women Philosophers. Ménage’s
reference to Ptolemaïs appears on page 62 of this translation. Zedler places
Ptolemaïs in the second–third century a.d. and suggests that her high level of
learning would have made her eligible to participate in the erudite circle surrounding Empress Julia Domna.
The metaphor, “Der Kritierienstreit,” was introduced by Lukas Richter, Zur
Wissenschaftslehre von der Musik bei Platon und Aristoteles, p. 184.
This is not to suggest that a woman of Ptolemaïs’ high estate would ever have performed in public. Hers was doubtless a private, but no less accomplished, artistry.
Her type of musical activity is portrayed on a grave stēlē from Alexandria, c. 250
b.c., showing a woman being handed her lyre by her maid. See Pomeroy, Women
in Hellenistic Egypt, Plate 13, p. 167. See also Pomeroy, “Technikai kai Mousikai;
The Education of Women in the Ancient World,” AJAH 2 (1977), 51–68.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
243
reason (logos), and how mathematics was to assist in this interpretive
process. Aristoxenus took issue with the mathematical theorists, but
at the same time, he never countenanced any approach to music that
was less sound in its hypotheses or less accurate in its computations
than that of mathematical science. As he argued, the “miraculous order”
belonging to the nature of music merited a science of its own – one that
could classify the genera and species of melody, define their respective
functions, and formulate the laws determining their manifold connections.7 To prosecute this goal, Aristoxenus introduced a new factor into
the proceedings, one which he maintained could only be cognized deep
in the soul. The organ of this cognition was understood by him to be
synesis, or musical intuition.8
Musical intuition in Aristoxenus’ theory implies a new conception of
knowledge as something different from sense-perception. To him, it was
a knowledge that penetrated beyond the manifold properties of melody
into the unity of true musical expression. He thus believed that it was
in the unity he intuited, and its unchanging attributes, that music’s
true nature could be grasped. The Pythagoreans were convinced, however, that music’s true nature lay in the discontinuity of musical space,
7
That Aristoxenus succeeded in differentiating between the genera and species
of melody may be referred to Aristotle’s teachings. For just as there seems to
be no satisfactory evidence that genus and species were used in a technical
sense before Aristotle, so, too, there is no evidence to suggest that they were
applied in a technical sense before Aristoxenus. To be sure, eidē (species) and
genos (genus) were sometimes used loosely to denote “style,” as by Ps. Plutarch
De. Mus. 114OE5 (the “style” or eidos of decadence) and 1142C4–5, where Telesias
is said to have tried, but failed, to compose in the Pindaric or Philoxenian “style
(genos). In Aristoxenian theory, however, these classifications were abstracted from
sense-perception and were applied, as did Aristotle in his biology, absolutely.
On the evolution of genus and species in the technical sense, see D. M. Balme,
“GENOS and EIDOS in Aristotle’s Biology,” CQ, n.s. XII (1962), 81–92.
8 Levin, “Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory,” TAPA 103 (1972), 211ff. thus construes synesis as an inherent mental capacity comprising one’s implicit musical
understanding. Commenting on this line of argumentation, Solomon, Ptolemy,
p. 55, n. 269 generously observes: “[Levin] restores Aristoxenus to a position
of some respect as a musical theorist after the lambasting he has taken from
the Pythagoreans, Ptolemaians, and their modern annotators and advocates.”
Cf. also A. Neubecker, Altgriechische Musik, p. 24, n. 79.
244
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
that discontinuity wherein the gaps between rational numbers could
be accurately defined on the canon, the instrument of measure. Thus,
whereas the Pythagoreans kept their focus on the discontinuity between
the rational numbers defined on the canon, Aristoxenus shifted his focus
to the perceived continuity of melody as it is experienced by the ear and
is expressed by the combination of rational and irrational numbers in
infinite quantities between any two integers. In other words, Aristoxenus
found evidence of melodic continuity in a true mathematical continuum.9
Aristoxenus appears consistently to have underemphasized the
quantitative aspects of music’s nature. Yet, in the final analysis, it was
in the properties of a mathematical continuum that he found the true
synthesis of melodic construction.10 As he explained, this synthesis was
framed on sets of consonantal correspondences. His line of thought can
be followed in this statement:11
Melody that is in attunement must not only be composed of intervals and notes,
but must also be constituted of a certain kind of synthesis, indeed, a synthesis of
no haphazard sort; for it is obvious that being composed of intervals and notes
is a common property [of melody] since it belongs also to melody that is out of
9
10
11
This was a great achievement for which Aristoxenus has never received adequate
credit. He arrived at it by positing a unit for measuring musical intervals, one
that was not an absolute unit in the Platonic sense, but something of the same
kind that was being counted – a melodic distance. Aristoxenus’ selection of this
unit of measure was like that of Aristotle for measuring time: by numbering
“nows.” For a “now” is a part of time, or as Aristotle says in Physics 220b22–24:
“We measure motion by time and we measure time by motion.” The number
Aristotle selected for measuring time was of the same kind as what was being
measured: the “nows” that were being counted. Cf. Sorabji, Time, Creation and
the Continuum, pp. 88–89.
The property of the mathematical continuum that answered Aristoxenus’ purpose
inheres in its formation of a system of elements wherein one can pass from any
one of them to any other by a series of consecutive elements such that each
cannot be distinguished from its predecessor. This linear series is to the musician what the isolated point is to the mathematician. But for such a series to
be uniform, there is required the addition of irrational numbers to the rational
numbers that define the consonances. This is what allows every note in the
series to be treated equivalently and thus to assume the function assigned to it
by the laws of melodic consecution.
Harm. El. I. 18–19 (Da Rios, 23. 16–24.11).
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
245
attunement. This being so, we must take it that the most important element,
and, in fact, the most critical factor by far on which the right constitution of
melody turns, is that which has to do with its overall synthesis and the particular
form this synthesis takes. Indeed, it is all but obvious that musical melody differs
from the melody occurring in speech by executing intervals in the motion of the
voice; while musical melody differs also from unattuned and faulty melody by
the difference in its synthesis of indivisible intervals. What this difference is will
be demonstrated in our analysis to follow. For the present, let it be said in general
that while attunement admits of many different possibilities in its synthesis of
intervals, there is nevertheless something of such sort which we shall assert to be
one and the same in every attunement, something that embodies so important a
function that when it is taken away, the attunement disappears also.
The orderly arrangement of intervals – their proper synthesis – is,
according to Aristoxenus, characteristic of all good melodies. This
synthesis, he explains, is a function of tetrachordal continuity. At the
same time, it is contingent on the sort of underlying continuum framed
by Aristoxenus. For there can be no synthesis of any sort, whether it
be well- or ill-attuned, without there being a well-defined melodic
continuum in place to accommodate it. To put it another way, there can
be many types of continuity in melody, but there is only one melodic
continuum. For example, in Harm. El. III. 63, Aristoxenus describes a
type of continuity from which there results a unity in virtue of the
contact (synaphē) between certain notes.12 The case he describes here is
that in which the lower of the notes containing the ditone is itself the
highest note of a pyknon, and the higher of the notes containing the
ditone is the lowest note of the pyknon. The unity resulting from this
contact can be mapped on the Meson tetrachord (E–A) as follows:
12
Harm. El. III. 63 (Da Rios, 79. 14–80.2).
246
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Figure 8. The Family of Ptolemaïs of Cyrene (?)
As Aristoxenus intuited, a synthesis of this sort would be impossible,
if the distance between E and A (a fourth) were not conceptually divisible into thirty equal parts.
Aristoxenus’ conceptual division of the tetrachord into thirty equal
parts was as close as he could come in approximating the ear’s own knowl
edge: that there is perceptible in this synthesis (as given above) a divided
(synthetos) semitone between E and F, and an undivided (asynthetos) ditone
between F and A.13 And F is recognized to be the point of union. To Ptolemy
and the mathematical theorists, Aristoxenus appeared to base his synthesis
of intervals on the assumption of the whole-tone as the difference between
the fourth and the fifth and on the acceptance of the octave as compounded
of six equal whole-tones. And this, they argued, ran counter to the axioms of mathematics. Their proof of this lay in the size of the semitone,
13
Synthetos and asynthetos are translated also as “compounded” and “uncompounded”
intervals, respectively. The ditone, F–A, cannot contain any intervening notes
in the Enharmonic genus, but in the Diatonic genus it is divided by the note G
and, as such, it is thought of as “compounded” of two whole-tone intervals.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
247
the interval remaining on the subtraction of two whole-tones from the
fourth. For this subtraction left an interval computed to be 256:243, an
interval that is slightly smaller than a true semitone if, on their construction, such an interval could be said to exist. Moreover, they showed that
adding one such semitone to another, or 256:243 x 256:243, results in an
interval that is somewhat smaller than a whole-tone computed to be 9:8.
In sum then, the assumptions of Aristoxenus contradicted everything that
mathematicians accepted as self-evident knowledge.14
Ptolemy and the mathematical theorists were right in charging
Aristoxenus with violating the fundamental laws of mathematical harmonic theory. But their grounds for indicting him on these charges
were misjudged. For when Aristoxenus computed the whole-tone and
the octave in the manner charged against him, it was not as the basis
for his theory but, rather, the result of his altogether original procedure.
As argued earlier, Aristoxenus’ is a generalizing procedure by which one
can calculate the distance between points on the continuum only when
one knows the quantities that fix their positions. Knowing Aristoxenus’
formula – the whole-tone of twelve equal units – one can discover all
the intrinsic properties of the continuum, that is to say, all those properties which do not depend upon its relation to points outside of the
continuum. Thus, one can discover that two semitones (6 + 6) do in fact
equal a whole-tone (12). The differences between the Pythagorean theory of music and the actual practices of musicians, which Aristoxenus’
theory represents, are, in short, as great as the differences between the
geometry on a plane and the geometry on a sphere.15
14
15
This is part of the classical argument against the Aristoxenian method in which
the focus is kept on the distances, or empty spaces, between notes, rather than
on the intrinsic qualities of the notes themselves. Cf. Barker, II, p. 295, n. 86.
To argue this point, Ptolemy Harm. I. 10 (Düring, 21. 21ff.) actually parodies Aristoxenus Harm. El. II. 56 (Da Rios, 69. 12ff.), in which Aristoxenus
describes his method of tuning by consonances and referring his conclusions
to the ear alone. Ptolemy’s parody is so apposite that Barker suggests that he
may have had Aristoxenus’ text before him. See Barker, II, p. 295, n. 88. For a
mathematical analysis of the fourth, see Solomon, Ptolemy, pp. 34–35.
Thus, where the rational hypothesis of metrical geometry, as implemented by
the Pythagoreans and the canonicians, eventually replaced the ear with the eye,
the algebraic properties of the geometric circle may be said to have replaced
248
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
If Ptolemy had much to say against the line of investigation that
Aristoxenus projected in his theory of harmonics, it was in part because
he could not envisage a system based on any activities other than those
assigned to perception and reason. To arrive at a positive understanding
of what is in the world of the ear was possible in his view provided only
that the proper methods be used. And these derived from sensation and
rational thought – the only sources of knowledge. That the nature of
empirically given things could be accounted for by acts of intuition –
which are often attended by feelings of absolute certainty – could not
be countenanced by Ptolemy. Thus, whereas Aristoxenus was aiming
at the liberation of music from traditional mathematics through the
mediation of musical intuition, Ptolemy was committed to a different
purpose entirely: the reconciliation of music with traditional mathematics through the application of logic. How far Ptolemy was ready to
proceed along this route is the question to which the opening chapters
of his monumental treatise, Harmonics, bear testimony.
Ptolemy begins his Harmonics by defining the province of the field
and identifying the criteria it employs in its investigations. The
proper focus of harmonics being sound and its attributes of pitch, its
goals, according to Ptolemy, are not only to account for the noticeable differences between the pitches of the various musical scales but
also to provide reliable means for measuring these differences. These
goals, Ptolemy explained, required a close collaboration between
the ear and rational thought – an alliance, as it were, in which the
abilities peculiar to the one would assist the other to an accurate
determination of attunement, or harmonia. Andrew Barker has stated
Ptolemy’s position with respect to the criteria in these unambiguous
terms:16
the eye with the mind. Cf. Kline, Mathematics in Western Culture, p. 177.
In Aristoxenian theory, the mind is added to the ear so as to back up the proposition that a series of notes is a collection of intervals having no minimum
distance. But the mind can posit an arbitrary distance of the kind represented
by Aristoxenus’ quantum to make the series numerically measurable. This
requires that the quanta used have a common (koinon) character such that each
number belongs only to the things being counted: musical intervals. Cf. Klein,
Greek Mathematical Thought, p. 81.
16 Barker, Ptolemy, p. 15.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
249
It is clearly Ptolemy’s view . . . that reason and perception are not competitors
for the scientist’s allegiance, as some harmonic theorists – and others – had
supposed. Properly understood, they are allies, and the scientist cannot
afford to ignore either.
Thus Ptolemy:17
The science of harmonics is a function of making perceptible the differences between sounds with respect to highness and lowness, sound being
an affection of air that has undergone percussion – the primary and most
general cause of things that are heard. The criteria of harmonia – hearing
and reason – do not operate in the same way, insofar as hearing occupies
itself with matter and its affection,18 while reason is concerned with form
and cause. In general, this is because the peculiar province of the senses is to
discover what is approximate and to be apprised of its accuracy; while the
peculiar province of reason is to be apprised of what is approximate and to
discover of its accuracy.
Ptolemy goes on to argue that because the domain in which perception operates is unprocessed matter, whose properties are unstable,
fluctuating, and multifarious, perception cannot but be influenced by
the same unreliability that afflicts the data it records. But because it is
the capacity of reason not only to impose form on these data obtained
by perception in its rough-and-ready fashion but also to discover their
cause, reason operates in conjunction with that which is uniform and,
like itself, inherently stable. On this basis, reason, being dictated to by
all that is orderly and cohesive, must support perception by providing it
17
18
Ptolemy Harm. I. 1 (Düring, 3. 1–8). On the difficulty of translating Ptolemy’s
dynamis (function), see Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 2, n. 3.
Ptolemy’s word here is pathos, which is translated by Barker, II, p. 276, as
“modification,” by Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 3 as “condition.” The problem with
pathos, as explained by Barker, Scientific Method in Ptolemy’s Harmonics, p. 16,
n. 16, is that it is often used to refer to a pain or to a disease. Here, however,
Ptolemy seems to mean the “impression” made on the ear. As Barker adds:
“More broadly, a person’s pathē may be his experiences, not necessarily ones of a
distressing sort. Hence, in connection with perception a pathos may be the content of a sensory experience, the impression made on a person’s consciousness
by an external object, through the channels of the senses.”
250
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
with a corrective for its innate deficiencies. Perception needs, therefore,
a crutch of some sort (baktēria) that will function as a monitor. And it
is only reason itself that can supply this necessary assistance.19 Ptolemy
proceeds thereupon to demonstrate that what may appear to the senses
to be identical will be proved by reason to be in fact different. This,
he explains, especially holds true in the case of minimal relations, the
capacity of perception to make judgments being far more reliable when
confronted by maximum proportions. In saying this much, Ptolemy
appears to be referring to Aristoxenus’ own method of arriving by ear at
such minimal relations as ditones and semitones, namely, by using the
larger and more easily perceptible intervals – fourths and fifths – as his
standards of judgment.20 But the consonances are used by Aristoxenus
not solely as aids for the ear to make correct judgments; rather, they are
enlisted by the ear to confirm what it already knows to be true in advance
of the tuning process. Because he is speaking to musicians, Aristoxenus
makes this crucial point in such casual terms that its significance is
easily missed. Thus, Aristoxenus:21
It is obvious to those who are not inexperienced in instruments that by increasing the tension on the string, we raise its pitch; and in decreasing the tension,
we lower its pitch. But during the time in which we are raising the pitch and
changing the tension on the string, it is not possible that the height of the pitch
which is going to result through the increase in tension is as yet in existence.
In other words, if the pitch to be arrived at by these means exists
anywhere, it is potentially in the mind’s ear. For, as Aristoxenus implies,
the mind’s ear knows in advance what pitch it is seeking. It is this
knowledge that guides the instrumentalist’s tuning processes. Thus,
even while the ear is doing the perceiving, it is the mind that is doing
the judging. And all this complex activity is taking place simultaneously, without outside assistance or intervention.
19
20
21
See Barker (note 16). According to Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 4, n. 13, however:
“One of the premises of the Harmonics is that reason generally surpasses the
senses and that, insofar as music and harmonics are concerned, reason surpasses
the hearing.”
Cf. Chapter 3, note 58.
Harm. El. I. 11 (Da Rios, 16. 3–7).
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
251
To Ptolemy, however, neither the eye nor the ear can be trusted to
make correct estimations, especially in the case of minimal differences.
He argues, for example, that the eye will assess a circle to be a perfect
one until another is drawn by a compass. Comparison between the two
will then reveal to the eye the imperfections in the circle which it had
judged to be perfect. So, too, when certain differences between sounds
are accepted by the ear to be correctly distributed, measurements in the
form of appropriate mathematical ratios will often prove the ear to be
wrong. As he says:22
The ear, being provided with a basis for comparison, will then recognize
which is the more accurate, distinguishing the genuine, as it were, from the
spurious. And since it is generally the case that the judging of something is
easier than the creating of that same thing, it being easier, for example, to
judge a wrestling match than to engage in one, easier to judge a dance than
to dance oneself, easier to judge a performance on the aulos than to play it
oneself, easier to judge a song than to sing it oneself; then the deficiency of
perception is such that when it comes to recognizing merely the difference
or the lack of it between things, it would not depart appreciably from the
truth.
Whereas Ptolemy had argued earlier for the close alliance of perception and reason, here, for reasons not immediately apparent, he so
effectively severs them, one from the other, that they end up becoming combatants in the never-ending war between critics and performers. For in assigning the role of judging (krinai) to perception and
that of performing to reason, Ptolemy not only undermined his own
argument, but revealed the philosophical chasm that existed between
himself and Aristoxenus.23 To Aristoxenus, the performer is nothing if
not his own best judge. In the case of an aulete or citharode, certainly,
22
23
Ptolemy Harm. I. 1 (Düring, 4. 6–12).
Barker, II, p. 277, note 9, defends Ptolemy’s thesis by saying “our senses are
better equipped to judge such things than to construct them. Hence, we can
detect our mistakes through the same channels that we relied on when we
made them.” Cf. Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 5, note 19, who observes of this passage:
“The entire passage has harmonic implications foreshadowing Ptolemy’s refutation of the Aristoxenian assertion that six whole tones equal a diapason.”
252
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the collaboration between sensation and reason is complete. It is so
complete, as Aristoxenus makes explicit,24 that reason seems not only
to surmise, but actually to experience its union with something, which
Ptolemy calls matter (hylē), that is foreign to its own nature, which
Ptolemy calls form (eidos). If anything, Ptolemy seems here to be putting the act of attunement – a preliminary to performance on an instrument – on a par with the far more difficult act of performance itself.
Leaving aside the problems raised concerning performers and critics,
Ptolemy goes on to point out how noticeably inaccurate perception can
be when it comes to comparing minimal distances. Taking the division of a straight line as an example, Ptolemy proceeds to explain that
the eye needs greater assistance from the tools of measurement as the
relative dimensions it attempts to compute grow progressively smaller,
dissimilar, or more numerous. He then concludes the opening chapter
of the treatise with the following statement:25
Just as the eyes require for that purpose [the judging of minimal, dissimilar, and numerous distances] a rational criterion in the form of appropriate
instruments, as for example, a carpenter’s line (stathmē), let us say, for estimating the straightness itself, and a compass (karkinos) for measuring off a
circle and its parts, the same obtains for sounds and hearing. In the same
way, the ears, which together with the eyes are the chief servants of the contemplative and rational part of the soul, need some sort of approach derived
from reason for dealing with those things of which the senses are by nature
not given to judge accurately – an approach against which the senses will not
bear contradictory testimony, but with which they will be in agreement.
In the second chapter of Book I, Ptolemy discusses the instrument derived from reason to assist the ear – the harmonic canon. Its
name, he explains, testifies to the collaboration between perception
24
25
See note 43.
Ptolemy Harm. I. 1 (Düring, 5. 2–10). Ptolemy has set the stage here for the
Harmonics in its entirety by treating vision as the primary source of reliable
knowledge. For it is always vision, as he argues the case, that aids hearing, and
not the other way round. In this, Ptolemy is of a mind with Aristotle Met. 980a
1–7, who prizes vision above the other senses as the bringer of knowledge.
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 6, n. 28 thus observes: “Ptolemy uses the sense of sight as
a visible analogy to the sense of hearing.”
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
253
and reason described in the first chapter, inasmuch as its harmonic
component preserves the integrity of the observed data which its
canon – literally, ruler – attempts to reconcile rationally with the
laws of mathematics. To pursue his purpose, then, the harmonician
must turn away from the deficiency and inaccuracy of the senses,
away from all verbal solutions, away from all poor a priori reasons
and pretended absolutes, and direct himself toward the concreteness
and sufficiency of the facts supplied by the precision instrument, the
harmonic-canon. His purpose in so doing is to arrive at the truth.
With this in mind, his approach to the phenomena must be no less
scientific than that of the astronomer. That is, he must discover what
the observed facts mean without contradicting what they say. What
the harmonician should care about above all else are the inferences as
to the sensible phenomena which his hypotheses enable him to make.
His hypotheses should therefore be workable insofar as their results
will conform with the observed phenomena.26 Ptolemy then goes on
to explain in what respects the proponents of the leading schools of
harmonic theory – the Pythagorean and the Aristoxenian – depart
from this scientific method.
Porphyry’s aim is to capture the essence of Ptolemy’s dialectic.
Thus, to read Porphyry’s commentary along with Ptolemy’s text and
Porphyry’s citations from the work of Ptolemaïs is to listen in, as it
were, on something much like a Platonic dialogue – Platonic, in the
sense that the three participants in this case are engaged in the same
sort of pursuit as that which occupied Plato’s discussants: a search
for pure knowledge. The knowledge that these three are seeking
concerns harmonia – the type of knowledge it exemplifies and the
best way in which it can be represented. The dialogue derived from
these texts (mutatis mutandis) commences with a discussion of the
canon.27
26
27
Thus Barker, Ptolemy, p. 26: “Ptolemy’s exhortation to ‘save the hupotheseis,’ is
evidently related to the more familiar project of ‘saving the phenomena.’ The
difference is one of perspective and emphasis. In both cases the goal is to show
that the truths accessible to reason and the phenomena presented to the senses
are in harmony with one another, and that if their evidence is judiciously considered one can consistently accept both.”
The changes in Porphyry’s text will be noted where required.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
254
Ptolemy:
What is the purpose of the harmonician? The instrument for such an
approach is called “harmonic-canon,” a name derived from its common
category and from its measuring-out, literally, “canonizing,” those things
which the senses lack for arriving at the truth.28
Porphyry:
You are saying, I gather,29 that the instrument for the approach in question is that which reason invented and gave to the senses for the purpose of “canonizing” those things that the senses lack in themselves for
arriving at the truth; and that the instrument under discussion is called
“harmonic-canon,” so-called from the common term for the instrument –
which is called canon – that discovers what the senses lack in their ability
for attaining accuracy. Of course, the name, “canon,” and the approach
for the senses called canonic in harmonic theory, do not come from the
canon, so-called, namely, the cross-bar of the cithara on which its strings are
stretched. Rather, the Pythagoreans, who were, above all, the inventors of
this approach, called it canonic, in the same sense in which we today call
our theory harmonic; but some of them define the canon, which is the measure of accuracy of proportions, in this way: “A canon accurately measures
28
29
An extensive, but late, tradition assigns the invention of the canon to Pythagoras
himself. Cf. above, Chapter 4, n. 34. Ptolemy Harm. I. 8 (Düring, 18) describes
its construction, he being the only theorist to have done so, and offers a drawing
of it. According to his description of it in Harm. II. 12 (Düring, 66–67), it was
a lutelike instrument consisting of a long neck, which terminated in a hollow
resonating chamber over which a single string was stretched from a peg fixed
at the top of the neck to a fixed bridge (batēr) at the base. Between the neck and
the base there were moveable bridges (magadia) at each end, these operated by
the left hand, while the right hand plucked that part of the string which was
stretched over the resonating chamber. It was an excellent tool for scientific study,
but very difficult to use for musical purposes. As Ptolemy reports in Harm. II. 13
(Düring, 67. 21ff.), Didymus, the musician, was the first person to introduce some
improvements to make the instrument more amenable to musical performance,
making the bridge easier to manipulate, for example. Cf. Ruelle, “Le Monocorde,
Instrument de Musique,” REG, 311–12. See also, Barker, II, p. 292.
Porphyry, Commentary (Düring, 22. 10) wrote, literally: “He [sc. Ptolemy] says
that the instrument for the approach . . .”
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
255
the different attunements amongst musical notes, those differences which
are studied in the form of numerical ratios.”30 But here is Ptolemaïs of
Cyrene,31 who writes about this in her work, The Pythagorean Doctrine of the
Elements of Music.
Ptolemaïs:
For whom, then, is the canonic discipline of greater importance? In general, for the Pythagoreans. For the discipline which we speak of today as
harmonic, they used to call “canonic.” For what reason do we speak of it as
canonic? Not, as some people think, from its having been named after the
instrument, the canon, but from its [quality of] straightness, since it is on
the basis of this science that reason discovers what is right and what the
fixed rules of attunement are.32
Porphyry:
The term “canonic” is in fact applied also to the study of syrinxes, auloi, and
other instruments, even though these are not canonic instruments.33 But
since ratios and theorems are applicable to them, even these instruments
are called canonic. It is rather the case, then, that the instrument called
canon was named after the canonic discipline. But in general, a canonician
is a harmonician who deals with the ratios that concern attunement. There
is, however, a difference between musicians and canonicians. For musicians
30
Porphyry does not identify the source of this statement other than that it comes
from the Pythagoreans, who invented and practiced canonic science.
31 Porphyry, Commentary (Düring, 22. 22–24) wrote, literally: “Indeed, Ptolemaïs
the Cyrenian writes about this also in her Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of
Music as follows: . . . ”
32 The science of straightness to which Ptolemaïs refers here is the sort of
metrical geometry that is exemplified in the Sectio Canonis of Euclid; cf.
Chapter 4, n. 6.
33 Porphyry means by ‘canonic’ the mathematical laws according to which all musical instruments – whether they be stringed, like lutes, lyres, and harps, or winds,
like syrinxes (reedless panpipes) or auloi (reeds) are constructed. See, for example,
K. Schlesinger, The Greek Aulos, pp. 3ff., Mathiesen, Apollo’s Lyre, pp. 159ff. And
K. Coates, Geometry, Proportion and the Art of Lutherie, pp. 106ff. Cf. R. A. Higgins
and R. P. Winnington-Ingram, “Lute Players in Greek Art,” JHS 85 (1965),
62–71.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
256
who proceed from the evidence of the senses are called harmonicians; but
canonicians are Pythagorean harmonicians. Both are, of course, musicians in
the generic sense. But Ptolemaïs has some question to raise here.34
Ptolemaïs:
Of what things are the theory of the canon constituted? Of the general
assumptions that are postulated by musicians and that are adopted by
mathematicians.35
Porphyry:36
The assumptions that are postulated by musicians are those data derived
from the senses that the canonicians accept, as, for example, that certain
intervals are concordant and discordant, and that the octave is composed
of the fourth and the fifth and that the whole-tone is the excess of the fifth
over the fourth, and similar assumptions. But the facts accepted by mathe
maticians are those that the canonicians study in their own way in terms
of proportion, only after they have been moved to do so by the points of
departure provided by the senses. They base their theory on the fact, for
example, that the musical intervals consist in numerical proportions and
that musical pitch derives from numbers of percussions, and matters of a
similar sort. One might determine, then, that the postulates of canonic
science belong to the science of music as well as to that of numbers and
geometry.
34
35
36
Porphyry Commentary (Düring, 23. 10) wrote, literally, “She [sc. Ptolemaïs]
adverts to these matters again in question and answer form.”
In this concise statement, Ptolemaïs is using the technical language of philosophy. The general assumptions postulated (ὑποτιθεμένων) by musicians such
as Aristoxenus are made after countless observations and much experience.
Her reference here is clearly to Aristotle Met. 981a5: “Art is born when out
of many bits of information derived from experience there emerges a grasp of
those similarities in view of which they are a unified whole” (trans. Hope). See
note 40.
Barker, II, p. 240, has assigned this entire passage to Ptolemaïs. But in n. 138,
he adds: “This sentence and the remainder of the paragraph may be from
Porphyry’s pen, rather than that of Ptolemaïs.”
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
257
Ptolemy:
The purpose of the harmonician should be the preservation by all possible
means of the rational postulates of the canon,37 the postulates that in no
way whatever conflict with the senses as they pertain to the judgment of the
greatest number of people, just as the purpose of the astronomer should be
to preserve the postulates concerning the heavenly movements that accord
with their courses as observed by us [on earth], seeing to it that the postulates themselves have been derived from the manifest and general outline
of the phenomena, while discovering by rational means their particulars
as far as is accurately possible.38 For it is in all cases the special province of
the theoretician and the scientist to demonstrate that the works of nature
have been wrought with a certain logic and fixed cause, there being nothing in nature that is without plan, nor anything accomplished by nature in
random fashion. This applies especially to all those constructions of such
surpassing beauty as those belonging to the more rational senses, sight and
hearing.
37
In translating hypotheseis as “postulates,” I am following the rationale
of Barker, II, 278, n. 15. In his Ptolemy, pp. 23–24, he says, however: “I
have rendered the word [hypotheseis] as ‘postulate’: but as a translation it
is hardly adequate . . . [hypotheseis] are fundamental propositions which are
not formally derived from others that the discipline has already established,
but which form the basis for the derivation or explication of subordinate
propositions.” Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 7, translates the phrase as: “the reasoned hypotheses of the canon.” As he points out, p. 7, n. 34, “Preserving
the hypotheses” was an important concept in ancient Greek science.” Cf.
note 38.
38 Barker, Ptolemy, p. 26, observes: “Ptolemy’s exhortation, to ‘save the hypotheseis,’
is evidently related to the more familiar project of ‘saving the phenomena’.”
According to P. Duhem, To Save the Phenomena: An Essay on the Idea of Physical
Theory from Plato to Galileo, pp. 5–6, the ancient astronomers had the same purpose in mind as that expressed here by Ptolemy: “the object of astronomy is
here defined [by Simplicius in In Aristotelis quator libros de Caelo commentaria 2.
43. 46] with utmost clarity: astronomy is the science that so combines circular and uniform motion as to yield a resultant motion like the stars. When its
geometric constructions have assigned each planet a path which conforms to
its visible path, astronomy has attained its goal, because its hypotheses have then
saved the appearances.”
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
258
Porphyry:39
You write of these matters, Ptolemaïs, in your introduction which I
mentioned earlier.
Ptolemaïs:
Pythagoras and his followers are pleased to accept perception to begin with
as a guide for reason, so as to offer reason some sparks, as it were; but reason,
after it has been stimulated by these sparks, is treated by the Pythagoreans
as something that works independently, standing quite apart from perception. And even if their system, though discovered by the diligent prosecution of reason, is hence no longer in tune with perception, they do not
repudiate their position, but charge perception with being aberrant and
assert that it is reason which discovered by itself what is correct and that it
is reason which convicts perception of being wrong. Standing in opposition
to these Pythagoreans are some musicians of the school of Aristoxenus who
adopted a theory based on conceptual thinking (ennoia), while developing
it from their training in instrumental practices. For these musicians viewed
perception as their leading authority, while treating reason as a follow-up to
be used only as needed. According to these musicians, as may be expected,
the rational postulates of the canon40 were not in every case in accord with
perception.
39
40
Porphyry Commentary (Düring, 23. 24–25) wrote, literally: “Ptolemaïs writes
about these matters in her aforementioned Introduction.”
The phrase, “the rational postulates of the canon” was introduced here by
Ptolemaïs, in whose writings it was found by Didymus, who passed it on
to Ptolemy Harm. I. 2 (Düring, 5. 14). It is repeated verbatim just below
by Porphyry. As Barker, Ptolemy, p. 25 sees it, the expression “is not altogether clear. The parallel phrase used here [by Ptolemy], ‘the hupotheseis
of the movements in the heavens’ . . . refers plainly to the principles governing those movements, or to expressions of those principles as scientific
propositions.” As applied to the canon, however, Barker finds the expression
“ambiguous.” Ptolemaïs, as is argued (see note 44), understood these rational hypotheses or postulates of the canon as axioms accepted by mathematicians, because they were necessarily imposed on them, not as affirmations
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
259
Porphyry:
But Ptolemy sought to show that the rational postulates of the canon do not
in any way conflict in any respect with the senses, as regards the judgments of
these musicians; and, in fact, it is the special feature of his harmonic treatment
that accounts, too, for his departure from the calculation of divisions made
by the former theorists [the Pythagoreans]. He made the same point in his
astronomical writings also in holding that the astronomer’s purpose must be
to preserve the postulates concerning the heavenly motions that accord with
their courses as observed by us [on earth]; and that the postulates themselves
must be derived from the manifest and general outline of the phenomena, not
only discovering by rational means their particulars as far as is accurately possible.41 He in fact speaks of this at the beginning of his Treatise on Mathematics
[Mathematikē Syntaxis = Almagest I. 2; Heiberg, 9. 11] in these words: “We
shall try to show each of these things, using as principles and foundations for
our investigations the manifest phenomena and the undisputed observations
of the ancients and of our contemporaries, reconciling with their observations
the resulting judgments through the use of proofs involving the geometrically linear approach.” It is correct to say that the task proper to the observer
and to the scientist is demonstrating that the works of nature have been
wrought with a certain logic and fixed cause, there being nothing in nature
that is without plan, nor is anything accomplished by nature in random fashion. For the Pythagoreans also were given to saying and promulgating the
view that it is essential to banish randomness from all quarters, both from our
way of life and from our theory and practice, and to realize that in no way does
randomness exist in nature, seeing that nature is the finished product of Mind
(nous), the why and the whence existing in Mind. Almost all philosophers
agree that the fairest of the senses are sight and hearing and some, such as he
[sc. Ptolemy], call them rational because they render a special service to reason
in its pursuit of an appropriate theory.
41
of the musical mind, but as affirmations of the properties of the stretched
string of the canon.
It may be said in this connection that Aristoxenus’ hypothesis of equal measure
is a statement of principle by which he proposed to “save the phenomena” that
are presented audibly to the ear, namely, the phenomena, or appearances, of the
melodic continua.
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
260
Ptolemy:
Some theorists appear to have paid no attention at all to this purpose, devoting their attention to the technical craft alone and to the
bare and irrational exercise of perception; while others have been more
theoretically inclined in approaching their goal. These would be the
Pythagoreans and the Aristoxenians in particular – both of whom
were wrong. For the Pythagoreans, because they did not defer to the
impression of the ear in all those cases in which it is essential to do
so, applied ratios to the differences between sounds, ratios which were
often incompatible with the phenomena, the result being that they
created a basis for calumny against their sort of criterion amongst
the theorists who held a different opinion. On the other hand, the
Aristoxenians, because they accorded the greatest importance to the
facts derived from the resources of perception, treated ratios as extraneous to the subject, being in violation of the ratios as well as of the
phenomena. They [sc. the Aristoxenians] were in violation of the ratios
in that they adapt numbers, that is, the semblances of ratios, not to
the differences between sounds, but to the spaces between them; they
were in violation of the phenomena in that they also match up these
numbers with divisions which are extrinsic to the testimony of the
senses. Each of these violations will become clear from the facts that
will be introduced, provided that the preliminaries to what follows
are first defined.
Porphyry:42
I believe that you wrote concisely about these issues in your introduction,
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, and that Didymus, the musician, followed up on them
at greater length in his work, On the Difference Between the Aristoxenians and
the Pythagoreans. What is it that you had to say?
42
Porphyry Commentary (Düring, 25. 3–8) wrote, literally: “The Cyrenian Ptolemaïs
wrote concisely about these issues in her Introduction, and Didymus the musician followed up on them at greater length in his work, On the Difference Between
the Aristoxenians and the Pythagoreans. We shall record what was said by both of
them, making a few alterations for the sake of brevity. Ptolemaïs writes thus as
follows.”
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
261
Ptolemaïs:
What is the difference between those that have been preeminent in music?
For some of them preferred reason alone, while others preferred perception
alone, and still others preferred both together. Reason alone was preferred by
the Pythagoreans, those Pythagoreans who rather enjoyed contending with
the musicians for the purpose of casting out perception altogether and introducing reason as an independent criterion that works by itself. But these
Pythagoreans are completely refuted by their accepting something that is
perceived by the senses at the very beginning and then disregarding it altogether. Instrumentalists, on the other hand, preferred perception, but for
them it did not in any sense become the conceptual basis for a theory, or if it
did, it was a trivial one.43 What is the difference between those who preferred
both in combination? Some accepted both perception and reason on equal
terms as being equivalent in power, while others took the one as their guide
and the other as a follow-up. Aristoxenus the Tarentine took them both on
equal terms. For [as he saw it] an object of perception cannot exist on its
own apart from rational thought, nor is rational thought sufficiently strong
to prove anything without accepting its first principles (archai) from perception and then paying back its debt to perception in the form of a theory,
the conclusion of which theory agrees in turn with perception.44 What is the
basis for his willingness to grant perception the lead over rational thought?
On the basis that perception comes first in the order of events, but not on the
43
44
Ptolemaïs speaks here of instrumentalists (organikoi) in much the same way as
Aristoxenus did of his predecessors, the harmonikoi. In fact, Barker, II, p. 241,
n. 145, suggests that this entire statement by Ptolemaïs is based on Aristoxenus
Harm. El. II. 32 (Da Rios, 41. 19ff.), where Aristoxenus criticizes his predecessors for rejecting the senses as inaccurate. Her words also closely echo those of
Aristoxenus Harm. El. II. 41 (Da Rios, 52. 4ff.), where he dismisses any theory
that is based on instruments as atopos, or “out of place.”
Cf. Barker, II, p. 241, n. 146, who points out that what Ptolemaïs says here
as to Aristoxenus’ principles (archai) and their dependence on perception is a
theme that is pervasive throughout Aristoxenus’ Harmonic Elements. It should
be noted also that she has in this statement concisely defined the true character
of science: the preservation of the phenomena within the connective links of
true generalizations. That certain scientific theories never die is thus owing
to their consistent expression of true relations. Cf. H. Poincaré, Science and
Hypothesis, pp. 164–65.
262
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
basis of its power. For, he says,45 “Whenever a perceptible object, whatever it
may be, makes contact with this [sc. perception], then we must promote rational thought to the forefront, in order to get a theoretical understanding of this
[sc. perceptible object].” Who regard them both in the same way? Pythagoras
and his followers.46 For they are willing to accept perception initially as a guide
for reason so as to provide reason with sparks, as it were; but reason is treated
by them as something which, though set into motion by perception, works
by itself, standing quite apart from perception. And even if, as a result, their
system which was discovered by the application of reason no longer is in tune
with perception, they do not retract their opinion, but charge perception with
being deviant and assert that it is reason which discovered on its own what is
correct and that it is reason which refutes perception. Who are opposed to these
theorists? Some musicians of the school of Aristoxenus, all those who accepted a
theory based on conceptual thinking, while promoting it from their training in
instrumental practices. For these musicians considered perception as their leading authority, while treating reason as a follow-up to be used only as needed.
It is at this dialectic juncture that Porphyry introduced into his commentary his citations from the work of Didymus, the musician, most of
which have been represented at the end of Chapter VI. And, as becomes
obvious on comparison between Didymus’ statements and those of
Ptolemaïs, it was indeed Ptolemaïs herself who was the primary source
for Didymus. This is especially true in the case of Didymus’ words,
which bear repeating here:47
Music is not only a rational knowledge, but it is at [one and] the same
time perceptual and rational; hence it is necessary for the truly systematic
45
46
47
It is not uncommon for direct quotations to be introduced, as Ptolemaïs does
here, by φησί (“he says”). Since quotation marks were unknown, other devices
such as that used by Ptolemaïs were routinely employed. Numerous examples of
a similar sort may be found in Ps.-Plutarch De mus. quoting from Aristoxenus.
See. e.g., Frs. 80, 81, 82 (Wehrli) where the convention, “he [sc. Aristoxenus]
says,” is as Ptolemaïs has it.
In making a few changes for the sake of brevity, Porphyry manages to mis
attribute this strictly Aristoxenian position to the Pythagoreans. The rest of
this passage repeats almost verbatim what was recorded earlier. On these problems with Porphyry’s text, see Barker, II, p. 242, n. 148 and n. 149.
See Chapter 6, note 48.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
263
student not to neglect either one of the two, even while having what is
evident to perception take the lead, since it is from there that reason must
make its beginning.
Didymus’ words bear repeating for the additional reason that
they appear to contradict his earlier statement about those organikoi (instrumentalists) and phonaskikoi (voice coaches) who, he said,
are habitually engaged in an irrational or non-rational (alogos) activity. Didymus was wise enough to know, of course, that no irrational
activity deserved to be called a technē, an “art,” such as iatrikē (the art
of medicine), or rhetorikē (the art of public speaking).48 Yet here he
agrees with Ptolemaïs in characterizing music as a “rational knowledge” (logikon mathēma) and, hence, qualified to be included among
the various fields of knowledge as a genuine technē, or mousikē. The
inference to be drawn is that instrumentalists and voice experts were
more concerned with performing techniques than with the status of
mousikē as a rational knowledge. The question is, however, in what
respect is music a rational knowledge: is it abstract and intuitive or
is it experimental and scientific? To her credit, Ptolemaïs saw that
this problem is linked to the meaning of logos, or, more properly,
the meanings of logos. For logos and the forms to which it gives rise
in these contexts – logikos (rational) and logikoi hypotheses (rational
hypotheses or rational postulates) – meant one thing to Ptolemy, but
quite another to Aristoxenus.
To Ptolemy, the rational postulates of the canon49 – a phrase he
may have picked up from Ptolemaïs by way of Didymus – are those
mathematical formulae which interpret or “rationalize” the intervallic relations that are classified to begin with by the ear. They are
judged by the ear to be concordant or discordant, but it is the task
of the canonician to prove them to be such. To Aristoxenus, however, the question of rationality and irrationality belongs to a different line of inquiry entirely, one that has nothing to do with the
ratios (logoi) of canonic science. For in his theory of music, intervals
48
49
Indeed, as Socrates said in Plato Gorgias 465A5–6: “I will not call any irrational endeavor (alogon pragma) an art (technē).”
Cf. note 40.
264
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
are considered rhēta (rational) or aloga (irrational) in virtue of the
relation that they bear to the melodic genera in which they participate. Intervals are rational, therefore, if they can be played or sung
in any of the genera and nuances of melody. To be sure, Aristoxenus’
quantum – 1–12 of a whole-tone – is, if taken in isolation, amelōdētos,
or “unsingable,” as he specified; but taken as a natural unit of enumeration, it broke through the obstreperous bonds of the canonic
ratios and freed Aristoxenus to define rationality and irrationality in
strictly melodic terms. With 12 as his basic unitary and indivisible
measure, Aristoxenus could treat any interval, no matter how small
it might be, as rational, if it was commensurate with his quantum.
Thus, intervals such as the enharmonic diesis (–14 tone) or the chromatic diesis (–13 tone), which escape reliable measure on the canon,
could be established to the ear’s satisfaction as consisting of 1–32 and 1–42,
respectively.
The debate over the criteria – Aisthtēsis and Logos – thus belongs to a
larger topic: the proper scientific method for dealing with the subject,
Harmonics. As practiced today, Harmonics is a strictly mathematical
discipline that is limited to analyzing the complex periodic motions in
sound production (called Fourier analysis), and to determining the complex periodic motion from a given set of harmonic components (called
Fourier synthesis).50 In antiquity, Harmonics had a far greater reach. For
Ptolemy, it had to do with the absolute and organic unity implicit in the
notion of harmonia: the correct fitting together of parts. Ptolemy’s goal,
therefore, was to discover the correct attunement (hērmosmenon) for melody. As Aristoxenus saw it, however, Harmonics was a branch of a larger
discipline, which he called the Epistēmē of Melos, the Science of Melody.
His goal, therefore, was to discover the correct constitution (synthesis) of
melody.51
50
51
So, too, in projective geometry, the relation between two points is thought of as
‘harmonic’ when it involves a reference to two other fixed points. Thus, a relation of four terms may serve to divide a straight line into two parts with respect
to any two of its points. See Russell, Principles of Mathematics, pp. 384–85 on
quadrilateral constructions and harmonic ranges.
This synthesis began with the topological limits or boundaries formed by the
proper arrangement of fourths and fifths in the continuum of melodic space.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
265
In Ptolemy’s lexicon, Harmonics was the very counterpart of
Astronomy. Indeed, as he argues the case, the difference between the two
is essentially one of language and not in what is being described. In the
course of arguing this position, Ptolemy uses the words logos and logikos
to mean three very different things: rational thought, the spoken word,
formula:52
No one would predicate beauty or ugliness of things touched, tasted, or
smelled, but only of things seen and heard, as when we speak of form and
melody, or again, of heavenly motions and human actions; for which reason
sight and hearing are the only ones of all the senses that quite often offer
their mutual services to the rational (logikos) part of the soul in the form
of their reciprocal perceptions, as though they two were actually sisters.
Indeed, hearing explains visible things solely through its interpretations,
while vision reports on audible things solely by means of written illustrations.53 And it is often the case that a clearer understanding of each of these
This method of dealing with the infinite divisibility of the continuum made
it possible for Aristoxenus to speak, for example, of two tetrachords of
the same genus as being consecutive (ephexēs), or of two tetrachords being
in contact (synaphē) when the highest note of one tetrachord coincided
with the bass note of another tetrachord. That all such types of syntheses
or constitutive elements in Aristoxenian theory are based on the teachings of Aristotle has been detailed by Bélis, Aristoxène, pp. 153–55. The
Aristotelian model for these concepts in Aristoxenian theory are examined
(independently of Aristoxenian theory) by White, The Continuous and the
Discrete, pp. 23–25.
52 Ptolemy Harm. III. 3 (Düring, 93. 20–94. 20). According to Plato Theaetetus
206D1–2, logos and dianoia have a very close relationship for, as Theatetus
points out, a logos is the making apparent one’s thought (dianoia) through
speech (literally, through nouns and verbs).
53 Ptolemy does not explain how the sense of hearing interprets what the eye
sees. Barker, II, p. 373, in translating this passage, supplies the words “by
means of [spoken] explanations.” When it comes to the priority of the visual
sense where music is concerned, Aristoxenus has a significantly opposing
view. As he argues in Harm. El. II. 39 (Da Rios, 49. 12–14), the written,
or notated, form of a Phrygian melody is of little or no help in conveying
the mode (tropos), or “Phrygianness” of such a melody. As it happens, the
Aristoxenian Aristides Quintilianus De mus. I. 9 (Winnington-Ingram, 19)
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
266
facts of perception is attained than if the same facts are interpreted by the
one to which they belong. Such is the case when things transmitted by the
spoken word (logos) are rendered more intelligible to us and are more easily remembered by us when accompanied by diagrams or symbols; while
things recognizable by sight are revealed more imitatively through poetic
interpretation – the appearance of sea-waves, for example, and scenes and
battles and the circumstances of emotions, so that people’s souls are made
to sympathize with the forms of the things that have been communicated
to it, as though these things had been seen with one’s own eyes.54 It is,
therefore, not only by the senses each apprehending what is proper to it
alone, but by both senses somehow assisting one another to learn and to
understand everything that is accomplished by each in accordance with
its own appropriate formula (logos), that these senses themselves, and the
most rational of the sciences that are based on them, reach more deeply
into beauty as well as into usefulness. Of these most rational sciences, the
one pertaining to vision and to the motions in place of things that are
only seen – that is, the motions of the heavenly bodies – is Astronomy;
and the science pertaining to the motions in place, again, of things that
are only heard – that is, the motions of sounds – is Harmonics. Since
gives us a glimpse of the ancient Phrygian mode, or harmonia (together
with the Lydian, and Iastian) to which he said Plato referred in Rep. 399A.
Because Aristoxenus himself may have been Aristides’ source here, the
Phrygian scale which Aristoxenus may have had in mind would look something like this:
The
54
enharmonic character, or ethos, of this scale springs instantly into view.
But, according to Aristoxenus Harm. El. I. 23 (Da Rios. 29. 15ff.), the ear
has only to hear the ditone (as between F and A) to recognize the beauty of
a melody composed in this style – the beauty which cannot be conveyed by
viewing the entire scale. On this evidence, see Levin, “The Hendecachord of
Ion of Chios,” TAPA 92 (1961), 304–05; Barker, II, pp. 420–21; Mathiesen,
Aristides, p. 86. Cf. Henderson, “The Growth of the Greek ἁρμονίαι,”
98–99.
Following Aristoxenus’ line of argument, however (note 53), poetry, not even
with all its mimetic powers, can succeed in interpreting a strain of melody.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
267
both of these sciences use the incontrovertible instruments, arithmetic and
geometry, for judging the quantitative and qualitative attributes of the
primary motions, they are as first cousins, born of the sister senses, sight
and hearing, and are reared so closely as is generically possible by arithmetic and geometry.
These are the words of a confirmed Pythagorean – one who was not
only imbued with Platonic doctrine, but one who had also assimilated
the teachings of Archytas, the Pythagorean par excellence. For it was
Archytas who wrote at the beginning of his Harmonics:55
The mathematicians seem to me to have acquired superb knowledge; and
it is not at all unusual that they think correctly about individual things
and their nature. For by having acquired exceptional knowledge about
the nature of the universe, they must have come to see its parts and their
nature very well, also. They have, in fact, handed down to us a precise
understanding about the velocity of the stars and their risings and settings, as well as about geometry, numbers, and spherics, and not least,
about music. For these seem to me to be sister sciences, since their concern is with the sister subjects: the first two forms of being [things heard
and things seen].
Even though Ptolemy criticized the Pythagorean method for dealing
with consonant intervals, such as the octave and a fourth, and judged
their system for grading ratios as “utterly ridiculous” (panu geloios), his
sympathy with the Pythagorean worldview was fundamental.56 If this
55
56
This is quoted by Nicomachus Introduction to Arithmetic I. 3 (Hoche 6. 17–7.
4). Cf. Vors. 47B, Fr. 1. Diels – Kranz, I, p. 432, understand Archytas’ first two
forms of being here as “Zahl und Grosse” (number and size).
On Ptolemy’s criticism of the Pythagoreans, see Barker, Ptolemy, p. 71, who
says of Ptolemy’s criticisms of the Pythagoreans’ principle that all consonances
have to be either multiple or epimoric ratios: “It is one of the most savage
passages of critical writing in the Harmonics – Ptolemy positively devours the
unfortunate theorists, spicing the funeral meats with peppery sarcasm.” Barker
adds to this highly seasoned account this important observation: “Ptolemy’s
268
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
licensed him to chide them – sometimes mercilessly – on points of detail,
it was only because he wanted the Pythagorean method to be perfect in
all respects, even if he had to make it so himself. That he succeeded in
his undertaking is an effect of his mathematical genius; but it is no less
an effect of the very nature of mathematics itself. For Harmonics, as
Ptolemy conceived it, had to become a branch of universal mathematics
if it were to be truly scientific. Ptolemy’s success in this purely scientific
endeavor is in fact reflected in the mathematically balanced structural
design of his Harmonics, the three books of which are each neatly composed of sixteen chapters.57 Even more remarkable is the supersymmetry
he achieved in his system of seven tonos-scales in whose central octave
(as from E to E’) the seven species of a revolving set of octave scales are
uniformly located.58
unmerciful assault should not be allowed to mislead us. In one important
respect their approach is closely parallel to his own.” The point to be made (and
which has been made fully by Barker in these pages) is that Ptolemy shares the
assumptions of the Pythagoreans when it comes to distinguishing the consonant intervals.
57 See Solomon, Ptolemy, pp. xxxi–xxxii.
58 Centuries before Ptolemy, Aristoxenus had revolutionized the system of cithara
tunings by fixing the relative pitch of the mode-bearing keys of transposition
at equal semi-tones from one another. These tunings, or raisings and lowerings of the entire cithara (the principle being much like that of the modern
pedal-harp), were thought of as tonoi. Each tuning brought the desired modal
segment of the Greater Perfect System into a practical vocal range. See Fig. 4
and Fig. 9. To take one example: the diatonic sequence of intervals marking
the Phrygian mode is: D, E, F, G, A, B, C, D (tone, semi-tone, tone, tone, tone,
semi-tone, tone). This sequence is preserved intact in the F to F octave of the
tuning: C, D, E♭, F, G, A♭, B♭, C, D, E♭, F, G, A♭, B♭, C (the Greater Perfect
System of the Phrygian tonos). Ptolemy Harm. II. 5 (Düring, 51–53) effected
an innovation on this centuries-old system, first by reducing the number of
keys from 15 to 7, and second, by distinguishing notes in respect to their
position (kata thesin) in the individual mode and in respect to their function
(kata dynamin) in the tonos. Thus, for example, in the octave segment F–F
(earlier), the note C is mesē by function, but B♭ is mesē by position. Cf. Macran,
Aristoxenus, pp. 63–64; Barker, II, p. 325, n. 37; Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 73, n.
68; Henderson, “Ancient Greek Music,” 352–56. Reinach, La musique grecque,
p. 58, speaks of Ptolemy’s tonoi as “malentendus” and even more Aristoxenian
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
269
In sum, the more mathematically logical his method, as he developed
it, the farther Ptolemy removed himself from Mousikē, the art of music.
Jon Solomon has aptly stated Ptolemy’s aims in these words:59
than Aristoxenus’ own system of 13 tonoi. Ptolemy’s schēmata, for which see
Fig. 9, seem to have found little success with practicing musicians.
Mixolydian
F
Gb
Ab
Bb
Cb
Db
Eb
|
F
Mese
Lydian
F
G
A
Bb
C
D
|
E
F
D
E
F
C
Db
Eb
F
B
C
D
E
F
A
Bb
C
D
E
F
Ab
Bb
C
Db
Eb
F
Mese
Phrygian
F
G
Ab
Bb
C
|
Mese
Dorian
F
Gb
Ab
Bb
|
Mese
Hypolydian
F
G
A
|
Mese
Hypophrygian
F
G
|
Mese
Hypodorian
F
|
G
Mese
Figure 9. The Seven Tonoi of Ptolemy
59
Solomon, Ptolemy, xxxv.
270
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
But Ptolemy had no intention of writing a book about music. His
work is on harmonics, and despite our familiarity with the modern derivative of that term, and despite that “harmony” has quintessentially a
musical meaning and only [a] secondarily a metaphorical meaning. . . .
Ptolemy’s conception of harmonics was one that was self-contained,
well-established, highly scientific, and technical.
Harmonics, as practiced by Aristoxenus, however, was a different
field entirely, and no one saw the root of the difference more clearly
than Ptolemy. In his criticisms of the Aristoxenians, by whom he meant
Aristoxenus himself, he draws our attention to Aristoxenus’ radicalism
by contrasting it with the Pythagoreans’ rationalism. The Pythagoreans
focused on individual notes and, in accordance with Ptolemy’s views,
defined the differences between these notes by numerical ratios, even
though perception contradicted them on occasion.60 But Aristoxenus,
by concentrating on the intervals or spaces between the notes, not
only contradicted the numerical ratios but also arrived at results that
Ptolemy found truly impossible to describe. He called them eikonēs
of the ratios,61 which Barker translates as “the images” of the ratios
and Solomon as “the symbols” of the ratios. Eikonēs is, however, not a
complimentary term. In using it, Ptolemy had in mind those units of
measure by which Aristoxenus divided the whole-tone into twelve equal
parts. Divisions of this sort were no more rigorous to Ptolemy than
the Aristoxenian method of computing the whole-tone as the difference between the fourth and the fifth. The whole-tone must be defined
instead by its proper ratio, 9:8. Nor could Ptolemy refer Aristoxenus’
divisions of the melodic topos to the notes themselves, for there would in
60
61
Ptolemy’s rationale for the Pythagorean position with regard to pitch and
quantity is best expressed by Barker, Ptolemy, p. 35 (perhaps better than by
Ptolemy’s own representation): “All differences whose causes differ quantitatively, however, are themselves quantitative, no matter how they are perceived;
and hence the question whether a distinction that seems qualitative actually
is so raises quite recondite issues that fall into the province of the scientist. It
is not to be answered on the basis of appearances alone.” No statement can be
more contra Aristoxenum than that.
Ptolemy, Harm. I. 2 (Düring, 6. 8–9).
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
271
this case turn out “to be infinitely many of them in each ratio.”62 Worst
of all, Ptolemy could not submit Aristoxenus’ divisions to verification.
As Ptolemy argued, therefore, the Pythagoreans may have gone
astray by relying too heavily on the ratios, thereby contradicting the
ear at times; but Aristoxenus did far worse: not only did he violate the
integrity of the ratios, but he had to have offended the ear by postulating eikonēs, or “simulacra” of the true facts: the canonic ratios. To
Ptolemy, these eikonēs of Aristoxenian theory were as abstract wraiths,
rooted in imagination and bearing no relation to reality, for they could
not be verified objectively. When it came, therefore, to his theory of
melodic quanta, Aristoxenus was in as difficult a position as that of
present-day cosmologists; for cosmologists today are subject to the
same sort of criticism as that leveled against Aristoxenus by Ptolemy:
there are no objective ways to verify their proposals for a quantum theory of gravity.63
Aristoxenus, had he been present to hear Ptolemy’s criticism, would
have been little troubled by it, because he had no doubts about the
convenience of his method for the study of melody. He knew something fundamental: that if we study melodic consecution, it is in
order to apply it; and we can only apply it if it remains objective. For
Aristoxenus, then, the source of melodic truth was not solely perception, as his critics charged, but experiment with the concurrence of the
ear (akoē) and musical reason (dianoia). Ptolemy and the Pythagoreans
had of course conceded that the matter (hylē) of harmonics is provided
by the ear. But, as Ptolemy argued, harmonic truths can only be verified
by measurements on the canon. In order to arrive at harmonic truths,
62
63
Ptolemy Harm. I. 9 (Düring, 20. 11–14).
Aristoxenus was engaged in a pursuit not unlike that of present-day scientists.
For scientists today are seeking a single theory that will unify all the insights
derived from relative and quantum theory and link them to the real world (that
is, to the world outside their minds). So, too, Aristoxenus was seeking a unified theory of melody that would link together the delicate networks of scales,
keys, and modes and anchor them to musical reality. To Ptolemy, Aristoxenus’
was apparently just an imaginative theory that was rooted in the more unscientific realms of metaphysics. Thus, Ptolemy had to have failed when it came to
translating Aristoxenus’ representations into the language of mathematics. Cf.
Barker, Ptolemy, pp. 115–17.
272
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the harmonician or canonician must believe that the numerical ratios
derived from these canonic measurements are themselves true; and if his
belief in these ratios is unconditional, then the ratios become his incontestably true facts. As Aristoxenus argued, however, these ratios, derived
as they were from the straight line of the canon, had nothing to do with
his subject, because his subject had no connection with a straight line.
His subject, as he defined it, was the nature of musical melody, and the
facts with which he had to deal were not simply notes and intervals, but
phenomena that are much harder to interpret: melodic genera, melodic
species and, most important, the nature and origin of continuity in the
musical scales. That being the case, a new science was required to deal
with these and related phenomena and, as Aristoxenus reminds us, he
had to invent this new science himself.64
Aristoxenus’ science was far from being universally received; but,
as Ptolemy’s criticisms (given earlier) show, it was a science that could
not be ignored. Ptolemaïs neither ignored it nor did she criticize it; on
the contrary, she is one of the few authorities, if not the only one, to
champion it. She began by indicating that the science of canonics has
the closest kinship with the eye, whereas that of Aristoxenus belongs
to the ear alone. It follows from this, as she implies, that Aristoxenus
chose to give unity to all his melodic constructions not within ratios
abstracted from the canon, but within the vivid and audible forms of
melody. Setting Ptolemy, Porphyry, and Ptolemaïs in the framework of
a discussion is admittedly rather unfair to Porphyry. For in contrast to
the single-mindedness of Ptolemy, arguing for the virtues of canonic
science, and Ptolemaïs, offering a philosophical basis for Aristoxenus’
theory, Porphyry comes across as verbose and digressive. If he is not
repeating the words of his sources almost verbatim, he is introducing
irrelevancies, as, for example, the cross-bar of the cithara, only to reject
it as a derivative of the term “canon”; similarly gratuitous is his observation about syrinxes and auloi being “canonic” for being subject to
64
Aristoxenus Harm. El. I. 4 (Da Rios, 8. 16–9. 4): “Hitherto these questions
[continuity of species and genera in musical melody] have been absolutely
ignored, and in dealing with them we shall be compelled to break new ground,
as there is in existence no previous treatment of them worth mentioning”
(trans. Macran).
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
273
mathematical laws, even though they are not, strictly speaking, canonic
instruments. Porphyry is obviously a polymath and, just as obviously,
he wants the reader to know it.
Porphyry’s most important contribution to the discussion is his categorization of musicians into two kinds of harmonicians: those who proceed from the evidence of the senses, by whom he probably means the
Aristoxenians; those who base their theory on the canon, these being,
he says, the Pythagoreans. What lies behind these categorizations is
the notion that things perceived by the ear can be accounted for in
the same way as things perceived by the eye. Assuming, then, that the
world of the ear and that of the eye consist somehow of parallel phenomena, the path to their respective realities must lie in the application
of what Ptolemaïs, in open disapproval, calls “the rational postulates of
the canon,” a phrase which Ptolemy picks up with intentional approbation. For, as Ptolemy argues, the harmonician is engaged in the same
sort of task as that of the astronomer: to preserve the phenomena – those
heard as well as those seen – while adhering to the principles invented
by reason, that is, mathematical reason. To violate the one, mathematical logic, is therefore just as unscientific as contradicting the other, the
evidence of the senses. Barker is especially helpful on this point:65
To “save the hupotheseis,” in this context [that of accounting for beauty
in the phenomena] at least, is not just to show that certain complexes of
mathematical propositions are true, but to show that they are indeed the
principles which underlie the facts to be coordinated and explained – that
is, that certain perceptible patterns of sound relations are admirable and
beautiful, while others are not.
There are, of course, serious limitations to the similarities between
visible and audible phenomena, and it is to these that Ptolemaïs directs
us in all of her statements. She begins by calling attention to the quality
of straightness that is the basis for all the computations of canonic theory. As she explains, the canon, by virtue of its straight edge, gave title to
the branch of mathematics called Kanonikē. This term – Kanonikē – was
in fact introduced into the language by Ptolemaïs herself to designate
65
Barker, Ptolemy, p. 27.
274
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
a discipline – the canonic method, or pragmateia – that was intended
to bridge the gap between the world of audition and that of vision.
The question and answer form she adopts here is reminiscent of the
Aristotelian Problems; what is more, the noun she uses – euthytēs – to designate the quality of straightness that belongs to the canon, is uniquely
Aristotelian. In using euthytēs in this context, she directs us, perhaps
intentionally, to Aristotle’s Categories, where Aristotle explains that
sometimes the quality of a thing (as, in this case, straightness) does
not give its name to the science that is based on it.66 But, as Aristotle
says elsewhere, the very quality that enables us to judge both it and its
opposite is present in the soul:67
For one part of the soul is sufficiently able to judge itself from its opposite
and to judge what is opposite to it. For indeed it is by means of a straight
line that we recognize both straightness itself and its opposite, crookedness.
For the straight-edge (Kanon) is a judge of both. But what is crooked is neither a judge of itself nor of that which is straight.
As Ptolemaïs argues, therefore, “canonic” denotes straightness – the
essential visual property that allows for the representation of a stretched
string by a mathematically straight line. Little wonder, then, that the
Pythagoreans looked to the canonic method for arriving at harmonic
66
67
See Aristotle Categories 10a10 on euthutos and its opposite, kampulotēs, crookedness. See also, Categories 10b5: “Sometimes, moreover, the quality possesses a
well-defined name, but the thing that partakes of its nature does not also take
its name from it.”
Aristotle De anima 411a 3–7. The notion of recognizing the “rightness” of
things through a knowledge of its opposite, “wrongness,” is one that goes back
to Plato and the pre-Socratics. Thus, for example, in Gorgias, Plato explains
how a doctor recognizes illness because he has a thorough knowledge of its
opposite, health. The principle is adhered to by Aristoxenus in his Harmonic
Elements, where he emphasizes that the truly scientific musical theorist is one
who recognizes an unmusical (ekmelēs) melody because of his knowledge of its
opposite: a musical (emmelēs) melody. Cf. Harm. El. I. 18 (Da Rios, 23. 19–24.
4). As Aristoxenus argued, there is a fixed principle underlying all musical
melodies, a principle which ordains that a correspondence of fourths and fifths
be maintained between every note of the scale on which a good melody is
framed. Cf. Barker, II, p. 129, n. 24.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
275
truths since, as Ptolemaïs observed, it is only on the straight line
that mathematical reason (logos) can discover, without the assistance
of the ear, what is right (orthos). Implicit in Ptolemaïs’ assessment of
the Pythagorean doctrine is this important fact: there are no terms in
the world of melody that are parallel in meaning to “straightness” and
“rightness.” We may speak metaphorically of “high” and “low” on the
vertical dimension of pitch, and we may refer to an orthios melody, by
which term we do not mean in ancient Greek music a “right” or “correct” song but a high-pitched one.68 And although it is a commonplace
to speak of a melodic “line,” be it ancient or modern, it is never in
application to a straight line, but to the thematic “contour” of a melody.
As Ptolemaïs impresses on us, then, the language of canonic theory is
strictly visual in its references, whereas the spatiality of the melodic
world is in no way amenable to measurement on the straight line of the
canon. She emphasizes the distinction between the visual and the aural
world additionally, in the most inventive way possible, by the use of
a metaphor: parapēgmata. The translation of this word, as here, by the
phrase “fixed rules of attunement,” does not do full justice to the metaphor, and Barker has perhaps more wisely left the word to stand transliterated rather than translated. Parapēgmata is of the world of vision in
its most conspicuous form: it is an astronomical term that refers to the
pegs inserted into stone to mark the predictable events of an astronomical and meteorological nature.69 By applying parapēgmata to the proportional divisions on the canon, Ptolemaïs has brought to our notice the
unalterable status of the numerical ratios of canonic theory.
In her next intervention, Ptolemaïs links musicians and mathematicians to the same starting point of harmonic knowledge: sensory perception. Here, her carefully chosen words are intended to mark the
differences between the two theories: that of the musicians, such as
Aristoxenus and his followers and that of the Pythagoreans and their
68
69
Thus, Talthybios in Euripides’ Trojan Women 1265–66 refers to the highpitched (orthian) sound of the salpinx (trumpet). And Herodotus I. 24 tells of
Arion’s singing an orthion nomon, a song perhaps so plaintive that it brought
about his rescue from the sea by a musically astute dolphin.
Diogenes Laertius 9. 48 speaks of a work by Democritus entitled The Great Year
or Astronomy, Calendar (parapēgma).
276
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
exemplars, the canonicians. As she has it, the musicians have their
hypotheses, by which term she means those undemonstrable principles that are arrived at by induction; the canonicians adopt these same
principles as matters of fact that are accepted, provided that they be
demonstrably true. Ptolemaïs thus framed the difference between the
two theoretical schools on the subtle distinction between those melodic
presentations which the minds of musicians construct for themselves –
consonance and dissonance, for example – and the numerical ratios by
which the canonicians give these presentations a concrete and demonstrable reality.
Porphyry’s commentary on these points is welcomely instructive and
doubtless was drawn from the text of Ptolemaïs herself. He thus defines
those general assumptions of musicians that lend themselves to mathematical documentation: the composition of the octave, the dimension of
the whole-tone, and the fact of concordancy and discordancy. He might
have added the important fact that the canonicians would accept musicians’ assumptions so long as the logical aesthetic of the Pythagoreans
was maintained, this being that only two types of ratios were deemed
admissible into the canonic system: multiples and superparticulars.70
Instead, Porphyry introduced something that is totally irrelevant in the
present context: that musical pitch is produced by numbers of percussion on the air by vibrating bodies. It is an issue that was thoroughly
explored by Euclid in his Sectio Canonis and falls beyond the range of
Ptolemaïs’ discussion.71
Ptolemaïs’ range of discussion was not limited to the similarity of
the evidence treated by the musicians and the canonicians, but, rather,
to the different modes of reasoning which ruled on the admission of this
evidence into their respective theories. All things considered, Ptolemaïs
70
71
Ptolemy Harm. I. 6 (Düring, 13. 23–14.2). Cf. Barker, II, p. 287, n. 59,
who directs us to Plato’s criticism of the Pythagorean harmonicians in Rep.
531B8–C4: “They are just like the astronomers – intent upon the numerical
properties embodied in these audible consonances; they do not rise to the level
of formulating problems and inquiring which numbers are inherently consonant and which are not, and for what reasons” (trans. Cornford).
Cf. note 36. On the role of percussion in the production of pitch, see Chapter
4. Cf. Barker, II, p. 240, n. 139. See also Levin, “Plēgē and Tasis in the
HARMONIKA of Klaudios Ptolemaios,” Hermes 108 (1980), 212–19.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
277
was in effect stating that musicians were concerned primarily with
what is, while the canonicians were concerned primarily to demonstrate
in the most scientific terms possible that it is so. Thus, for example, a
musician’s knowledge of what a consonance is may not in the strict
sense be a thought or a proposition (logos); it is more like an intimation, or a prompting of the musical mind. To a canonician, however,
it is the effect of a numerical relation of a certain type. The kinds of
ratios involved in the articulation of consonances and dissonances thus
make up the constituents of canonic science. In stating these points.
Ptolemaïs draws our attention once again to Aristotle, even to adopting
his mode of discourse (question and answer) as well as his terminology.
Thus, Aristotle:72
What is a consonance?
A numerical ratio of high and low pitch.
Why is the high note concordant with the low one?
Because a numerical ratio obtains between the high note and the low one.
Can high and low be concordant? Does their relationship consist in
numbers?
Accepting that it does, what then is the ratio?
Ptolemaïs’ response to questions such as these is an implicit “yes.”
Yes, relationships such as octaves, fifths, fourths, and whole-tones can
be represented in “the rational postulates of the canon,” these being
some of the elements of which melody is constituted. But melody contains much more than these, much that cannot be obtained from mathematics. As her few words suggest, then, harmonic knowledge proceeds
from perception through induction to the first principles of musicians,
and back through deduction to the conclusions of mathematicians from
these first principles. Ptolemaïs saw that the end-point of musicians’
induction is the starting-point of the canonicians’ demonstration.73
72
73
Aristotle Post An. 90a19–23.
As Ptolemaïs suggests here, canonics is a deductive science, and every deductive
science, canonics in particular, rests on a certain number of indemonstrable axioms. But there is a distinction to be drawn between the intuitions of musicians
and the axioms of canonic science. Thus, for example, when Aristoxenus asserts
in Harm. El. II. 45 (Da Rios, 56. 10–12) that if any consonance be added to an
278
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
She also saw that, owing to their differences in structure, the two
doctrines – that of the canonicians and that of the Aristoxenians – were
headed for a philosophical collision. On the one side, that of musicians,
there was limitless resourcefulness; on the other, there were the inherent
limitations of canonic theory. For, as Ptolemaïs perceived, the hypotheses of musicians comprehend only those things that can be expressed
melodically, while the canonicians will accept only those things that can
be expressed in multiple or superparticular ratios. But, as any musician
would see immediately, these, “the rational postulates of the canon,” are
too limited in their scope to provide a theoretical understanding of the
complexities of melodic phenomena. Taking one example – the ditone:
to a canonician, mathematical reasoning (logos) defines the ditone as 9:8
x 9: 8 = 81:64 (the Pythagorean major third); but to a musician, it
is musical logic (Aristoxenus’ dianoia) that defines the ditone as the
outstandingly characteristic interval of the Enharmonic genus.
Ptolemaïs was scrupulous, therefore, in distinguishing between the
criteria employed by Kanonikē and Mousikē. For, as she saw it, because
the objects of each science were decidedly different from one another,
the criteria, being specific to these objects, had also to differ from one
another. Pushing her analysis of these criteria further, Ptolemaïs ended
up treating the rational postulates of canonic theory as just so many
toilsome justifications of a doctrine that was, as Aristoxenus charged,
irrelevant to the subject: Mousikē. But Ptolemaïs did not stop there.
She charged Kanonikē, and the Pythagoreans who practiced it, with
the most egregious crime against science: the facts being treated were
forced to fit the theory being postulated.74 It is not coincidental that the
74
octave, the sum is a consonance, this is not a proposition in canonic science, but
one that is proper to musical analysis specifically.
In charging the Pythagoreans with having violated the most fundamental
rule of scientific inquiry – saving the phenomena – Ptolemaïs again directs
us to Aristotle Met. 986a3–8, where he charged the Pythagoreans with
altering the evidence in the interests of their theory. Cf. Harold Cherniss,
Aristotle’s Criticism of Pre-Socratic Philosophy, pp. 223–25. Ptolemaïs echoes
Aristotle even more closely, her words carrying the same content as his in De
caelo 293a25–27, where he says of the Pythagorean invention of a counterearth to make the planets add up to the perfect number, ten: “They did this
not by seeking arguments and reasons to explain the phenomena, but by
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
279
basis for her criticism is detailed by a musician for, according to Paul
Hindemith, even though he spoke centuries later, nothing about music
has changed in this respect:75
Generally, a musician is not too fond of the sciences, especially of those that
in his opinion have no connection with music. Physics he perhaps allows
to have its say, since he is well aware of the acoustical conditions of his art.
At mathematics, however, he looks with scorn, because in his opinion the
obvious exactitude of this science cannot be reconciled with the artistic
liberty of musical creation.
To reconcile the artistic liberty of musicians with the exactitude of
musical logic, Aristoxenus had to invent a new system, one that would
be the least artificial in harmonic structure, but, at the same time, the
most convenient for melodic composition. This system had, therefore,
to be as unlike the canonic theory of the Pythagoreans as Aristotle’s
mathematics was unlike that of Plato’s. For the Pythagoreans, pure
mathematics – including the science of canonics – described strictly
mathematical forms and the relations between them. In contrast,
Aristoxenus’ system would be an applied form of mathematics, one
that described empirical objects and their relations to the extent, at
least, that they approximated the mathematical form on the canon.
One might say, then, that Aristoxenus’ system of approximation is
the converse of the canonician’s idealization of intervallic reality. As
Ptolemaïs evidently realized, the propositions of canonic science were
regarded by canonicians as necessarily true, because they described
unchangeable relations (intervals) between unchanging objects (notes).
Moreover, as she explains, the necessity of these truths was treated as
independent of their apprehension by the ear and independent, in fact,
of any preliminary acts of canonic measurement. Her implication is
that construction of intervals on the canon was not essential to prove,
say, that the octave is indivisible; such constructions served merely a
practical need of the canonician to guide him in his progress toward
harmonic discovery.
75
forcing the phenomena and trying to make them fit their own arguments and
opinions.”
Hindemith, A Composer’s World, p. 29.
280
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Despite her criticisms of Pythagorean doctrine, Ptolemaïs could
not but concede that their theory of harmonics had a powerful backing
from pure mathematics. But, as she made clear, this mathematical
method applied in her view only to what the Pythagoreans kept in of
the melodic phenomena, not to what they left out. For what they left
out is the fact that perception denies those very items which reason,
independent of perception, accepts as true. Some of the more obvious examples of such discrepancies between mathematical imperatives
and the ear’s judgment occur in the case of the multiple ratio, 5:1.
This is a consonance according to mathematical standards, but it registers on the ear as a double octave and a major third – a dissonance.
So, too, the superparticular ratio, 5:4, which should be a mathematically legitimate consonance, is apprehended by the ear as a major
third – a dissonance. But Ptolemaïs had much more on her mind than
discrepancies such as these. She was bent, rather, on comparing
Aristoxenus’ theory with that of the Pythagoreans, not so much to discredit theirs where music is concerned, as to promote his. To judge from
the few words of hers that Porphyry chose to quote, Ptolemaïs was trying to explain in what respects Aristoxenus’ doctrine was theoretically
sound.76
To begin with, she points out that Aristoxenus differed from the
Pythagorean canonicians in placing perception and rational thought
on an equal basis. To be sure, as she acknowledges, perception, on
Aristoxenus’ standard, comes first in the order (taxis) of events, but
it is not first in terms of its function or power (dynamis). For perception, operating on its own, is incapable of providing a rational basis
for a genuine theory. Inasmuch as her quote from Aristoxenus to this
effect is not to be found in his extant writings, it may be assumed
that Ptolemaïs had more of his writings before her than have come
down to us. Those of his words that she quotes refer specifically to the
76
Cf. Richter, Zur Wissenschaftslehre von der Musik bei Platon und Aristoteles,
pp. 178–79, who sees Ptolemaïs’ words and those of Didymus (who followed
her) as based on the arguments of Aristoxenus against the Pythagorean method
in Harm. El. II. 32–33.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
281
p henomena of melody, these being the perceptible objects of which he
speaks:77
Whenever a perceptible object, whatever it may be, makes contact with
this [sc. perception], then we must promote rational thought to the forefront, in order to get a theoretical understanding of this [sc. perceptible
object].
The rational thought, or logos, as Ptolemaïs quotes it here, has nothing to do with the logical postulates of the canon. On the contrary, it
is a strictly musical type of reasoning which comes into play when the
question of a note’s or an interval’s function (dynamis) arises. For the life
of every note or every interval takes its meaning and its justification
from the function that it performs as a member of the melodic whole.
Thus, what is omitted in Ptolemaïs’ representation of Aristoxenus’ theory is complemented by Aristoxenus himself:78
As a whole, our theory is about all musical melody, be it in song or on
instruments. Our treatment is referred to two things: to the ear and to reason (dianoia). We judge the sizes of intervals by ear, but we get a theoretical
understanding of their functions by our reason.
Dianoia – musical reasoning – is pivotal to Aristoxenus’ theory. And somewhere in her writings Ptolemaïs may have explained
how it operates in identifying the various functions of notes and
intervals.79 Without that explicit information, we are left to infer
77
78
79
On this quotation, see note 45. Cf. Barker, “Music and Perception: A Study in
Aristoxenus,” 10–12, on the nature of the phenomena under analysis.
Harm. El. II. 33 (Da Rios, 42. 8–13).
Ptolemaïs seems to have understood far better than other Aristoxenians that the
agreement between knowledge and its object where music is concerned consists
in an identity between the act of thinking and the object of thought. To put
it another way, it is an identification of an intelligible form with its defining
characteristics, these latter being in the soul itself. Cf. Aristoxenus Harm.
El. II (Da Rios, 51. 16–52. 4). These notions are made explicit by Aristotle,
who says of sound in De anima 425b26–28: “The action of the perceptible
object and that of perception is one and the same. I refer to the case of sound
282
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
from the writings of the master himself that dianoia comprehends
an immense range of human musical sensibility, as immense a range
as that required to see, for example, into the life of a poem. Where
melody is concerned, dianoia is a triangulation of intellectual forces
whose combined effect produces magnetic fields of understanding
that react now to one note and now to another. Dianoia responds to
the way in which notes in musical space attract, repel, and interact with one another, these activities depending on their respective
functions.80 It is for such reasons that Aristoxenus insisted that a
melody is no mere jumble of notes, but a statement of logic as comprehensive as that of a sentence. The logic of melody depended in
Aristoxenus’ theoretical scheme on the continuity of musical space,
the rationality of melodic functions, and the permanent consonantal
moorings of melodic correspondences. The logic of melodic continuity being paramount in Aristoxenus’ estimation, he stipulated that
despite everything asserted by mathematicians as to the divisibility
80
in its activity and hearing in its activity.” These activities are one, on the basis
that the defining characteristics of melody and the intelligible form it takes
in the mind of the listener are identical. See Sorabji, Time, Creation and the
Continuum, pp. 144–46.
In her criticism of instrumentalists, Ptolemaïs argued that their interests were
practical and not intellectual or conceptually theoretical (ennoia theorias). Cf.
note 43. Of the various types of musical knowledge, ennoia, on Ptolemaïs’ construction, would correspond to that faculty of the mind that retains concepts,
while dianoia, as in Aristoxenus’ lexicon, corresponds to the deliberative,
or noetic, intellect, which is capable of discursive or syllogistic reasoning.
Ptolemy Harm. III. 5 (Düring, 96. 21–27) actually distinguished seven types
of musical knowledge to match the seven species of the octave: imagination
(phantasia), which is concerned with the reception of sensible objects; intellect (nous), which registers the first impression of things; conceptual (ennoia),
which retains the form of a thing in its totality; rational thought (dianoia),
which is designed for inquiry and research; opinion (doxa), which is designed
for superficial conjecturing; abstract reasoning (logos), which is concerned with
correct judging of things; scientific knowledge (epistēmē), which is concerned
with truth and the comprehension of things (katalēpsis). All of these faculties come into play where music is concerned. Cf. Barker, II, p. 376, n. 44;
Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 146, n. 114. Cf. Johnson, “The Motion of the Voice,”
TAPA 30 (1899), 55.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
283
or indivisibility of any musical interval, it is melody alone which
divides musical space into the maximum number of parts it can
occupy so as to be intelligible to the musically cognizant ear (another
term for dianoia). As he maintained, melody, if it is truly musical, is
nothing if not logical in the way it divides into parts the space that
it occupies:81
We can trust in the fact that there is no interval which we play or sing
that we cut up into infinity. On the contrary, it is on the basis of melody
that we determine a certain maximum number into which each of the
intervals is divided. If we assert that this not only merits our trust, but
is in fact a necessity, it is obviously from the fact that musical notes that
succeed one another consecutively comprehend fractions of the aforesaid
number. Examples of such notes are those we have been playing since
antiquity, as, for example, the nētē, the paranētē, and the notes that succeed them.
If Aristoxenus had been as fortunate as Pythagoras in having had
an Archytas or a Philolaus to offer an account of his doctrine, the
profundity of his insight into the nature of melody would be better
appreciated today than is currently the case. As matters stand, we
can recover this much: Aristoxenus’ method for arriving at a proper
attunement of melody involved a process of dividing continuous magnitudes by using as a natural unit of enumeration a quantum which
was itself indivisible. This process was motivated by his views on
the distinguishability of melodic function (dynamis). Unfortunately,
Aristoxenus’’ own account of melodic function and its bearing on the
arithmetization of melody’s continuous magnitudes has not come
down to us. But, to judge from certain relevant and provocative statements that appear in his Harmonic Elements, his concept of the infinite with respect to the division of melodic space must have come to
him the moment he unhinged his attunement from the bonds of the
canonic ratios. Under this impetus, he contrasted his own method
with that of the Pythagorean canonicians in these words – words that
81
Harm. El. II. 53 (Da Rios, 66. 14–67.3).
284
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
betray his frustration with the reception that was being accorded his
theory of attunement:82
First of all, we must be quite aware of this: many have misunderstood us
in supposing us to say that melody admits the division of the whole-tone
into three or four equal parts. This misunderstanding is due to their not
observing that to employ the third part of the whole-tone is a very different thing from dividing the whole-tone into three parts and singing
them. Secondly, taken in the abstract, we assume no interval to be the
smallest.
As Aristoxenus had explained earlier, all of his statements
r egarding maximum and minimum limits on the line of pitch should
be construed with reference to these factors only: the capabilities of
the human voice and ear. He had these factors very much in mind
in the statement quoted earlier. For there he was concerned to contrast the division of the whole-tone into three or four equal parts by
mathematical means – an impossibility – with the employment by
the voice of thirds and fourths of whole-tones – a melodic necessity.
He brings this contrast into sharp focus by suggesting that it is one
thing to compute the fourth part of a whole-tone as a mathematician would, as 28:27, for example; but it is quite another matter to
employ the fourth part of a whole-tone in song or on an instrument
in the Enharmonic genus by having it approximate three twelfths of a
whole-tone, an approximation which the voice is capable of making.
So, too, it is one thing to compute a third of a whole-tone mathematically at 15:14, say, but it is quite another thing to employ a third
of a whole-tone in song or on an instrument in the soft or flat chromatic nuance by having it approximate four twelfths of a whole-tone,
a micro-interval that can be recognized by the ear. Aristoxenus’ point,
then, is that, taken in the abstract, there can be no smallest (or greatest) interval, melodically speaking, save that which the voice cannot
sing or the ear cannot identify.
On the one standard, then, that of melody, all intervals smaller than
the whole-tone can be spoken of (rhēta) because they are thinkable
82
Harm. El. II. 46 (Da Rios, 57. 6–12).
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
285
and, in that sense, rational.83 On the other standard, however, that of
mathematics, all intervals smaller than the whole-tone cannot be thought
or spoken of (aloga), because there is no whole-number ratio by which
they can be expressed. The inference is that in music, rationality has to
do with the kind of reasoning called dianoia by Aristoxenus, a level of
thought that not only generates phenomena such as quarter-tones and
thirds of whole-tones, phenomena which are connected with its own cognition, but also accepts the effects of these phenomena as they are given
in sensory perception. Thus, where music is concerned, what is rational is
of human origin; and what is irrational must be the work of nature. This
is, of course, to reverse the universal order of things because, as Ptolemy
had expressed it, there is nothing in the works of nature that is irrational
or done at random.
Once musical space was shown by the Pythagoreans to be alogos by
being mathematically indivisible, the fault, as they saw it, could not
be assigned to nature, but to man’s own disposition of the melodic elements. To pursue Aristoxenus’ doctrine, however, this state of things
had in reality to derive from man’s own intuition of musical space
as homogeneous and from his construal of the melodic functions as
melodically imperative. As if to prove as much, Aristoxenus’ intention
was to chart every specific route and generic artery of melody’s topography directly onto a symmetrical grid which he conceived to represent
melody’s ear-borne topology.84 It was there that he located the very center of music’s emotional gravity. This mysterious force, or gravitational
pull, issues forth on melody’s contact with the rational topography of
83
Thus, Macran, Aristoxenus, p. 238: “An interval [in Aristoxenian terms] must
be rational or irrational in virtue of the relation it bears to some quantum
outside itself.”
84 Such a grid is worked out by Macran, Aristoxenus, p. 249. As this grid shows,
Aristoxenus’ quanta form a domain which is reached by thought (dianoia), whose
acts find fulfillment in giving an account (logos) of its operations and in reckoning up (arithmein) their totality. Comparing Aristoxenus’ method to that of the
mathematical theorists, West, Ancient Greek Music, p. 168, makes this important observation: “Aristoxenus’ approach is very different. According to him, the
two inner notes of the tetrachord can be pitched anywhere within a continuous
band, and it is necessary to lay down boundaries to demarcate one genus from
another.”
286
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
human origin – the evenly distributed attunement of mathematical
continuity – and the irrational topology of physical origin – the harmonic series85 that is habituated in mathematical discontinuity.86
According to Aristoxenus, then, intervals are rational if they have a
legitimate function to discharge in melody; and the only arena in which
this function can work in a musically perceptible way is the melodic
continuity of a mathematical continuum. Musical reasoning, or dianoia,
can detect any violation of this most fundamental rule of melodic continuity (hexēs kata melos) that was laid down by Aristoxenus: the correspondence of the interval of a fourth between every note and the fourth
note distant from it; and the correspondence of the interval of a fifth
85
86
There is no certain evidence that the ancients were aware of the harmonic
series – the set of notes (called ‘harmonics’) that issue from pipes and strings
on the sounding of a “fundamental,” the notes produced by an entire aircolumn or an entire string. There is a reference by Aristoxenus Harm. El.
I. 21 (Da Rios, 27. 1–3) to what may be a ‘harmonic” produced by the
over-blowing technique of a virtuoso on the aulos. The word syrinx used
here by Aristoxenus is interpreted by Schlesinger, The Greek Aulos, p. 54, to
signify the mouthpiece of the single-reed aulos. But see West, Ancient Greek
Music, p. 102. On the harmonics of strings, see Roederer, Introduction to the
Physics and Psychphysics of Music, pp. 90ff.; on those of winds, pp. 117ff.
The Pythagoreans did seem to intuit that the closer the relations are to the
fundamental note (isotone?), the more consonant the intervals produced.
Just as Superstring theory seems to resolve the conflict between general
relativity and quantum mechanics, the juxtaposition of equal temperament on the harmonic series of physical nature appears to create a conflict between the notes of melody, a conflict that is as hard to explain
as the workings of the universe. Thus, harmony, in the modern sense,
and the tensions and resolutions between the notes of melody (epitasis and
anesis in Aristoxenian theory) derive from the conflict between equalized
intervals and those of the harmonic series. Cf. Cooke, The Language of
Music, pp. 40–41. The most remarkable thing about the harmonic series
is that its numbered sequence gives us the ratios of frequencies of all the
intervals produced from a fundamental tone. Thus, if one numbers the
notes of the series from one to sixteen, one finds that the upper note of
any octave always doubles the frequency of the lower note. Accordingly,
the notes represented by 1, 2, 4, 8, 16 are octaves, while 4 and 5 gives
the ratio of the major third, and 8, 9 give the whole-tone. See Fig. 10.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
287
between every note and the fifth note distant from it.87 Any deviation
from this rule would not only upset the attuned continuum, but would
have necessarily to result in an unmusical (ekmelos) melody. Aristoxenus
gives a vivid example of such a violation against the continuum, where he
Figure 10. The Harmonic Series
At
87
the same time, harmonics from 4 to 10 contain two kinds of major thirds
(4:5 and 7:9), two kinds of minor thirds (5:6 and 6:7), and three kinds of wholetones (7:8, 8:9, and 9:10). See Maconie, The Concept of Music, pp. 110–11. These,
the facts of acoustical nature, are met by anyone building a simple panpipe or
playing a complex aulos, and they challenge the musical mind to seek a solution. It is in fact possible that Archytas came upon the harmonic series in the
course of his experiments with the panpipe, for as his computations show, he had
located the major third in the ratio of 5:4, the 4th and 5th partials of the series.
Cf. Barbera, “Arithmetic and Geometric Divisions of the Tetrachord,” Journal
of Music Theory 21 (1977), 296. Cf. Barker, II, pp. 43–45. Fokker, “On the
Expansion of the Musician’s Realm of Harmony,” Acta Musicologica 38 (1966),
197, speaks of the duodecimal temperament as man-made: “It is a compromise
between the finite technical power of man and his inmost desire to realise the
highest musical truths attainable in his songs and instrumental playing.”
See Chapter 5, note 96.
288
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
describes a sequence in which one pycnum ( = two quarter-tones) directly
follows another, in other words, a sequence of two pycna would result in
the unmelodic: E E + F F+ Gb. Aristoxenus observes:88
A pycnum, neither a whole one nor a part of one is to be played or sung next
to another one. For the result will be that notes that are fourth from one
another will not form the consonance of a fourth, nor will notes that are a
fifth from one another form the consonance of a fifth. Notes thus situated
have been deemed unmelodic.
In confronting a sequence such as that described above by Aristoxenus,
the ear and dianoia do work as one: for the ear, the sequence would sound
utterly displeasing and would accordingly be interpreted by dianoia as
having violated the limiting law of tetrachords, that of the consonantal
fourth, or E–A. The four notes in this particular case must strike the ear
as unmelodic since, as dianoia would explain, they occupy an ill-defined
interval: E–Gb. An even closer alliance of the ear and dianoia is most
urgently required on the advent of metabolē, or modulation, this being
a change that is as essential to melody as metaphor is to language, to
poetic language, especially. Poetic metaphors have to be rationalized,
because they are expressed typically in language that is semantically
deviant. So, too, melodic modulations must be rationalized (by dianoia)
against an established harmonic, or well-attuned structure to which the
ear has become thoroughly trained. In processing a metaphor, we experience and require ourselves to interpret one thing in terms of another.
Similarly, modulation, in its simplest form, requires us to experience
and to process the function of a melodic element in one setting in terms
of its function in a different setting. The settings in question may be
scale structures, pitch ranges of the voice, modes, or keys.89 Speaking
88
89
Harm. El. III. (Da Rios, 78. 13–16).
Modulation was evidently as important to the ancients as it is to all composers of great and lasting melodies (one thinks instantly of Schubert, one of the
special masters of the technique). According to Ptolemy Harm. II, 6 (Düring,
55. 3–6), there is modulation by change of key (what we today call transposition) and modulation in which “the melody is turned aside from its proper
ordering, while the pitch [tasis] is not altered as such, but as having an effect
on the melody” (trans. Barker). For discussion, see Barker, Ptolemy, pp. 169–72.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
289
of modulation in the modern diatonic system, Richard Norton has
observed:90
Modulation, true modulation, means a complete change from one key to
another, which happens in three ways: 1) modulation by changing the
meaning of a harmony; 2) modulation by chromatic change; and 3) modulation by enharmonic change.
Metabolē and metaphora both mean “change”; the one, metabolē, signifying a change in melody, the other, metaphora, a change in meaning.
Aristoxenus’ all-too-few references to metabolē, there being only four
such in his Harmonic Elements,91 teach us something well beyond the
isolated facts of the canon; true melodic change (metabolē) can only be
90
91
As Solomon, Ptolemy, p. 77, n. 92 explains: “Ptolemy means that the change in
pitch does not simply carry the old succession of notes at a different pitch; in
fact, the pitch is almost irrelevant, especially compared to the importance of
pitch in modulation by tonos.” To state it another way, modulation has to do
with an identity of pitch and the change of its function in melodic formation,
for every modulation, whatever its type, demands some common element.
Norton, Tonality in Western Culture, p. 42.
In his first reference to the subject of modulation in Harm. El. I. 7–8 (Da Rios,
12. 15–18), Aristoxenus speaks of the most critical requirement for modulation, a requirement that not one of his predecessors saw fit to discuss or, as he
suggests, were too ignorant to consider worthy of discussion: the symbiosis
or affinity (oikeiotēs) between scales, regions of the voice, and keys. Although
Aristoxenus’ own examination of this critical factor in modulation has not
come down to us, his implication is clear enough: without such an affinity or
intimacy between scales, regions of the voice, and keys, there is no possibility
for modulation to occur. In his second reference to modulation in Harm. El. II.
34 (Da Rios, 43. 13–15), he speaks of melodic intervals that are identical, but
whose limiting notes differ in their melodic functions, these changes in the
functions of common elements leading to modulation. In his third reference in
Harm. El. II. 38 (Da Rios, 47. 17–48.3), Aristoxenus promises to define modulation, to explain how it arises, and to tell how many kinds there are, none of
these topics ever having been discussed by his predecessors. Aristoxenus’ own
discussion of these subjects does not survive. His fourth mention in Harm. El.
II. 40 (Da Rios, 50. 14–51. 3) concerns the differences between modulating
scales and non-modulating scales, and their relevance to different melodic styles
(tropoi) of composition. Aristoxenus concludes his remarks here by referring to
the profound and powerful ignorance of his predecessors.
290
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
explained by true melodic permanence.92 The two things that remain
constant and permanent in his harmonic doctrine are the Systēma
Ametabolon, the unchangeable or immutable scale, and the permanent quantum (menon ti megethos) that makes the construction of the
Systēma Ametabolon possible. As he explains, unless there is a permanent quantum to deal with the division and arrangements of the various elements involved in melodic composition, no distinctions can be
made between the ways in which these elements may function. He says
accordingly:93
It is obvious that the distinctions between the divisions and their forms
(schēmata) are predicated on a certain permanent quantum.
On the advent of modulation, the ear – especially the trained ear –
perceives that a note’s function must be intrinsically different from what
it would be if it were not modulating. But the construal of this advent is
a conceptual exercise of the musically cognizant mind (dianoia), a construal that has been induced by a novel melodic transition. Aristoxenus
thus realized, where other theorists did not, that the ear and reason
must operate as one. Moreover, as he saw it, the ear and reason must deal
simultaneously with permanent as well as with changeable elements,
for modulation involves both at the same time.
As Ptolemaïs of Cyrene evidently understood, then, there are certain
melodic situations that cannot be explained by the detached facts of the
canon, and modulation is one of the most vivid of them. When Ptolemaïs
pointed out, therefore, that Aristoxenus employed perception and reason on equal terms for the interpretation of melodic phenomena, it was
in recognition of a fundamental fact at the heart of Aristoxenian theory:
he did not work with experiment alone; he worked also with method. It
was this method that demanded the inseparable alliance of ear and mind
which enabled him not only to make melodic generalizations, but also
92
93
Harm. El. II. 33 (Da Rios, 53. 3–6).
Harm. El. II. 34 (Da Rios, 43. 19–44. 1). There is more than a hint of Aristotle’s
thoughts on change in this statement, especially in Physics 190a13, where he
speaks of the necessity for something always to underlie change. Cf. Barker, II,
p. 152, n. 19.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
291
to make melodic predictions. Ptolemaïs’ quotation from Aristoxenus
thus bears repeating if only to indicate that the conflicts between the
facts of the canon and the percepts of the ear forced Aristoxenus to look
at the melodic phenomena under different aspects, for he refused to be
a slave to the canonic ratios:94
Whenever a perceptible object, whatever it may be, makes contact with
this [sc. perception], then we must promote rational thought to the forefront, in order to get a theoretical understanding of this [sc. perceptible
object].
Without the ear and musical cognition working together in the
manner described by Aristoxenus (via Ptolemaïs), it is altogether
impossible to deal with something as subtle as modulation. Of the
four references to modulation by Aristoxenus, the saddest is the one
in which he promises to deal with modulation in the abstract, to
explain how it comes about, and to specify how many types there
are in the composer’s musical lexicon.95 This promise is not fulfilled
in Aristoxenus’ extant writings. But in a discussion about intervals,
he refers to the fact that beyond the ear’s ability to judge the sizes of
intervals, it is unable in itself to deal with certain melodic distinctions, as, for example, between composite and incomposite intervals.
For, as he explains further, knowing the difference between the sizes
of intervals is not sufficient for distinguishing between a simple
melody and one that contains a modulation, or between one mode
(tropos) and another. The reference that has provoked the greatest
dispute amongst scholars is the one in which Aristoxenus says:96
We must speak of the symbiosis (oikeiosis) of scales (systēmata) and regions
of the voice (topoi) and keys (tonoi), not by focusing on the tables of
micro-intervals (katapyknoseis) as the harmonicians do, but on the melody as
94
95
96
Porphyry Commentary (Düring, 25. 23–26).
See note 91.
Harm. El. I. 7–8 (Da Rios, 12. 8–18). See Winnington-Ingram, Mode in Ancient
Greek Music, pp. 74ff.
292
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
it moves from one system to another, and on what the keys are in which it
lies for the melody to move from one to another.
After criticizing his predecessors for barely touching upon these
critical issues, Aristoxenus concludes:97
But, to speak in general, this is the part of the study of modulation that
pertains to the theory of melody.
Aristoxenus’ theory of the symbiosis between scales, modes, and
keys depends ultimately on the permanent quantum which he extra
polated from the ear’s perception of continuity in melody. It is true, as
he acknowledged, that his permanent quantum is itself not an immediate fact of perception. But, as has been argued here, it can be viewed
as an appropriately selected unit of measure for approximating the
primary fact of perception: the melodic continuum. Even though it is
mathematically disconnected from the canonic ratios, it can nonetheless be used effectively and interchangeably with the empirical propositions of melodic theory. It is the purpose, therefore, which Aristoxenus’
permanent quantum served that makes it acceptable. This purpose was
to represent melodic concepts by ordered classes of quanta (twelfths),
their instances in melodic structures by elements of these classes, and
their relations in melodic forms by an arithmetization of continuous
magnitudes. It was this process – in reality, a replacement of the purely
exact mathematics of the canon with the approximately exact arithmetic
functions deduced from empirical premises – that enabled Aristoxenus
to do what he said had to be done:98
It is necessary to the science of music to assign and to arrange everyone
of the elements in music in accordance with the place to which it is limited, and if it is infinite, to let it be.99 As regards the magnitudes of the
97
98
99
Harm. El. I. 8 (Da Rios, 12. 17–18).
Harm. El. III. 69 (Da Rios, 86. 6–12).
Macran and Barker translate Aristoxenus’ word apeiron as “indefinite” and
“indeterminate,” respectively. As argued here, however, the problem that
Aristoxenus faced was to reconcile those elements that are fixed by the laws
of melodic consecution – the functions (dynameis) of notes, the species (eidē)
of consonances, the positions (thēseis) of the moveable or interior notes of the
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
293
i ntervals and the pitches of the notes, there seem somehow to be elements
pertaining to melody that are infinite; but as regards their functions and
their species and their positions, they are both limited and prescribed.
The domain of music is “illimité.”100 As Aristoxenus explained, it is
potentially infinite in both directions. – in magnitudinem and in parvitatem.
To deal with the infiniteness of music’s domain, Aristoxenus focused on
the process that generates it: the infinite divisibility of musical intervals.
He began by accepting the infinity of the melodic topos as a given, and
agreed to “let it be.” His doing so was an admission that any well-attuned
synthesis of the melodic topos by the geometric method of canonic science would be an impossibility, for such a synthesis could never succeed in
accommodating all of the forms and genera of melody, this owing to the
infinite divisibility of the melodic topos. At the same time, he intuited that
even though the melodic topos was in itself illimitable, there was at any
given moment in song some finite segment of it that could be represented
to the ear’s satisfaction. He found such finite segments to be dependent on
the unchanging tonal functions that are productive of the various genera
and species of melody. But when it came to expressing these finite segments by traditional geometric means, he ran head-long into the mathematical problems described earlier as a discontinuity between rational
numbers.101
The geometric method, as Ptolemaïs of Cyrene realized, belongs to a
domain utterly different from that of music: the domain of vision. This
method, as practiced by the canonicians and handed down through succeeding centuries, was strictly metrical and became the official norm for
all artistic endeavors. It was not until the Renaissance that artists were
urged to reinvent metrical geometry if they hoped to represent what
they intuited to be true of the domain of vision: an infinite vanishing
tetrachord – with the mathematical infinity of musical space. His motivation
in this effort was to ensure that the resulting melodic segments of his divisions
each had its own proper terminus.
100 Cf. Chapter 5, note 53.
101 To escape the contradiction between the empirical data of melody and discontinuity within the canonic ratios, Aristoxenus was led to create what he intuited
to be true: a continuum in which every note takes its place just as in a series of
integers or units.
294
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
point in three-dimensional space. To accommodate this phenomenon,
artists had to invent a perspective geometry so as somehow to produce
a “there” – a there that would impress the eye as an acceptable relation
between objects.102 In other words, artists had to create the unbroken
continuity of different visual fields within the fixed limits of the canvas’
finite dimensions. They had in effect to project themselves straight
through the canvas into infinity. The geometric proportions between
objects had, therefore, to be their principal concern. But such proportions would be impossible to achieve without a fixed unit of measure.
The one most commonly used was the square.103 Whatever the unit of
measure and however complex the perspective methods employed, artists know for a certainty that in the end all paintings are a compromise
with what the eye actually sees.
Aristoxenus recognized and accepted the same thing where the
melodic topos was concerned. All attunements are a compromise with
what the ear actually hears: a continuum of musical sound that escapes all
traditional geometric representation. His solution was as ingenious as
that of the Renaissance artists; he invented an arithmetic method that
would reflect as nearly as possible the continuity of the melodic topos.
It was a system of elements whereby one could pass from any one species of melody to another, from any one genus to another, and from any
one tonos to another. It evolved from Aristoxenus’ unique manipulation
of the quantum, or unit of measure, to create a series of consecutive
elements such that one was the equal of every other.104
102 This
sort of relation has been most aptly characterized by J. V. Field, The
Invention of Infinity, p. 59 as “visually right and mathematically wrong.”
103 See Field (note 102), pp. 192–94 on the method of Girard Desargues, especially p. 194, Fig. 8.14.
104 This made it possible for all the modulations to occur that are mentioned by
such Aristoxenians as Cleonides Introduction to Harmonics 13 (Jan. 204. 19–206,
18); by genus, by system, by key, by melodic composition; Bacchius Introduction
to the Art of Music I. 50 (Jan. 304. 6ff.); by system, by genus, by mode (tropos),
by ethos, by rhythm, by tempo, by rhythmic position; Aristides Quintilianus
De mus. I. 11 (Winnington-Ingram, 22. 11ff.). See Barker, II, p. 424, n. 126;
Mathiesen, Aristides, pp. 88–92.
Aisthēsis and Logos: A Single Continent
295
Thus, where painters have had to create by geometric means the
infiniteness of perspective within the limits of a canvas’ finite dimensions, Aristoxenus was led by his calculations of fixed units of measure
to create the finite forms of melody from the infiniteness of the melodic
topos. The forms (eidē) with reference to which he created his attunement
belong to melody; for melody, like a soul which gives form to a body, is
the end (telos) of all attunement.
8 The Infinite and the Infinitesimal
The phenomena of melody
seem to be infinite with respect
to the sizes of musical intervals
and the pitches of musical notes;
but as to their functions, forms,
and positions, they are finite and prescribed.
Aristoxenus, Harm. El. III. 69
In all that pertains to the science of melody, Aristoxenus was
a man per se, a man who stood very much alone. As a musician, he was
an avowed conservative, ever at war with any kind of innovation that he
thought of as violating the ancient forms of the musical art. He speaks,
for example, of two ancient styles (tropoi) which he regarded as especially
beautiful, styles which his contemporaries were, in his eyes, either too
ignorant to appreciate, or too avid in their pursuit of a chromatic kind
of sweetness even to remember. But these ancient styles had to be preserved at any cost, as he saw it, with all their ethical distinctions intact.1
He seems, in fact, to have accepted the Damonian-Platonic view that
these distinctions were ethical in nature, inasmuch as they appeared to
1
Harm. El. I. 23 (Da Rios, 29. 17–30. 5). Cf. Barker, II, p. 141, n. 90, who sees
this passage as referring to “styles of music current before the middle of the fifth
century.” These ancient styles were evidently of the Enharmonic genus and its
precursor, the spondeion of Olympos. Both are distinctive for the prominence that
they give to the ditone, or major third.
296
The Infinite and the Infinitesimal
297
have a decided effect upon the listener.2 The problem for Aristoxenus, as
stated above, was to provide an affinity (oikeiotēs)3 between all the ancient
styles of melody (tropoi), all the pitch ranges of the voice and instruments
(tonoi), and all the scales and genera (systēmata and genē) of theory, such
that modulations (metabolai) from one style, key, and genus to another
could be easily effected. There was one proviso, however: such modulations would be acceptable only if they did not disturb or compromise the
characteristic forms of the individual melodic modes, or tropoi.
Aristoxenus could not but accept the Pythagorean proofs of the consonantal magnitudes, for these proofs defined to a certainty the limits
of the consonances: fourth, fifth, and octave. They also demonstrated
that the whole-tone is the excess of the fifth over the fourth. The mathematical laws that followed necessarily from these geometrically defined
magnitudes also showed incontrovertibly that six whole-tones cannot
be made to fit mathematically into the space of an octave, there being
always something left over; that the superparticular ratios defining the
fourth and the fifth are themselves mathematically indivisible; consequently, that the octave, music’s most perfect consonance, is in fact
incommensurable with its own constituents.4 These facts yielded wonderfully fruitful mathematical concepts in the form of arithmetic classes.
There is, for example, one such class the squares of whose numbers are
all smaller than 2; and another such class the squares of whose numbers
are greater than 2. But in neither class can a number be found whose
square is equal to 2. All these abstract formulations flow from the number √2, that number which emerges on the mathematical division of
2
3
4
Aristoxenus’ most telling reference to the ethical theory is in Harm. El. II. 31 (Da
Rios, 40. 13–41.2), where he refers to one type of music as hurtful to the moral
character and another type that improves it. Cf. Barker, II, p. 148, n. 6, where he
says that it is not certain to what extent Aristoxenus endorsed the ethical theory,
“but the present passage shows that he did not reject [it] altogether.”
Harm. El. I. 7 (Da Rios, 12. 8–12). The question of affinity is one of great
importance and has been vigorously debated by scholars for decades. See, for
example, Barker, II, p. 131, n. 34. As he explains, the tonoi, or keys, do not
themselves incorporate differing arrangements of notes and intervals, but are
identical interval sequences at different relative pitches.
See Chapter 4.
298
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
the whole-tone. But all such mathematical repartitions had no relevance
for Aristoxenus when it came to his perception of musical space.
For Aristoxenus, musical space was homogeneous and isotropic
in that the melodic movement produced in one pitch range could be
reproduced in another pitch range without any variation of its properties. Moreover, this movement, once produced, could be repeated again
and again, so long as the voice or instrument could conduct it within
its own inherent limitations. The case has been stated by Helmholtz in
much the same terms as those of Aristoxenus:5
Every melodic phrase, every chord, which can be executed at any pitch,
can also be executed at any other pitch in such a way that we immediately
perceive the characteristic marks of their similarity. . . . Such a close analogy
consequently exists in all essential relations between the musical scale and
space, that even alteration of pitch has a readily recognized and unmistakable resemblance to motion in space.
This meant that there was a genuine affinity, or as Helmholtz has it, a
close analogy, between scales, keys, and modes. The goal of Aristoxenus’
system was to maintain this affinity between the scales of abstract pitch
and their mode-bearing segments, so that these segments, or octavespecies, could be reproduced in any pitch range without any variation
in their distinctive properties. For musicians, the immediate practical
result of this endeavor would be the possibility of modulating from one
mode or scale to another, and the ability to transpose one melody in one
pitch range to the same melody in another pitch range. But to make for
these possibilities, there would have to be an affinity, or close analogy,
between the scales and musical space
Aristoxenus’ predecessors had recognized the need to deal with the
affinity between scales, keys, and modes, but their efforts were judged by
Aristoxenus to be wholly inadequate. This, he argued, was because they
had no fundamental principle in place to back up their constructions.
If they managed to touch on the subject at all, what they produced was
purely accidental and not scientifically verifiable. Ironically enough,
5
On the Sensations of Tone, p. 370. Unfortunately, Aristoxenus’ own systematic
treatment of the connection between the tonoi (keys) and systēmata (scales) has
not survived. CF. Barker, II, p. 126, n. 3.
The Infinite and the Infinitesimal
299
the charges leveled by Aristoxenus against his predecessors’ work, and
the reasons for them, are identical to those leveled against Aristoxenus
himself by his modern critics. His theory is judged to be unscientific
primarily because it lacks mathematical rigor. Yet Aristoxenus accomplished what no one had ever succeeded in doing before him: he found
a way of measuring the rough data of aural sensation. He proposed as
a firm ground for his type of measure a system of elements such that
each could not be distinguished from its predecessor. It would be a linear series that allowed the passage from any one of the elements to any
other. It was a continuum of one dimension.
In Aristoxenus’ science of melody, a vital distinction is made between
numbers for counting and numbers for measuring. It is a distinction that, for
all its apparent simplicity, is, in reality, one of the most profound responses
of the human mind to the universe and all its attributes. It is the distinction that separates Aristoxenus’ theory from that of the Pythagoreans. For
the concepts with which Aristoxenus deals are limits and continuity, or, as
mathematicians have it, the infinite and the infinitesimal. These notions
go back to Zeno, who insisted that the motion of an arrow is really impossible, if at any given moment in time the arrow must be at some instant,
and that at such an instant there cannot be any motion. The same case can
be made, as Aristoxenus in fact does, with the singing voice. For at any
given instant, the voice appears to the ear to have stopped on a point of
pitch; if the voice moves at all, it does so between pitches by increments.
The incremental quantity that Aristoxenus selected for his working measure was what he called amelodētos, the number 1/2.6 He had to invent a
term for that number, as there was no word in the language to describe it:
a measuring number. To Ptolemy, as noted earlier,7 this number seemed
to be nothing more than a ghostly wraith, neither finite nor actual, in any
sense of the word. Yet, with this number in place, Aristoxenus could travel
in his musical imagination from one note to any other, from lichanos Meson
(F), say, to mesē (A), passing easily over the whole infinitude of possible
pitches lying between them. It is this idea of connectedness that informed
Aristoxenus’ concept of continuity and limit, making it possible for him
to construct a homogeneous and regularly linked system of tonalities that
offered all the possibilities for modulation.
6
7
See Chapter 5.
See Chapter 6.
300
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
Aristoxenus’ method is a pragmatic one for solving the most difficult
of musical problems: how to accommodate the individual modes, each
with its own local characteristics, into a musical topos afflicted with its own
mathematical incommensurability. For, mathematically speaking, a contradiction seemed to emerge from the heart of the musical universe, even
though the elements of music appeared to Aristoxenus to move in one
concordant and ordered society. The Pythagoreans had long since known
of the problem and tried to resolve it by forcing musical space to conform
to the laws of mathematics. Aristoxenus’ achievement was to bring musical space into correlation with what the ear perceives to be true: the space
through which melody moves is as symmetrical as time itself appears to
be. Like a modern savant, Aristoxenus saw that the problem with musical
space was comparable to that of terrestrial time. For time, through which
the seasons move with unchanging regularity, is afflicted with the same
sort of incommensurability as is musical space: no convenient whole number of lunar months can be made to fit into one solar year. That the earth’s
diurnal rotations do not synchronize with its revolutions around the sun is
not apparent to the senses, however; it is only when the intellectual faculty
attempts to make lunar calendars that the discrepancy is revealed.
Accordingly, in contemplating music, which exemplified to him a
miraculous order of events, Aristoxenus saw in its actual practice the
same chaos and confusion that were afflicting the reckoning of time in
fourth-century Greece, and the harmonicians were, in his estimation,
doing nothing to alleviate the problem. As he says:8
The harmonicians’ rendering of the tonalities is exactly like the observance of
the days of the month; as, for example, when the Corinthians observe one day
as the tenth of the month, while the Athenians reckon it as the fifth, and others
construe it as the eighth. Thus, some of the harmonicians say that the lowest of
the tonalities is the Hypodorian, that a semi-tone above it is the Mixolydian,
that a semi-tone above this is the Dorian, that a whole-tone above the Dorian is
8
Harm. El. II. 37 (Da Rios, 46. 20–47. 6). As Gevaert, I. p. 250, observed, the
absence of unity and the rampant individualism on the part of the various musical masters and schools of music were characteristic of the whole pre-Aristoxenian
era. As he put it: “Around the epoch of Alexander, the theory and nomenclature
of the keys are found in an indescribable disorder. All the authorities had in matters of this sort a different practice; some admitted only five keys, others went up
to six; as for a practice universally followed, it simply did not exist.”
The Infinite and the Infinitesimal
301
the Phrygian, and that the Lydian lies another whole-tone above the Phrygian.
Others add to the aforementioned tonalities the Hypophrygian aulos tonality
at the bass. Still others, basing their method on the boring of auloi, separate the
three lowest tonalities – the Hypophrygian, the Hypodorian, and the Dorian –
by three quarter-tones from one another. And they set the Phrygian at a distance from the Dorian by a whole-tone and the Lydian from the Phrygian again
at three quarter-tones, as they do the Mixolydian from the Lydian.
Aristoxenus concludes by observing of the authors of these systems:9
“But what is the principle they are looking at that makes them so willing to
distribute the tonalities in this way? Of this, they have nothing to say.”
Unfortunately, Aristoxenus’ own system has not come down to us.
What we have instead is that of Cleonides, who cites Aristoxenus as his
authority. According to Cleonides, Aristoxenus set up a system of thirteen tonoi, or scales of transposition, whose distribution over musical
space is not unlike that of the fifteen keys in use today. Each is separated
from the next by a semitone. Taking the note mesē as a basis for comparison, the thirteen tonalities, each being a paradigmatic scale, or System
Ametabolon, transposed a semitone down, appear as follows:10
Hypermixolydian
Hyperionian or higher Mixolydian
Hyperdorian or lower Mixolydian
Higher Lydian
Aeolian or lower Lydian
Higher Phrygian
Ionian or lower Phrygian
Dorian
Higher Hypolydian
Hypoaeolian or lower Hypolydian
Higher Hypophrygian
Hypoionian or lower Hypophrygian
Hypodorian
9
10
Harm. El. II. 38 (Da Rios, 47. 13–15).
Cleonides, Isag. Harm. 12 (Jan, 203–4).
Mesē
F
E
Eb
D
C#
C
B
Bb
A
G#
G
F#
F1
302
Greek Reflections on the Nature of Music
The framework into which Aristoxenus made everything fit is one
of his own construction; but he did not construct it at random. He
constructed by measurement, and that is why he was able to fit the
facts – the modal facts – into his framework without altering their
essential characteristics. Ultimately, it is the doctrine of limits that
underlies Aristoxenus’ harmonic structure, and not any conscious
use on his part of the infinitesimal. This is to say that Aristoxenus’
amelōdētos, his 12
–1 of a whole-tone, involves neither the infinite nor
the infinitesimal; for it is itself not a sum, but simply and strictly, the
limit of a sum. As Aristoxenus intuited, an octave, a fifth, and a fourth
are relatively finite pairs, though all three consist of terms which are
absolutely infinite.
The Pythagoreans had demonstrated that melody, like all natural
processes, betrays a fundamental discontinuity when its elements can be
measured with mathematical precision.11 But Aristoxenus, to his credit,
restored melody to its primordial character – continuity of motion – by
creating a new convention of measurement that conforms to melody’s condition of symmetry. To accommodate this symmetry, Aristoxenus adopted
the concept of melodic space or topos, a space inhabited by homogeneous
objects – notes, consonances, dissonances, functions, and species. Between
these objects he established spatial relations – continuity and intervallic
distances. He abstracted from the properties of these objects only those
that are determined by their spacelike relationships. These relationships
define what Aristoxenus conceived of as his Science of Melody.
11
Time, the paradigm of all natural processes; time “the moving image of eternity,” is converted by music into a continual present. The seamless “now”
which music inhabits, does not exist in its own right, but is an amazing characteristic of music. And space, the infinite progenitor of the universe, has no
boundaries between the notes of music. A paradigm of infinity, music draws
its power from the space it fashions for itself. Music thus astonishes nature: for
what is otherwise inscrutable and ineffable, escapes through the mediation of
music into the sphere of human existence and becomes the wonder-provoking
phenomena that Aristoxenus so vigorously managed to describe.
Bibliography
Abert, H., Die Lehre vom Ethos in der griechischen Musik. Ein Beitrag zur
Musikästhetik des Klassischen Altertums. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel
1899; repr. Wiesbaden: Hans Schneider Tutzing 1968.
Anderson, W., Ethos and Eduction in Greek Music. The Evidence of Poetry and
Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1966.
——— Music and Musicians in Ancient Greece. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press 1994.
Ansermet, E., Die Grundlagen der Musik in menschlichen Bewusstsein. Munich:
Piper 1985.
Arnoux, G., Musique Platonicienne: Ame du Monde. Paris: Dervy-Livres
1960.
Balme, D. M., “Genos and Eidos in Aristotle’s Biology,” CQ n.s. xii (1962),
81–92.
Barbera, A., “Octave Species,” Journal of Musicology 3 (1984), 229–41.
——— “Placing Sectio Canonis in Historical and Philosophical Contexts,”
JHS 104 (1984), 157–61.
——— “Greece,” New Harvard Dictionary of Music, ed. D. M. Randel,
346–51. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press 1986.
——— Ed., Music Theory and its Sources: Antiquity and the Middle Ages.
Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press 1990.
——— The Euclidean Division of the Canon. Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press 1991.
——— “Music and Perception: A Study in Aristoxenus,” JHS xcviii
(1978), 9–16.
——— “`OI KALOYMENOI `ARMONIKOI: The Predecessors of
Aristoxenus,” PCPS n.s. xxiv (1978), 1–21.
——— “SUMFWNOI `APMONIKOI: A Note on Republic 531C1–4,” CPh.
73 (1978), 337–42.
305
306
Bibliography
——— “Methods and Aims in the Euclidean Sectio Canonis,” JHS 101
(1981), 1–16.
——— “Aristides Quintilianus and Constructions in Early Music Theory,”
C.Q. n.s. 32 (1982), 184–97.
——— “Aristoxenus’ Theorems and the Foundations of Harmonic
Science,” Ancient Philosophy 4 (1984), 23–64.
——— Greek Musical Writings: I. The Musician and his Art. Cambridge
University Press 1984.
——— Greek Musical Writings: II. Harmonic and Acoustic Theory. Cambridge
University Press 1989.
——— Scientific Method in Ptolemy’s “Harmonics.” Cambridge University
Press 2000.
Barrow, J. D., Pi in the Sky. Counting, Thinking, and Being. Oxford: Clarendon
1992.
Beckmann, P., A History of Π (PI). New York: The Galen Press 1971.
Bélis, A., Aristoxène et Aristote: le Traité d’Harmonique. Paris: Klincksieck,
Études et Commentaires vol. 100. 1986.
Bevan, E. R., The House of Ptolemy: A History of Egypt under the Ptolemaic
Dynasty. Chicago: Ares Publishers 1968.
Blum, D., Casals and the Art of Interpretation. London: Heinemann 1977.
Bowman, A. C., “The Foundations of Early Pythagorean Science; Archytas,
Fragment I,” Ancient Philosophy 2 (1982), 79–104.
Bowman, W. D., Philosophical Perspectives on Music. New York: Oxford
University Press 1998.
Brumbaugh, R. S., Plato’s Mathematical Imagination. The Mathematical
Passages in the Dialogues and their Interpretation. Bloomington: The Indiana
University Press 1954.
Burkert W., Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, trans. E. L. Minar Jr.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard 1972.
Caspar, M., Ioannis Kepleri Harmonices Mundi Libri V, Vol. VI; Johannes
Kepler, Gesammelte Werke, ed. W. von Dyck and M. Caspar. Munich: Beck
1940.
Casson, L., Libraries in the Ancient World. New Haven: Yale University Press
2001.
Chaignet, E., Pythagore et la philosophie pythagoricienne. Paris: F. Vieweg
1873.
Chailley, J., La musique grecque antique. Paris: Les Belles Lettres 1979.
Cherniss, H., Aristotle’s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy. Baltimore: The
Johns Hopkins Press 1935; repr. New York: Octagon Books 1964.
Bibliography
307
Clements, E., “The Interpretation of Greek Music,” JHS 42 (1922),
133–66.
Coates, K., Geometry, Proportion and the Art of Lutherie. Oxford: Clarendon
1985.
Comotti, G., Music in Greek and Roman Culture. Trans. Rosaria V. Munson.
Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press 1989.
Cook, A., Myth and Language. Bloomington: Indiana University Press
1980.
——— The Stance of Plato. Lanham, MD: Bowman & Littlefield 1996.
Cook, N., Music, Imagination, and Culture. New York: Oxford University
Press 1990.
Cooke, D., The Language of Music. New York: Oxford University Press
1959.
Cornford, F. M., The Republic of Plato. London: Oxford University Press
1941.
——— Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Educational
Publishing 1957.
——— The Republic of Plato. New York: Oxford University Press 1970.
Cousin, V., Opera Patri Abaelardi. 2 vols. Paris: Pottier de la Laine
1849–59.
Da Rios, R., Aristoxeni Elementa Harmonica. Romae: typis publicae officinae
polygraphicae 1954.
Delatte, A., Études sur la Littérature Pythagoricienne. Paris: Edouard Champion
1915; rep. Genève: Slatkine 1974.
Derbyshire, J., Prime Obsession: Bernhard Riemann and the Greatest Unsolved
Problem in Mathematics. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press 2003
Deubner, L., Iamblichi De Vita Pythagorica Liber. Leipzig: Teubner 1937.
Dicks, D. R., Early Greek Astronomy to Aristotle. Bristol: Thames and
Hudson 1970.
Diels, H. and Kranz, W., Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Dublin/Zürich:
Weidmann 1966.
Dijksterhuis, E. J., Archimedes. Princeton: Princeton University Press
1987.
D’Ooge, M. L., Nicomachus of Gerasa. Introduction to Arithmetic. With Studies
in Greek Arithmetic by F. E. Robbins and L. C. Karpinsky. New York
and London: Macmillan 1926.
Duhem, P., To Save the Phenomena. An Essay on the Idea of Physical Theory from
Plato to Galileo. Trans. E. Doland and Ch. Meschler. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press 1969.
308
Bibliography
Düring, I., Die Harmonielehre des Klaudios Ptolemaios. Götesborgs Högskolas
Ärsskrift, vol. 36, no. 1. Göteborg: Elanders 1930; repr. New York:
Garland 1980.
——— Porphyrios Kommentar zur Harmonielehre des Ptolemaios. Götesborgs
Högskolas Ärsskrift, vol. 38, no. 2. Göteborg: Elanders 1932; repr.
New York: Garland 1980.
——— Ptolemaios und Porphyrios über die Musik. Götesborgs Högskolas
Ärsskrift, vol. 40, no. 1. Göteborg: Elanders 1934; repr. New York:
Garland 1980.
Dzielska, M., Hypatia of Alexandria. Trans. F. Lyra. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press 1995.
Fargue, Léon-Paul, Maurice Ravel. Paris: Domat 1949.
Field, J. V., Kepler’s Geometrical Cosmology. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press 1988.
——— The Invention of Infinity. New York: Oxford University Press.
Fokker, A. D., “On the Expansion of the Musician’s Realm of Harmony,”
Acta Musicologica 38 (1966), 197–202.
Fortlage, C., Das Musikalische System Der Griecheschen In Seiner Urgestalt Aus
Den Tonleitern Des Alypius. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel 1847; repr.
Amsterdam, P. Schippers N. V. 1964
Frank, E., Plato und die sogenannten Pythagoreer. Halle: M. Niemeyer 1923.
Gaca, K. L., “The Reproductive Technology of the Pythagoreans,” Cl. Ph.
95 (2000), 113–32.
Gevaert, Fr. Aug., Histoire et Théorie de la Musique de L’Antiquité, Vol. I,
1875; Vol. II, 1881 Gand: Annoot-Braeckman.
Gildersleeve, B. L., Syntax of Classical Greek from Homer to Demosthenes.
2 vols. New York: American Book Company 1900.
Godwin, J., ed., The Harmony of the Spheres. A Sourcebook of the Pythagorean
Tradition in Music. Rochester, VT: Inner Traditions 1993.
——— Cosmic Music. Musical Keys to the Interpretation of Reality. Rochester,
VT: Inner Traditions 1989.
Godwin, J., Robert Fludd. Hermetic Philosopher and Surveyor of Two Worlds.
Grand Rapids, MI: Phanes Press.
Gombosi, O. J., Tonarten und Stimmungen der Antiken Musik. Kopenhagen:
Ejnar Munksgaard 1939.
Grassi, T., “Musica, Mimica e Danza,” Studi Della Scuola Papirologica
3 (1920), 117–35.
Greene, B., The Elegant Universe. Superstrings, Hidden Dimensions, and the
Quest for the Ultimate Theory. New York: Vintage Books 2000.
Bibliography
309
Greene, M., A Portrait of Aristotle, Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press 1963.
Guthrie, W. K. C., A History of Greek Philosophy, I: The Earlier Presocratics
and the Pythagoreans. Cambridge University Press 1971.
Heath, Sir Th. L., A History of Greek Mathematics, vol. I; From Thales to Euclid;
vol. II: From Aristarchus to Diophantus. Oxford: Clarendon 1921.
——— The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 3 vols. New York: Dover
Publications 1956.
Heath, Sir Thomas, Aristarchus of Samos. The Ancient Copernicus. Oxford:
Clarendon 1913.
Heath, Sir Th. L., Greek Astronomy. London: J. M. Dent & Sons, Ltd. 1932;
repr. Dover 1991.
Heiberg, J. L., Claudii Ptolemaii Syntaxis Mathematica. 2 vols. Leipzig:
Teubner 1898–1903.
Helmholtz, H. L. F., On the Sensations of Tone as a Physiological Basis for the
Theory of Music. Trans. A. J. Ellis. New York: Dover Publications 1954.
Henderson, M. I., “The Growth of the Greek `ARMONIAI,” CQ 36 (1942),
94–103.
——— “Ancient Greek Music,” New Oxford History of Music, vol. 1, 336–
403. London: Oxford University Press 1957.
Higgins, R. A. and Winnington-Ingram, R. P., “Lute Players in Greek
Art,” JHS 85 (1965), 62–71.
Hiller, E., Theonis Smyrnae philosophi Platonici. Expositio rerum mathematicarum
ad legendum Platonem utilium. Leipzig: Teubner 1878; repr. New York:
Garland 1987.
Hindemith, P., A Composer’s World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press 1952.
Hoche, R., Nicomachi Geraseni Pythagorei Introductionis Arithmeticae Libri II.
Leipzig: Teubner 1966.
Hubbard, F., Harpsichord Regulating and Repairing. Boston: Tuner’s Supply
1963.
Huntley, H. E., The Divine Proportion. A Study in Mathematical Beauty.
New York: Dover Publications 1970.
Isacoff, S., Temperament. The Idea that Solved Music’s Greatest Riddle. New York:
Alfred A. Knopf 2001.
Jaeger, W., Paideia: the Ideals of Greek Culture. Vol. I: Archaic Greece. The
Mind of Athens. Trans. Gilbert Highet. New York: Oxford University
Press 1945.
James, Sir J., Science and Music. Cambridge University Press 1961.
310
Bibliography
James, J., The Music of the Spheres. Music, Science and the Natural Order of the
Universe. New York: Grove Press 1993.
Jeppesen, K., Counterpoint. The Polyphonic Vocal Style of the Sixteenth Century.
Trans. Glen Haydon. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall 1939.
Johnson, C. W. L., “The Motion of the Voice, Å tÁj fwnÁj kίnhsij, in the
Theory of Ancient Music,” TAPA 30 (1899), 42–55.
Jonker, G. H., The Harmonics of Manuel Bryennius. Groningen: WoltersNoordhoff Publishing 1970.
Jourdain, R., Music, the Brain, and Ecstasy: How Music Captures Our
Imagination. New York: William Morrow 1997.
Kemke, I., Philodemi De Musica Librorum Quae Exstant. Leipzig: Teubner
1884.
Kivy, Peter, Music Alone. Philosophical Reflections on the Purely Musical
Experience. Cornell University Press 1990.
Klein, J. Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. Trans.
Eva Braun. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press 1968; repr. New York: Dover
Publications 1992.
Kline, M., Mathematics in Western Culture. New York: Oxford University
Press 1953.
Kucharski, P., Étude sur la Doctrine Pythagoricienne de la Tétrade. Paris: Les
Belles Lettres 1952.
Kuhn, Th. S., The Copernican Revolution. Planetary Astronomy in the Develop
ment of Western Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1957.
Laloy, L., Aristoxène de Tarente: Disciple d’Aristote et la Musique de l’Antiquité
Paris. Société Francaise d’Imprimerie et de Librairie 1904; repr. Genève:
Minkoff 1973.
Landels, J. G., Music in Ancient Greece and Rome. London: Routledge 1999.
Langer, S. K., Philosophy in a New Key. A Study in the Symbolism of Reason,
Rite, and Art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1957.
Lasserre, F., Plutarque, de la musique: Texte, traduction, commentaìre, précédés d’une étude sur l’éducation musicale dans la Grèce antique. Olten and
Lausanne: URS Graf-Verlag 1954.
Lavine, S., Understanding the Infinite. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press 1994.
Lawlor, R. and D. Qewnos Smurnaiou, Mathematics Useful for Understanding
Plato. San Diego: Wizards Bookshelf 1979.
Levin, F. R., “The Hendecachord of Ion of Chios,” TAPA 92 (1961),
295–307.
——— “Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory,” TAPA 103 (1972), 211–34.
Bibliography
311
——— The Harmonics of Nicomachus and the Pythagorean Tradition. American
Classical Studies No. 1 University Park: The American Philological
Association 1975.
——— “πληγη and τασιζ in the Harmonika of Klaudios Ptolemaios,”
Hermes 108 (1980), 205–29.
——— “Unity in Euclid’s ‘Sectio Canonis’,” Hermes 118 (1990),
430–43.
——— The Manual of Harmonics of Nicomachus the Pythagorean. Grand
Rapids, MI: Phanes Press 1994.
——— “Aspects of Ancient Greek Music,” Alexandria 1 (1991), 251–92.
——— “Philolaus of Croton” and “Nicomachus of Gerasa” in The New
Grove Dictionary of Music II. London: Methuen 1999.
——— “Ἀπειρία in Aristoxenian Theory,” Hermes 135 (2007), 406–28.
Lippman, E. A., “Spatial Perception and Physical Location as Factors in
Music,” Acta Musicologica 35 (1963), 24–34.
——— Musical Thought in Ancient Greece. New York: Columbia University
Press 1964.
Maas, M. and Snyder, J. M., Stringed Instruments of Ancient Greece. New
Haven: Yale University Press 1989.
Maconie, R., The Concept of Music. Oxford: Clarendon 1990.
Macran, H. S., The Harmonics of Aristoxenus. Oxford: Clarendon 1902; repr.
Hildesheim: G. Olms 1974.
Macurdy, G. H., Hellenistic Queens. A Study of Woman-Power in Macedonia,
Seleucid Syria, and Ptolemaic Egypt. Chicago: Ares Publishers 1985.
Mathiesen, T. J., Aristides Quintilianus: On Music in Three Books. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
Mathiesen, Thomas J., Apollo’s Lyre. Greek Music and Music Theory in
Antiquity and the Middle Ages. University of Nebraska Press 1999.
McClain, E. G., The Pythagorean Plato. Prelude to the Song Itself. York Beach:
Nicolas-Hays 1984.
Meibom. M., Antiquae Musicae Auctores Septem Graece et Latine. 2 vols.
Amsterdam: Elsevir 1652; rep. New York: Broude Brothers 1977.
Ménage, G., Historia Mulierum Philosopharum. Lyons: 1690.
Merleau-Ponty, J. and Morando, B., The Rebirth of Cosmology. trans.
H. Weaver. Athens: Ohio University Press 1982.
Mersenne, M., Harmonie Universelle, The Books on Instruments, Paris, 1635,
trans. R. E. Chapman, The Hague 1957.
Michaelides, S., The Music of Ancient Greece: An Encyclopedia. London: Faber
and Faber 1978.
312
Bibliography
Michel, P.-H., De Pythagore à Euclide. Contribution à l’Histoire des
Mathematiques Préeuclidiénnes. Paris: “Les Belles Lettres” 1950.
Monro, D. B., The Modes of Ancient Greek Music. Oxford: Clarendon 1894.
Morgenstern, S., ed., Composers on Music. An Anthology of Composers’ Writings
from Palestrina to Copland. New York: Pantheon Books 1956.
Morris, R., Achilles in the Quantum Universe. The Definitive History of Infinity.
London: Souvenir Press 1998.
Mountford, J. F., “Greek Music and its Relation to Modern Times.” JHS
40 (1920), 13–42.
——— in The Greek Aulos, by Kathleen Schlesinger. “Introduction,”
pp. xv–xxvii.
Moutsopoulos, E., La Musique dans l’oeuvre de Platon. Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France 1959.
Najock, D., Drei anonyme griechische Traktate über die Musik. Eine Kommentierte
Neuausgabe des Bellermanschen Anonymus. Göttinger musikwissenschaftliche Arbeiten, vol. 2. Kassel: Bärenreiter 1972.
Neubecker, A. J., Die Bewertung der Musik bei Stoikern und Epicurean. Berlin:
Akademie-Verlag 1956.
——— Über Die Musik IV. Buch. Text, Übersetzung und Kommentar. Napoli:
Istituto Italiano Per Gli Studi Filosofici 1986.
Neugebauer, O., The Exact Sciences in Antiquity. Providence, RI: Brown
University Press 1957.
Newton, I., Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophia. Trans. A. Motte;
rev. F. Cajori. Berkeley and Los Angeles: 1974.
Nietsche, F. The Birth of Tragedy in the Philosophy of Nietsche. New York: The
Modern Library n.d.
Norton, R. Tonality in Western Culture. A Critical and Historical Perspective.
University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press 1984.
O’Meara, D. J., Pythagoras Revived. Mathematics and Philosophy in Late
Antiquity. Oxford: Clarendon 1989.
Owen, George E., The Universe of the Mind. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins
Press 1971.
Pearson, L., Aristoxenus. Elementa Rhythmica. The Fragment of Book II and the
Additional Evidence for Aristoxenian Rhythmic Theory. Oxford: Clarendon
1990.
Philip, J. A., Pythagoras and Early Pythagoreanism. University of Toronto
Press 1966.
Pine-Coffin, R. S., Saint Augustine Confessions. Baltimore: Penguin Books
1961.
Bibliography
313
Pistelli, H., Iamblichus. In Nichomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem Liber.
Stuttgart: Teubner 1975.
Piston, W., Harmony. New York: W. W. Norton 1941.
Pöhlmann, Egert, Denkmäler altgriechischer Musik. Nürnberg: Hans Carl
1970.
Pöhlmann, E., and West, M. L., Documents of Ancient Greek Music. Oxford:
Clarendon 2001.
Poincaré, H., Science and Hypothesis: New York: Dover Publications 1952.
Pomeroy, S. B., “Technikai kai Mousikai: The Eduction of Women in
the Fourth Century and in the Hellenistic Period,” AJAH 2 (1977),
51–68.
——— Goddesses, Whores, Wives, and Slaves. Women in Classical Antiquity.
New York: Schocken Books 1975.
——— Women in Hellenistic Egypt from Alexander to Cleopatra. Detroit, MI:
Wayne State University Press 1984.
Proust, M., Remembrance of Things Past, 2 vols., trans. C. K. Scott Moncrief.
New York: Random House 1934.
Raffman, D., Language, Music, and Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
1993.
Redfield, John., Music: A Science and an Art. New York: Alfred A. Knopf
1930.
Reinach, Th., La Musique Grecque. Paris: Payot 1926.
Richter, Lukas., Zur wissenschaftslehre von der Musik bei Platon und Aristoteles.
Berlin: Akademie-Verlag 1961.
Richter, L., Momente der Musikgeschichte Antike und Byzanz. Salzburg: Verlag
Mueller-Speiser 2000.
Riley, M., “Theoretical and Practical Astrology: Ptolemy and His
Colleagues,” TAPA 117 (1987), 235–56.
Robbins, F. E., Ptolemy. Tetrabiblos. The Loeb Collection Library. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press 1940.
Ross, W. D., ARISTOTEΛΟΥΣ FUSIKH AKΡOASIS. Aristotle’s Physics.
Oxford: Clarendon 1936; repr. 1960.
Ross, Sir D., Aristotle. London: Methuen 1923.
Rothstein, E., Emblems of the Mind. The Inner Life of Music and Mathematics.
New York: Random House 1995.
Ruelle, Ch.-E., Traductions de traités musicaux, 6 vol. Paris: Collection des
auteurs grecs relatif à la musique 1871–1898.
Ruelle, Ch.-E., “La Monocorde, Instrument de Musique,” REG 10 (1897),
309–12.
314
Bibliography
Russell, B., Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. New York: Macmillan
1919.
——— Principles of Mathematics. New York: W. W. Norton 1902.
——— A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon and Schuster
1945.
Sacks, Oliver, Musicophilia, Tales of Music and the Brain. New York: Alfred
Knopf 2007.
Sautoy, M. du, The Music of the Primes. New York: HarperCollins 2003.
Schlesinger, K., The Greek Aulos: A Study of Its Mechanism and of its Relation
to the Modal System of Ancient Greek Music. London: Methuen 1939; repr.
Groningen: Bouma’s Boekhuis 1970.
Schoenberg, A., Theory of Harmony. trans. Roy E. Carter. London: Faber and
Faber 1978.
Schopenhauer, A., The World as Will and Representation. Trans. E. F. J. Payne.
Vol. I. New York: Dover Publications 1959.
Scruton, R., The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press
1997.
Seashore, Carl E., Psychology of Music. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1938; repr.
Dover 1967.
Sloboda, J. A., The Musical Mind. The Cognitive Psychology of Music. Oxford:
Clarendon 1985.
Solomon, J., “The Diastaltic Ethos,” CPh 76 (1981), 93–100.
——— “Cleonides: EISAGOGE HARMONIKE: Critical Edition,
Translation, and Commentary.” Ph.D. dis., University of North Carolina:
Chapel Hill, 1980.
——— “The Seikilos Inscription: A Theoretical Analysis,” AJPh 107
(1986), 455–79.
Solomon, Jon, “EKBOLE and EKLUSIS in the Musical Treatise of Bacchius,”
Symbolae Osloensis 55 (1980), 111–26.
Solomon, J., Ptolemy “Harmonics”: Translation and Commentary. Leiden: Brill
2000.
Sorabji, R., Time, Creation and the Continuum. Theories in Antiquity and the
Early Middle Ages. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press 1983.
Spitzer, L., Classical and Christian Ideas of World Harmony. Prolegomena to
an Interpretation of the Word “Stimmung.” Ed. Anna Granville Hatcher.
Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press 1963.
Stahl, W. H., with Johnson, R. and Burge, E. L., Martianus Capella and
the Seven Liberal Arts. Records of Civilization: Sources and Studies, no. 84.
New York: Columbia University Press 1971–77.
Bibliography
315
Stanford, W. B., The Sound of Greek: Studies in the Greek Theory and Practice
of Euphony, Sather Classical Lectures, vol. 38. University of California
Press 1966.
Steinmayer, O., “Bacchius Geron’s Introduction to the Art of Music,” Journal
of Music Theory 29 (1985), 271–98.
Stephenson, B., The Music of the Heavens. Kepler’s Harmonic Astronomy.
Princeton University Press 1994.
Stravinsky, I., An Autobiography. New York: Simon and Schuster 1936.
Strunk, O., Source Readings in Music History: Antiquity and the Middle Ages.
New York: W. W. Norton 1965.
Tannery, P., “Inauthenticité de la ‘Division du Canon’ attribuée à Euclide,”
Memoires scientifiques III (1915), 213–19.
——— Quadrivium de Georges Pachymere ou = Syntagma ton tessaron mathmaton
arithmetikes, mousikes, yeometrias kai astronomias, rev. R. P. E. Stephanou.
A. A. Studi e Testi, vol. 94. Vatican City: Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana
1940.
Tarn, W. W., Hellenistic Civilization. Cleveland and New York: The World
Publishing Company 1952.
——— Antigonas Gonatas. Oxford: Clarendon 1913.
——— “Queen Ptolemais and Apama,” CQ 23 (1929), 138–41.
Taub, L. C., Ptolemy’s Universe. The Natural Philosophical and Ethical
Foundations of Ptolemy’s Astronomy. Chicago: Open Court 1993.
Taylor, A. E., A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus. Oxford: Clarendon 1928.
Thesleff, H., An Introduction to the Pythagorean Writings of the Hellensitic
Period. Äbo: Äbo Akademi 1961.
——— The Pythagorean Texts of the Hellenistic Period. Äbo: Äbo Akademi
1965.
Tillyard, H. J. W., “Inscriptions: Laconia, Geraki,” BSA 11 (1904–5),
111–12.
Tillyard, H. J. W. and Wace, A. J. B., “The History of Demetrius the Fair,”
BSA 11 (1904–05), 113–19.
Van der Waerden, B. L., Science Awakening I. Egyptian, Babylonian, and Greek
Mathematics. Trans. A. Dresden. Dordrecht: Noordhoff International
Publishing 1975.
——— “Die Harmonielehre der Pythagoreer,” Hermes 78 (1943), 163–99.
Vincent, A. J. H., “Notice sur divers manuscritsgrecs relatifs à la musique,
comprenant une traduction française et des commentaires,” Notice
et extraits des manuscrits de la bibliotèque du Roi et autres biblioteches,
vol. XVI, 2. Paris: Imprimerie royale 1847.
316
Bibliography
Wachsmuth, T. C. and Hense, O., Stobaei Eclogae vols. I–III. Leipzig:
Teubner 1884.
Wallis, Ch. G., The Harmonies of the World by Johannes Kepler. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press 1952.
Wasserstein, A., “Theaetetus and the History of the Theory of Numbers,”
CQ n.s. 8 (1958), 165–77.
Watts, W., Augustine. Confessions. 2 vols. The Loeb Classical Library.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1912; repr. 1997.
Wehrli, F., “Aristoxenos,” Die Schule des Aristoteles. Basle: Benno Schwabe
1945.
Werner, E., The Sacred Bridge. The Interdependence of Liturgy and Music in
Synagogue and Church during the First Millenium. New York: Columbia
University Press 1959.
West, M. L., Ancient Greek Music. Oxford: Clarendon 1992.
White, M. J., The Continuous and the Discrete. Ancient Physical Theories from a
Contemporary Perspective. Oxford: Clarendon 1992.
Wilkinson, L. P., “Philodemus on Ethos in Music,” CQ 32 (1938),
174–81.
Williams, C. F. Abdy, The Story of Notation. New York: Haskell House
Publishers 1969 (repr. of 1903 ed.).
Willis, J. Martianus Capella. Leipzig: Teubner 1983.
Wilson, A. M., The Infinite in the Finite. New York: Oxford University Press
1995.
Winnington-Ingram, R. P., “Aristoxenus and the Intervals of Greek Music,”
CQ 26 (1932), 195–208.
——— Mode in Ancient Greek Music. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press 1936.
Wittgenstein, L., Notebooks, 1914–1916, ed. G. H. von Wright and G. E. M.
Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell 1961.
Wood, A., The Physics of Music, rev. J. M. Bowsher. London: Chapman and
Hall 1975.
Zeidler, B. H., The History of Woman Philosophers. Lanham, MD: University
Press of America 1984.
Ziegler, K. and Pohlenz, M., Plutarchi Moralia, vol. vi. Fasc. 3. Leipzig:
Teubner 1953.
Zuckerkandl, V., Sound and Symbol. Music and the External World; trans.
W. R. Trask. Bollingen Series xliv. Princeton University Press 1956.
Index
Abelard, Peter, 69
absolute pitch, xiv–xv
Academy, 97, 123
acoustic theory, xvi, 173
Aristoxenus and, 82n85, 180n64 (see
also Aristoxenus)
canonic ratios and, 148n34 (see also
canonic ratios)
Cooke and, 41
decad and, 7–8
Didymus and, 228
Euclid and, 129
Harmonic Series and, 286n86
Helmholtz and, 200
Hindemuth and, 279
Lasus of Hermione and, 189
motion and, 13n26 (see also motion)
Philodemus and, 38
Ptolemy and, 142n24
Pythagoras and, 65, 81, 152, 206, 215
tetratkys and, 7–8
acroamatic discourses, 98
aesthetics
Aristoxenus and, 50 (see also
Aristoxenus)
cosmology and, 155–69
intellectual knowledge and, 39–41,
46
perfection and, 14–16, 39–40, 75,
155n2, 159, 162, 201n106, 251
Philodemus and, 33–39
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene and, 231–32
subjective/objective duality and,
27–28, 33–39
topos of melody and, 169–203
Aesthetics of Music, The (Scruton), 88n1
Agenor of Mitylene, 86
aisthēsis vs. logos debate
advanced knowledge of pitch and, 250
Aristoxenus and, 242–53, 260–66,
270–74, 278–95
attunement and, 264, 283
consonance and, 277
continuum and, 244–47, 259n41,
286–88, 292
dianoia and, 281–83, 285, 288, 290
Didymus and, 262–63
dissonance and, 276–77, 280
dynamis and, 280–81
human ear and, 242–66, 270–74,
278–95
irrationality and, 263
judgment of performer and, 251–52
modulation and, 288n89
monitoring of perception and, 250–53
octaves and, 268–69
317
318
aisthēsis vs. logos debate (cont.)
Phrygian scale and, 265n53, 268n58
Porphyry and, 253–62, 272–73, 276
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene and, 253, 255–58,
261–63, 272–82, 290–93
Ptolemy and, 247–54, 257, 260,
264–72
Pythagoras and, 242–44, 267–71, 274,
279–80, 283–85
semitones and, 246–47
simulacra and, 271
straightness and, 274–75
superparticulars and, 280
synthetos and, 246–47
topos and, 270–71, 285–86, 293–95
whole-tone and, 246–47, 264,
284–85
Alcman, 92–93
Alexander of Aphrodisias, 63
Alexander the Great, 91
Allen, Diane, xii
Alypius, 55n14
anatomy, 11
Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, 187
Anderson, Warren, 75–76
André de Crète, 10
anima, De (Aristotle), x,
Anonymus (Bellermann), 61
Ansermet, Ernest, 83–84
Antigonos II Gonatas, 233–34, 236
Antiochos I, 234
Antiphanes, 93n7
Antiphon, 90n3
Antony, 233n58
Apama, 234–37
“Apeiria in Aristoxenian Theory” (Levin),
xviin8
Apollo, 97, 232
Apollo’s Lyre (Mathesien), 54nn10, 11
Archimedes, 146
Index
approximation methods and, 89–90,
201, 208, 225
influence of in geometry, 63–64
multiplicities and, 197
Pi and, 89–90
transcendental numbers and, 200
Archytas, 86
Aristoxenus and, 71–72, 74, 91–92,
267, 283
canonical ratios and, 214–15, 216n26,
222–23
Harmonic Series and, 286n10
irrationality and, 180
pitch speed and, 124
Aristarchus, 15
Aristides Quintilianus, xvn6, 56–58, 60,
148n34, 209, 212
Aristodama, 230n50
Aristophanes, 93n7
Aristotle, x, xvii, 48, 58n22, 81, 88n1
acroamatic discourses of, 98
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 274
death of, 91n4, 97
energein and, 53–54
equality of proportion and, 98
exoteric discourses of, 98
homogenous space and, 50
infinite divisibility and, 51
influence of, 205n2
invariable functions and, 50
Lyceum and, 86, 91, 97–99
Metaphysics and, 121
method of approximation and, 51
perfection and, 39
Peripatetics and, 99
Physics and, 98–99, 105n34, 218n30,
244n9
Problems and, 58n22, 88n1, 133
successor of, 91n4
Theophrastus and, 99–100
Index
Aristoxenus, x–xi, xiv, 9n17
accomplishments of, 86–87
acroamatic discourses and, 98
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–53,
260–66, 270–74, 278–95
approximation method of, 121–22
Archytas and, 71–72, 74, 91–92, 267,
283
Aristides Quintilianus and, 56–58, 60
arithmetic/geometric sequences of, 210
attunement and, 179, 199–203
Bacchius and, 49–51, 56, 59n26, 60
background of, 89–91, 94–97
canonic ratios and, 214–17, 221–26,
299
Chromatic genus and, 209–10,
215–16, 226
circle of fifths and, 73–74
Cleonides and, 51–54, 58, 209–10
conservative nature of, 296–97
continuous pitch and, 70–71
continuum and, 110–18, 121, 187–88,
244–45, 299
critics of, 62–87
Damon and, 296–97
data sources for, 91n4
deduction and, xvi
defining music, 31
depth of, 57–58
Diatonic genus and, 79–80, 203,
209–10, 222
Didymus and, 223–29
diesis of, 71
direct experience and, 204–5, 242–53,
260–66, 270–74, 278–95
discontinuity and, 206
discrete notes and, 206–7
doubling of quanta by, 209–10
dynamis and, 53
energein and, 53–54
319
Enharmonic genus and, 78–81, 209–11
epimoric ratios and, 221–22
epitritic ratios and, 220–21
Euclid and, 135, 143, 145–47, 150–53
feeling and, 26–27
Gaudentius and, 54–56, 59–60
Greater Perfect System and, 212, 226
growing reputation of, 99–100
harmonics and, 59, 65–87, 98n18,
109–19, 122–24, 127–28
homogenous space and, 50
human ear and, 54–56, 81, 86,
109–19, 190–91, 198, 204–5
ignoring laws of mathematics, 72
imperfection and, 206–7
incomplete writings of, 57
infinity and, 184–87
intervals and, 58n23, 70–87, 195–96,
218–26
intuition (synesis) and, 86, 136, 243–44
invariable functions and, 50
irrationality and, 89–90, 205, 208,
210, 297–98
judgment of performer and, 251–52
Latin translations of, 59–60, 65–66
linear intervals and, 70–71
logic and, 87, 219–20
magnitude and, 122–24, 206–7
Mantinea and, 91n4, 92, 94–95
mathematical training of, 89–90, 95
melody and, 64n45, 74–75, 88–89, 98
(see also melody)
miraculous order of music and, 243
modal relationships and, 298–99
modern reputation of, 62–66
modulation and, 77
moral purity approach of, 94
motion of voice and, 109–14, 121
Mountford and, 70–71
musical space and, 50
320
Aristoxenus (cont.)
musical vs. unmusical, 88–89
as “The Musician”, 62, 82–83, 85–86
music notation and, 60n32
originality of, 61–62
personality of, 77–78
pitch and, 66–87, 109–18, 298–301
Plato and, 296–97
pride of, 194
Ptolemy and, 56–58, 68, 71–72,
207–8, 211–15, 220–27, 299
Pythagoras and, 68, 70, 81–83, 85,
95–96, 122, 178, 204–6, 238, 240,
297–99, 302
quarter-tone and, 71, 75
rhythm and, 219
scientific rigor and, 66–81
Tarentum and, 95n12
tension and, 22n41, 50
Theophrastus and, 99–100, 108–9
topos of melody and, 171–203, 207,
211, 219–20, 300, 302
tuning and, 73–77, 204
value of music and, 49–50
West and, 76–77, 80–81
whole-tone and, 66n51
Winnington-Ingram and, 71–75, 77, 81
“Aristoxenus and the Intervals of Greek
Music” (Winnington-Ingram), 71
astrology, 154–58
astronomy, 61n36, 99, 253, 257n38
Copernicus and, 160
decad and, 7–8
geometry and, 15–16
harmonics and, 13–16, 265
heliocentric model and, 160n14
irrationality and, 9
Kepler and, 160–66
motion and, 13–17
Newton and, 165–66
Index
Ptolemy and, 56, 62, 154–66
Pythagoras and, 13–17
relativity and, 167
Superstring theory and, 167–68,
286n86
tetraktys and, 7–8
universal order and, 16–18
Athenaeus of Naucratis, 5, 57, 61, 83n87
Athenaus XIV, 93n7
Attic plays, xiii
attunement, 179, 199–203, 264, 283
auloi, xiii, 4, 9, 79n79, 102, 188, 255
Austen, Jane, 154
Bacchanals, 85
Bacchius, 1, 9n17, 56, 58n22
Aristoxenus and, 49–51, 56, 59n26, 60
defining music, 21, 25, 31
experience of, 48–49
feeling and, 26–27
Gaudentius and, 55
intellectual knowledge and, 39–40
logic and, 48
melody and, 2–3, 21–23, 25, 49n2
modulation and, 20–21
as “Old Man”, 48
Pythagoras and, 50
use of number, 20–21
Bach, J. S., 19
Barbera, André, 226n43
magnitude and, 125n7, 126n8,
135n17, 138n19, 139n21, 142n24
topos of melody and, 191n87
Barker, Andrew, 296n1
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 248–49,
251n23, 253n26, 257nn37, 38,
261n44, 265n53, 275
Aristoxenian influence and, 59–60, 62,
64, 68n52, 78n75, 82n84, 226n42,
226n44, 231
Index
magnitude and, 133n16, 135n17,
142n24
melody and, 104–5, 112n46, 155n2,
156n8, 171n41, 177n55, 179n62,
190nn85, 86, 195
Barrow, John D., 178n59
Bartoli, Cecilia, 25
Battle of Gaugamela, 91
Beckmann, P., 89n2
Beethoven, xii, 27, 29, 39, 182–83
Bélis, Annie, 181n66, 182n67, 185n73,
193n92, 194n95, 205n2
Bellermann, F., 55n14, 61
Berenice, 234–37, 239
Bernikes Plokamos (Callimachus), 236
Bernoulli, Daniel, 11
Bernstein, Seymour, ix–x
Bible, 10n18, 120n60
Blum, David, 175n50
Boethius, 10, 54, 57, 61, 91n4, 152n40
Bowman, Alan C., 124n5
Bowman, Wayne D., 103n28, 206n4
musical formalism and, 25n51, 30n66,
32n69, 33nn70, 71, 36n76, 39n79,
40n82
topos of melody and, 170, 172, 174,
180n64
Brahe, Tycho, 160
Brahms, Johannes, 27, 33
Bruno, Giordano, 160
Bryennius, Manuel, 61n36
Cain, 10n18
Callimachus, 236
canonic ratios, 122–24
aesthetics and, 231–32
Archytas and, 214–15, 216n26,
222–23
Aristoxenus and, 214–17, 221–26, 299
comparison of various methods of, 222
321
Didymus and, 223–29, 240
ear and, 216, 255–58 (see also aisthēsis
vs. logos debate)
epimoric, 221–22
epitritic, 220–21
Erastosthenes and, 222n35, 225
Euclid and, 134–53
lichanos and, 216–17, 223
Ptolemy and, 221–26, 241
simulacra and, 271
Cantor, Georg, xvii
Capella, Martianus, 63–64
Carlyle, Thomas, 1
Carter, Elliott, Jr., 164nn22, 23
Casals, Pablo, 175
Casals and the Art of Interpretation (Blum),
175n50
Cassiodorus, 54
Categories (Aristotle), 274
Catullus, 236
Censorinus, 9
Chalcidius, 10
Chalcis, 97
character (ethos), xv
Cheiron, 232
Chomsky, Noam, 43–45
chorus, xiii
Chromatic genus, 37, 185n74, 186n73
Aristoxenus and, 209–10, 226
Euclid and, 148–49
hemiolic, 143, 202, 209, 212, 214–16
Ptolemy and, 214
soft, 202, 209, 216n26, 217n28
Cicero, 10, 57, 63, 99
Circe, 25
circle of fifths, 73–74
circumference, 89–90
clarinets, 79n79
Clearchus of Cyprus, 99
Clements, E., 71
322
Cleonides, 51–56, 58, 209, 301
colors (chroai), xv
Coma Bernices (Catullus), 236
Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics
(Porphyry), xvii, 100n21, 101nn23,
24, 106n35, 229–30, 239–41,
260n42
Comotti, Giovanni, 60, 64–65, 81, 93n7
composition (melopoeia), 49n2
concordancy (symphonia), 54n11, 118–19
condensation, 128–29
Confessions (St. Augustine), 170n38
consonance
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 277
astrology and, 154–55
Bacchius and, 2
circle of fifths and, 73–74
Euclid and, 136, 148, 150–53
Fundamental Principle of, 138n19
human ear and, 135–36
planetary motion and, 154–55, 162–63
polygons and, 162
Pythagoras and, 6–7, 11–12
topos and, 195n97
tuning by, 73, 123n3
See also harmonics
Constantine the Great, 1n1
constants, 8n16
constellations, 155
continuum, 88–89, 95n11
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 244–47,
259n41, 286–88, 292
Aristoxenus and, 110–18, 121,
187–88, 244–45, 299
dynamic quality and, 117
Euclid and, 124 (see also Euclid)
Fourier analysis and, 128–30
infinity and, 89
magnitude and, 122–24 (see also
magnitude)
Index
melody and, 105–20
motion of voice and, 109–14, 121–24
Plato and, 116
Pythagorean harmonics and, 118–19
resolution and, 117
tension and, 117
Theophrastus and, 105
topos and, 110, 114n48, 170–71,
177–78, 187–88
tuning and, 118–19
Cook, Albert, xi, 18n33
Cook, Nicholas, 174
Cooke, Deryck, 117n55, 286n86
message of music, 41–42
motion of voice and, 111
musical formalism and, 26–31
Sloboda and, 42–43
subjective/objective nature of music
and, 34–35, 38–41
Copernicus, Nicholas, 15, 160
Corinna, 230n50
Corinth, 95–96
cosmology, xvi
decad and, 7–8
Demiurge and, 154–55
Godwin and, 167–68
harmonics and, 6–20
irrationality and, 9
Kepler and, 160–66
motion and, 13–17, 155–66
number 27 and, 152n40
Ptolemy and, 155–66
Superstring theory and, 167–68
tetraktys and, 7–8
topos of melody and, 169–203
universal order and, 16–18
World-Soul and, 15n29, 17
zodiac and, 155–58
Creator, 17, 19, 154–55
Curtis Institute, 92
Index
Damon of Athens, 34n71, 63, 92, 96, 189,
296–97
Da Rios, R., 91n4, 118n58
Aristoxenian influence and, 57nn20,
21, 78n77, 204n1, 210n13, 223n36
infinity and, 297n3, 300n8
topos of melody and, 171n41, 176n51,
177n56, 179n62, 194n96
Darius, King of Persia, 91
Darwin, Charles, 195
decad, 7–8
Deipnosophistai (Sophists at Dinner)
(Athenaeus,
of Naucratis, 5n10
Demetrius of Phalerum, 99
Demetrius Poliorketes, 233
Demetrius the Fair, 232–37
Demiurge, 17, 19, 154–55
dianoia (musical reasoning), 281–83, 288,
290. See aisthēsis vs. logos debate
Diatonic genus
Aristoxenus and, 79–80, 203, 209–10,
222
compounding and, 246n13
Greater Perfect System and, 75
magnitude and, 148–53
musical formalism and, 37n77
Norton and, 289
Phrygian mode and, 268n58
Plato and, 15n29
Ptolemy and, 214, 222
Dicaearchus of Messina, 86, 91n4, 99
Dickinson, Emily, 1, 241
Didymus, 71–72, 214–15, 258n40
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 262–63
canonic ratios and, 223–29, 240
as mousikos, 242
Dijksterhus, E. J., 208n9
Diogenes Laertius, 9, 35, 97n16, 100n20
Dionysius the Younger, 96
323
direct experience
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–53,
260–66, 270–74, 278–95
Aristoxenus and, 204–5,
242–53, 260–66, 270–74,
278–95
Euclid and, 131–36, 140–41
magnitude and, 131–33
motion and, 131
Dirichlet, Peter Gustave Lejeune, xvii
discordancy (diophonica), 54n11
dissonance, 302
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 276–77,
280
Bacchius and, 2
fourth-fifth interval and, 7
human ear and, 135–36
Pythagoras and, 7
topos of melody and, 198
dithyrambs, 93n7
ditones
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and,
245–46, 250, 265n53, 278
Aristoxenus and, 54n11, 79–80, 221,
226
infinity and, 296n1
magnitude and, 150n38, 151
musical formalism and, 38n78
topos of melody and, 195n97, 203
divisibility, 113
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 264n51,
283, 293
Aristoxenus and, 51
magnitude and, 121n1, 139
topos of melody and, 178n59, 187n77,
218n30
Dorian scale, 300–1
Double Concerto (Brahms), 33
Duhem, P., 257n38
dynamis, 53, 112, 176n52, 280–81
324
ear
advanced knowledge of pitch and, 250
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–66,
270–74, 278–95
Aristoxenus and, 54–56, 81, 86,
109–19, 190–91, 198, 204–5
canonic ratios and, 216
continuum and, 109–19
Euclid and, 135–41
magnitude and, 125
motion of voice and, 109–14
musical notation and, 183
topos of melody and, 175–78, 188,
190–91, 198
trained, 54, 56, 86
tuning by consonance and, 123n3
Egypt, 146, 148n34, 231–38
eidē, 40n80
eikonēs (simulacra), 271
Einstein, Albert, 167
ekbolē, xv, 123, 207n5
eklysis, xv, 122–23
Elegant Universe, The (Greene), 167nn31, 32
Elements (Euclid), 146–48
Eliot, George, 120n60
Eliot, T. S., 88
Emblems of Mind (Rothstein), 12n23,
106n35, 112n46, 118n57, 187n78
energein, 53–54
Enharmonic genus, 37, 217n28
Aristoxenus and, 78–81, 209–10, 226
Euclid and, 148–53
Ptolemy and, 210–11, 214
topos and, 185n74, 186n73, 192
Epaminondas, 92, 94n10
Epicureans, 65
Epigonus of Ambracia, 86, 189
epimeres (superpartient), 128, 134–35
epimorios (superparticular), 128, 213,
221–22, 280
Index
Equal Temperament, 200–1
Eratocles, 86, 108, 191, 193
Eratosthenes, 72n62, 99, 214–15, 222n35,
223, 225, 239
Erinna, 230n50
Eroica Funeral March, 29
Euclid, 50, 62, 64, 124–25, 183n70,
184n72
canonic ratios and, 134–53
Chromatic genera and, 148–49
consonance and, 136, 148, 150–53
Diatonic genus and, 148, 150–53
direct experience and, 131–36, 140–41
divisibility and, 139
ear and, 135–41
Enharmonic genera and, 148–53
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53
inference and, 132–33
intervals and, 136–44
isotones and, 137
magnitude and, 124–48, 153
modesty of, 147
multitudes and, 197
number and, 127
octaves and, 134–35
propagation of sound and, 128–29
Propositions of, 139, 144–45, 148–51,
184n72
pure knowledge and, 147
ratio and, 127
school of, 146
stillness and, 126
topos and, 183n70, 184n72, 188, 199
tuning and, 139–40
vibration and, 128–29
Euclidean Division of the Canon, the
(Barbera), 126n8
Eudemus of Rhodes, 99
Eudoxus of Cnidus, 90n3, 196–97, 208
Index
Euler, Leonard, 11–12
Eurytus, 95n12
Eusebius, 235n63
Exact Sciences in Antiquity, The
(Neugebauer), 10n18
feeling
Aristoxenus and, 26–27
Bacchius and, 26–27
Cooke on, 26–31
intellectual knowledge and, 39–41
pitch and, 25–31
pleasure-pain and, 27
subjective/objective duality and,
27–28, 33–39
time and, 26–27
triadic structure and, 43–46
volume and, 26–27
Field, J. V., 18
fifths, 302
continuum and, 118–19
Greater Perfect System and, 158, 212
hemiolios and, 135
Immutable System and, 148–53
infinity and, 184n71
magnitude and, 122–23
Ptolemy and, 162
topos and, 188, 198
See also pitch
finger-note (lichanos), xv, 114, 208
canonic ratios and, 216–17, 223
magnitude and, 144n28
topos of melody and, 186, 195
First Piano Concerto (Brahms), 27
First Symphony (Mahler), 27
five-quarters tone (ekbolē), xv, 123, 207n5
Fludd, Robert, 14n28
Fortlage, C., 55n14
Fourier, Joseph, 128–29
Fourier analysis, 128–30
325
fourths, 302
continuum and, 118–19
Greater Perfect System and, 212
Immutable System and, 148–53
Ptolemy and, 162
spitritos and, 135
topos and, 188, 198
See also pitch
frequency, 11
Euclid and, 133–34
Helmholtz and, 200–1
square root and, 11n21
Theophrastus and, 101, 104
Fulgentius, 10
Galilei, Galileo, 11, 160, 257n38
Galilei, Vincenzo, 11
Gaudentius, 9, 54–56, 59–60
Genesis, Bible Book of, 10n18
geometric square, 8
geometry, 99
astronomy and, 15–16
cosmology and, 155–66
Euclid and, 62, 124–48, 153
Kepler and, 160–66
magnitude and, 121, 125
motion and, 15–16, 155–66
Pi and, 89–90
planets and, 155–66
Ptolemy and, 155–66
zodiac and, 155–58
Geron (Old Man), 48
Glaucon, 192
Godwin, Jocelyn, 5n11, 14n28, 18, 157n9,
159n12, 167–68
Gogavinus Antonius, 66
Gombosi, Otto J., 83n87
Good, The, 97–98
Greater Perfect System, 75, 131n15, 155,
158, 212, 226
326
Greek Aulos, The (Schlesinger), 79n79,
179n61
Greek language, xiii–xv
Greeks,
absolute pitch and, xiv–xv
authors and, xiv
genius of, xv–xvi
logic and, 2
musical environment of, xiii
notation of, 55n14, 60n32
paideia and, 23–24
pitch concept of, 131n15
three musical genera of, 37n77
Greene, Brian, 167nn31, 32, 168
Hagiopolites, 10
Hanslick, Eduard, 4n7
Harmonic Elements (Aristoxenus)
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 245,
247n14, 261n43, 265n53,
272n64, 274n67, 277n73,
280n76, 281n79, 283–84,
286n85, 288n89, 289–90
infinity and, 296, 297nn2, 3, 300n8
magnitude and, 123n3, 150nn37, 38
melody studies of, 88, 98n18, 109n38,
111n44, 114n49, 118n58
musical formalism and, 38n78, 53n8,
59, 65, 75n70, 78n76, 84, 85n96,
204n1, 216n26, 218n29, 219n32,
223n36, 227
topos and, 171n41, 176n51, 177n56,
179nn61, 62, 181n66, 182n67,
186n76, 190n85, 192n90,
193nn91, 92, 194n96, 195n97,
197n99
Harmonic Introduction (Harmonikē Eisagōgē)
(Gaudentius), 54
harmonics
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
Index
Aristoxenus and, 59, 65–87, 98n18,
109–19, 122–24, 127–28
arithmetic/geometric sequences of, 210
astronomy and, 13–16, 265
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
Chromatic genus and, 37, 143,
148–49, 185n74, 186n73, 202,
209–17, 226
circle of fifths and, 73–74
Cleonides and, 51–54
continuum and, 109–19 (see also
continuum)
cosmology and, 155–66
decad and, 7–8
Demiurge and, 154–55
Diatonic genus and, 15n29, 37n77, 75,
79–80, 148–53, 203, 209–10, 214,
222, 246n13, 268n58, 289
ear and, 109–14 (see also ear)
Enharmonic genus and, 37, 78–81,
148–53, 185n74, 186n73, 192,
209–11, 214, 217n28, 226
Equal Temperament and, 200–1
Euclid and, 124–53
Fourier analysis and, 128–30
frequency and, 11, 101, 104, 133–34,
200–1
Greater Perfect System and, 75,
131n15, 155, 158, 212, 226
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53, 154n1
infinity and, 184–87
irrationality and, 7–9
Kepler and, 160–66
Lesser Perfect System and, 142
magnitude and, 122–24 (see also
magnitude)
modern sense of term, 49n2
motion and, 13–17 (see also motion)
Index
Newton and, 165–66
Plato and, 14–15
polygons and, 162
Ptolemy and, 56–57, 155–66
Pythagoras and, xvi-xvii, 6–20, 49–50,
55, 96, 118–19, 124–25, 127,
164–65, 178–79, 183–84, 195, 199
Schopenhauer and, 19–20
string length/tone relationship and, 7
(see also strings)
superparticular ratios and, 128, 213,
221–22, 280
Superstring theory and, 167–68
Systēma Ametabolon and, 290
tetraktys and, 7–8
Theophrastus and, 108–9
topos of melody and, 170–203, 207
universal order and, 16–19
zodiac and, 155–58
Harmonics (Archytas), 267
Harmonics (Ptolemy), xvii, 159n12, 213,
240, 248, 254n28
Harmonies of the World (Carter), 164nn22,
23
Harmonie Universelle (Mersenne), 11
Harmonikes mundi (Kepler), 162n20, 163,
166
Harmonists, 193–94
“Harmony of the Spheres”, 14–15
Harmony of the Spheres, The (Godwin),
157n9
Harmony of the World, The (Kepler), 18
harps, 9, 10n18
harpsichords, 118
Heath, L., 197n100
Heath, Thomas, 10n20
heliocentric model, 160n14
Helmholtz, Hermann, 11, 200–1, 298
Hemiolic Chromatic, 143, 202, 209, 212,
214–16
327
“Hendacachord of Ion of Chios, The”
(Levin), 265n53
Hermeias, 97n16
Highet, Gilbert, xi
Hindemith, Paul, 28–33, 36–37, 279
Hippasus, 8
Hippocrates, 64, 90n3
Historia Mulierum Philospharum (Ménage),
241–42
History of Pi, A (Beckmann), 89n2
History of Western Philosophy, A (Russell),
xvn7
Homer, 23–25, 64, 99
Hugo, Victor, 99n19
human soul, 99, 107
Hurlburt, Norma, xi-xii
Hypatia, 230n50
Hypseus, 231
Iamblichus, 9, 91n5
Idea, 2n3, 32
Idean Dactyls, 10n18
Iliad (Homer), 23–24
Immutable System, 145n29, 148–53,
154n1
Infinite in the Finite, The (Wilson), 199n102
infinity
Chromatic genus and, 186n73
continuum and, 109–20, 264n51
Enharmonic genus and, 186n73
intervals and, 72, 184n71
irrationality and, 297–98
method of exhaustion and, 90n3
Pi and, 89–90
pitch and, 296–302
topos and, 184–87, 199n102
Zeno and, 186–87
instrumentalists, xiii, 261, 282n80
intervals
addition/subtraction of, 73–74
328
intervals (cont.)
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 245–46
Aristoxenus and, 58n23, 70–87, 218–26
Bacchius and, 2, 22
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
as characterizing agent, 41n83
circle of fifths and, 73–74
continuum and, 109–18
epitritic, 220–21
Euclid and, 136–44
feeling and, 25–31
frequency and, 11
Gaudentius and, 54–56, 59
importance of, 109
infinity and, 72, 184n71
Kepler and, 163–65
linear, 70–71
mathematical representation of, 95n11
melody and, 22
mode/pitch relationships and, 298–301
motion of voice and, 109–14
Pythagoras and, 123nn3, 4, 164–65
superparticular ratios and, 128, 213,
221–22, 280
Theophrastus and, 100–9
topos and, 110, 114n48, 170–203
tuning and, 123n3 (see also tuning)
Introduction to Harmonics (Cleonides), 52n7
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy
(Russell), 8n15
Introduction to the Art of Music (Bacchius), 49
inverse-square relationships, 165–66
Ion (Socrates), 85
irrationality, 199–200
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 263
Aristoxenus and, 205, 208, 210,
297–98
logic and, 8–9
mathematics and, 7–9, 89–90
Index
Philodemus and, 34
Pi and, 225n40
Pythagoras and, 8
spatial continuity and, 9n17
Isacoff, Stuart, 184n71, 221n34, 224n39
Isidore of Seville, 10
isotones, 137
Jaeger, Werner, 100n20
James, Jamie, 18, 64n44, 83, 165–66
Jeppesen, Kund, 53n8
Josephus, 99
Jourdain, Robert, 18, 84–85
Jubal, 10n18
Justin, 234–35
Juvenal, 46n91
Kant, Immanuel, 171n39
Kemke, Johannes, 34n71, 35nn72–74
Kepler, Johannes, 15, 18, 160–66
kinēsis. See motion
Kivy, Peter, 85
Kline, Morris, 12, 247n15
Krexus, 93
Kronecker, Leopold, xvii
Lacedaemon, 92n6
Laloy, Louis, 91n4, 205n2
Lamprus of Erythrae, 92, 95
Landels, John, 81
Langer, Susan, 4nn7, 8
language
Greek, xiii–xv
music as, 25–31, 35, 40–47, 111n44,
117n55
Language of Music, The (Cooke), 117n55,
286n86
Lasus of Hermione, 86, 189
Latin translations, 59–60
Lawrie, Laura, xii
Index
Laws (Plato), 88n1
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 19
Leonore Overture No. 3 (Beethoven), 27
Lesser Perfect System, 142
Levin, F. R.
“Apeiria in Aristoxenian Theory”
(Levin), xviin8
heavenly order and, 13n16
“The Hendacachord of Ion of Chios”,
265n53
The Manual of Harmonics of Nicomachus
the Pythagorean, 6n13, 7n14, 13n26,
15n29, 58nn22, 25, 131n14,
148n34, 151n39, 222n35
“Plēgē and Tasis”, 11n21, 276n71
“Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory”,
95n11, 116n53, 204n1, 243n8
“Unity in Euclid’s ‘Sectio Canonis’”,
126n8, 129n12
Life of Pythagoras (Aristoxenus), 96
Lippmann, Edward, 49n2, 103, 140n22,
176n51
Little Gidding (Eliot), 88
logic, xii, 12
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
Aristotle and, xvii
Aristoxenus and, 87, 219–20
Bacchius and, 48
constants and, 8n16
continuum and, 109–19
deduction and, xvi
Euclid and, 124–53
feeling and, 27–28, 33–39
Greek passion for, 2
illusion and, 34–35
infinity and, 184–87 (see also infinity)
irrationality and, 8–9
Lyceum and, 97, 99
magnitude and, 121 (see also
magnitude)
329
melody and, 2–4
multitude and, 121
Philodemus and, 34–35
Pythagoras and, 68
of a resolution, x
spatial continuity and, 9n17
Zeno’s paradox and, 186–87
Longinus, 66n49
Lucian, 95n12
Lyceum, 86, 91, 97–99
Lydian scale, 301
lyres, 6, 14n28
Lysis, 91
Maas, Martha, 24n48
McDermott, William C., xi
Macedonia, 234
McIntosh Snyder, Jane, 24n48
Maconie, Robin, 18, 25, 84
Macran, 285n83, 285n84
Macrobius, 10
Magas, 234
Magna Graecia, 90–91
magnitude (megethos), 121, 206–7
direct experience and, 131–33
divisibility and, 139
Euclid and, 124–53 (see also Euclid)
evidence of measure and, 125
motion of voice and, 122–24
ratio and, 122–24, 134–53
topos and, 197–203
Mahler, Gustav, 27
Maitland, Sheran, xii
Mantinea, 91n4, 92, 94–95
Manual of Harmonics (Nicomachus),
58nn22, 25, 148n34
Manual of Harmonics of Nicomachus the
Pythagorean, The (Levin), 6n13,
7n14, 13n26, 15n29, 58nn22, 25,
131n14, 148n34, 151n39, 222n35
330
Martianus Capella, 61
mathematics, xv
abstract/certain nature of, 12
aesthetics of, 12–13
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
Aristoxenus’ training and, 89–90
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
constants and, 8n16
geometry, 8, 15–16, 62, 89–90, 99,
121, 124–48, 153–66
imperfection and, 206–7
infinity and, 72, 184–87 (see also
infinity)
interval representation and, 95n11
inverse-square relationships and,
165–66
irrationality and, 7–9, 89–90, 205, 208
(see also irrationality)
melody and, 3–5, 95n11
Mersenne’s Laws and, 11
method of exhaustion and, 90n3
musical limitations of, 100
octaves and, 4–5
Pi and 89–90
planetary motion and, 155–66
Ptolemy and, 56, 58
Pythagoras and, xvi-xvii, 5–20, 300
topos and, 180 (see also topos)
transcendental numbers and, 89n2,
200, 225n40
universe ruled by, 5–6
See also magnitude
Mathematics in Western Culture (Kline),
247n15
Mathiesen, Thomas J., 51n5, 54nn10, 11,
57, 58n24, 59nn26, 29, 60n32,
61n33
medicine, 11
Meibom, Marcus, 59, 65–66, 69, 82
Index
melody
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
Bacchius and, 21–25, 49n2
canonic ratios and, 134–44
codification of, 74–75
continuum and, 88–89, 105–20
defining, 2–3, 21–22
ekmeleia and, 106–7
Euclid and, 124–53
feeling and, 25–31
as form of tautology, 3–4
formalism and, 64n45, 70–87, 93–94,
98, 296–97
Greek language and, xiii–xv
human ear and, 135–36 (see also ear)
logic and, 3–4
mathematics and, 3–5, 95n11
meaning and, 46
motion and, x, 109–14, 121
musical/unmusical, 88–89
Philodemus and, 33–39
Plato and, 74
reciprocity of, 2
resolution and, x
rhythm and, 2, 20n39, 36n76, 39n79,
61n34, 79, 83n87, 87, 88n1,
189n83, 219, 294n104
straightness and, 274–75
tension and, x, 25–31, 41n83, 50,
53–54, 100–14, 117, 207, 211,
219–20
Ursatz and, 43–45
melos (complete musical complex), 58n24
Menaechmus, 90n3
Ménage, Gilles, 241–42
Mendelssohn, Felix, 33
Meno, 99
Mersenne, Marin, 1n2, 11, 131
Mersenne’s Laws, 11, 131n13
Metaphysics (Aristotle), 121
Index
Metochites, Theodorus, 61n36
Meursius, Johannes, 66
Michelangelo Buonarroti, 107
Mnesias, 91n4
modulation
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 288n89
Aristoxenus and, 77
Bacchius and, 2, 20–21
importance of, 20n39
as metaphor, 20n39
See also pitch
monochords, 9, 10n19, 148, 184n71
Morgenstern, Sam, 33n70, 182n68,
183n69
motion, 298
condensed/rarefied, 128–29
consonance and, 162–63
continuum and, 105–19, 170–71 (see
also continuum)
Copernicus and, 160
Demiurge and, 154–55
direct experience and, 131
energein and, 53–54
Euclid and, 124–48, 153
Fourier analysis and, 128–30
geometry and, 15–16
harmonics and, 13–16
heliocentric model and, 160n14
inverse-square relationships and,
165–66
Kepler and, 160–66
laws of planetary, 15–16, 154–66
Newton and, 165–66
percussive sound and, 16–17
pitch and, 124n5
propagation of sound and, 128–29
Ptolemaic system and, 154–60
Pythagoras and, 13–17
speed and, 130, 133–34
Superstring theory and, 167–68
331
topos of melody and, 169–203
vibration and, 11, 16, 58n25, 100n22,
101, 104, 110–11, 122n2, 125–35,
153, 167–68
of voice, 109–14, 121, 123–24,
282n80
Mountford, J. F., 70–71, 208
Mousikē (musical instrument), 10n19
Mozart, W. A., xivn4
multitude (plēthos), 121
Muscarella, Oscar White, xii
Muses, 97
music
absolute pitch and, xiv–xv
affects on listener, 25–47
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 241–95
Aristoxenus and, 48 (see also
Aristoxenus)
as beyond science, 32
defining, 21–22, 25, 31–34
feeling and, 25–46
as final word, 81–82
Greek culture and, xiii, 91n4, 92, 94–95
harmonics and, xvi-xvii (See also
harmonics)
homogenous space and, 50
as illusion, 34–35
intellectual knowledge and, 39–41, 46
invariable functions and, 50
Jubal and, 10n18
knowledge and, 49–50
as language, 25–31, 35, 40–47,
111n44, 117n55
as living sound, x
logic and, x, xii, 2 (see also logic)
mathematical limitations of, 100 (see
also mathematics)
message of, 41–42
miraculous order of, 243
motion and, 13–17 (see also motion)
Index
332
music (cont.)
nature and, x, 82n85, 302
notation and, 181–83 (see also notation)
organic value of, 49–50
perfection and, 39–40
Platonic Ideas and, 32
Pythagoras and, xvi-xvii, 5–20
reciprocity of, 2
as ruled by number, 5
subjective/objective duality and,
27–28, 33–39
subject matter of, 40
trained ear and, 54–56 (see also ear)
triadic structure and, 43–46
Musica, De (Aristides Quitilianus), 60,
148n34
Musica, De (Plutarch), 93n7, 94n10
Musical Mind, The: The Cognitive Psychology
of
Music (Sloboda), 42
musical space. See topos
Musical Thought in Ancient Greece
(Lippmann), 103, 140n22, 176n51
Music of the Heavens, The (Stephenson),
159n12
Music of the Spheres, The (James), 83
mythology, 10
nature, x, 82n85, 302
divine proportions and, 6
harmonics and, 6–20
ruled by number, 5–6
Nero, 214
nētē-Hyperbolation (highest note), 155–56
Neugebauer, Otto, 10n18
Newton, Isaac, 11, 13n25, 128n10,
165–66, 195
Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle), 48, 205n2
Nicomachus, 6–9, 13n26, 50, 58, 61,
148n34, 203
Nietzsche, F., 159n13
Norton, Richard, 62, 289
notation, 3–4, 55, 217n28
Alypius and, 131n15
Ansermet and, 83
Aristides and, 60n32
Aristoxenus and, 179–83, 225
Cooke and, 31
Greek genera and, 37n77
Kepler and, 164n22
Maconie and, 84
modern, 58n22
Plato and, 60n32, 192n90
rhythm and, 61n34
oboes, 79n79
octaves, 302
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 268–69
continuum and, 119–20
diplasios and, 134–35
Equal Temperament and, 200–1
Euclid and, 134–35
as form of tautology, 4
Greater Perfect System and, 155, 158,
212
infinity and, 184n71
mapping double-octave and, 155–60
mathematics and, 4–5
melodic constant and, 3–4
Ptolemy and, 162
Pythagoras and, 6n12, 7
string length and, 7
superparticular ratios and, 128, 213
tetraplasios, 134–35
twelve divisions of, 206–7, 216n25,
218–20, 226
zodiac and, 155–58
See also pitch
Odes (Pindar), 6
Ode to Joy (Beethoven), 39, 45–46
Index
Odyssey (Homer), 24
Olympus, 79–80
On Music (Aristides Quitilianus), 56–57
On Music (Plutarch), 78
On Music (Theophrastus), 105
On the Difference Between the Aristoxenians
and
the Pythagoreans (Didymus), 227
On the Nuptials of Mercury and Philology
(Martianus Capella), 61
Orpheus, 63–64
Owen, George, 8, 196n98
Pachymeres, George, 61n36
paideia (cultivation), 23–24
Pan-hellenic games, xiii
panpipes, 9
parabola, 90n3
Pathétique Symphony (Tchaikovsky), 27
Pearson, Lionel, 83n87
Pellana, 92n6
Penelope, 24
perfection, 14–16, 39–40, 75, 155n2, 159,
162, 201n106, 251
Pericles, 34n71
Peripatetics, 99–100
Phaedo (Plato), ix, 18n33
Phaenius of Eresus, 99
Phemius, 24
Philebus (Socrates), 191
Philodemus, 83n87
background of, 34n71
irrational nature of music, 34
subjective/objective duality of music,
33–39
Philodemus of Gadara, xii, 33–34
Philolaus, 91, 95n12, 152n40
Philopater, 239
philosophy, xi, xvi
absolute truth and, 30
333
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
cosmology and, 154 (see also cosmology)
Damonian theory and, 34n71
the Good and, 97–98
Idea and, 2n3, 32
imperfection and, 206–7
Lyceum and, 97
pure knowledge and, 147
subjective/objective duality and,
27–28, 33–39
Will and, 32n69
See also specific philosopher
Philoxenus, 92–95
Phintias, 96
phorminx (musical instrument), 24
Phrygian chronicles, 10n18
Phrygian scale, 265n53, 268n58, 301
Physics (Aristotle), 98–99, 105n34,
218n30, 244n9
physiology, 11
Pi, 89–90, 225n40
piano, ix-x, 3, 75
Pi in the Sky (Barrow), 178n59
Pindar, 6, 92, 95
Piston, Walter, 53n8
pitch
absolute, xiv–xv
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–95
Aristoxenus and, 66–87, 109–18,
298–301
Bacchius and, 2
canonic ratios and, 122–24, 134–53,
214–17, 221–26
as characterizing agent, 41n83
Chromatic genus and, 37, 143,
148–49, 185n74, 186n73, 202,
209–17, 226
circle of fifths and, 73–74
Cleonides and, 51–54
condensed/rarefied motion and, 128–29
334
pitch (cont.)
continuum and, 70–71, 105, 109–20
cosmology and, 163–64
deviation (tasis) of, 53
Diatonic genus and, 15n29, 37n77, 75,
79–80, 148–53, 203, 209–10, 214,
222, 246n13, 268n58, 289
ear and, 109–14, 135–41 (see also ear)
energein and, 53–54
Enharmonic genus and, 37, 78–81,
148–53, 185n74, 186n73, 192,
209–11, 214, 217n28, 226
Equal Temperament and, 200–1
Euclid and, 124–53
feeling and, 25–31
Fourier analysis and, 128–30
frequency and, 11, 101, 104, 133–34,
200–1
fundamental, 6n12
Greater Perfect System and, 75,
131n15, 155, 212
Greek concept of, 131n15, 177n55
Greek language and, xiii–xiv
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53
infinity and, 184–87
irrational numbers and, 7–8 (see also
irrationality)
magnitude and, 122–24
melodic constants and, 3–4
Mersenne’s Laws and, 11
modal relationships and, 298–301
motion and, 13–17, 124n5
as number and ratio, 127
Ptolemy and, 56–58
Pythagoras and, 6–20
scale-model of, 131n15
string length and, 7, 125 (see also
strings)
Theophrastus and, 101–4
Index
topos of melody and, 170–203 (see also topos)
tuning and, 9, 14n28, 54–56, 73–77,
118–19, 123n3, 134–44, 204,
268n58
zodiac and, 155–58
See also harmonics
pitch-accent, xiii–xv,
Plato, xi, 81, 86, 88n1, 99, 188n80, 199,
265n52
Academy and, 97, 123
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 279
Aristoxenus and, 296–97
astronomy and, 15
continuum and, 116
Creator and, 17, 19
Damonian theory and, 34n71
defining music and, 2n3
Demiurge and, 17, 19, 154–55
eye and, 31
Form and, 2n3
the Good and, 97–98
harmonics and, 14–15, 17–18
Idea and, 2n3, 32
light and, 31
mathematical propositions and, 13n26
melody and, 2n3
motion and, 17
notation and, 60n32, 192n90
Phaedo and, ix, 18n33
rightness of melody and, 74
status of, 50, 64, 69
Timaeus and, 10, 14, 15n29, 17n32,
116n54
vibratory speed and, 17
World-Soul and, 17
“Plēgē and Tasis” (Levin), 11n21, 276n71
Plutarch, 57, 61, 78, 83n87, 92n6, 93n7,
99, 233n58, 243n7
poetry, xiii, 13n26, 85–86, 99, 230n50,
266n54
Index
pollaplasios (multiple), 128
polygons, 162
polymaths, 100
Pomeroy, Sarah B., 230n50
Porphyry, xi, xvii, 83n87, 91n4
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 253–62,
272–73, 276
Aristoxenus and, 57, 61, 66–68, 72
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene and, 229–31, 233,
238–41
Pratinas of Phlius, 49n2, 95
Primal Unity, 159n13
Principia (Newton), 165–66
Principles of Mathematics (Russell), 8n16,
125
Problems (Aristotle), 58n22, 88n1, 133
proslambanomenos (lowest note), 155–56
Protarchus, 191
Proust, Marcel, 175
Ptolemaïs of Cyrene, x-xi, 46n91, 66n49
aisthēis vs. logos debate and, 253,
255–58, 261–63, 272–82, 290–93
background of, 232n54
Battle of the Criteria and, 242
Demetrius Poliorketes and, 233
Egypt and, 231–33
instrumentalists and, 282n80
Kanonikē and, 240, 278
as mousikē, 242
Porphyry and, 229–31, 233, 238–41
Pythagoras and, xvii, 58n22, 255
public performance and, 242n6
social standing of, 230–31, 241–42
straightness and, 274–75
writings of, 237–40
Ptolemy, Claudius, xvii, 15, 66, 91n4
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 247–54,
257, 260, 264–72
Aristoxenus and, 56–58, 68, 71–72,
214–15, 220–27, 299
335
astrology and, 154–58
astronomy and, 56, 62, 154–66
canonic ratios and, 224–25, 241
Chromatic genus and, 214
cosmology and, 155–60
criticism of Aristoxenus by, 207–8,
211–15
Diatonic genus and, 214
Enharmonic genus and, 210–11, 214
epicycles of, 160
epimoric ratios and, 221–22
epitritic ratios and, 220–21
Greater Perfect System and, 155, 158
harmonics and, 56–57
imperfection and, 207
Kepler and, 160–66
Lesser Perfect System and, 142n24
as mousikē, 241–42
seven tonoi of, 268–69
superparticular ratios and, 213
Ptolemy III Euergetes, 214, 236
Ptolemy II Philadelphus, 234
Ptolemy I Soter, 146, 231–32
Ptolemy IV Philopater, 239
Pythagoras, xvi, 58, 61, 100
acoustic theory and, 65, 81, 152, 206,
215
advanced knowledge of pitch and, 250
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 242–44,
267–71, 274, 279–80, 283–85
Aristoxenus and, 68, 70, 81–83, 85,
95–96, 122, 178, 204–6, 238, 240,
297–99, 302
astronomy and, 13–17
Bacchius and, 50
bean-eating cow and, 91n5
consonance and, 6–7, 11–12
continuum and, 123
cosmology and, 154
decad and, 7–8
336
Pythagoras (cont.)
Didymus and, 227–29
dissonance and, 7
divine proportions and, 6
Euclid and, 136–38, 140
harmonics and, xvi-xvii, 6–20, 49–50,
55, 96, 118–19, 124–25, 127,
164–65, 178–79, 183–84, 195, 199
influence of, 5
intervals and, 123nn3, 4, 164–65
irrational numbers and, 8, 89–90
literature on, 5n11
Magna Graecia and, 90–91
modern reputation of, 62–65
monochord and, 148
motion and, 13–17
Nicomachus on, 6–7
octaves and, 6n12, 7
square root of 2 and, 89n2
string length/tone relationship and, 7
superparticular ratios and, 213
tetraktys and, 7–8
universe ruled by number, 5–6
whole-tone and, 89–90
Xenophilus and, 96–97
Pythagorean Doctrine of the Elements of Music,
The (Ptolemaïs of Cyrene), xvii, 58n22,
255
quarter-tones, 71
Aristoxenus and, 75
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53
magnitude and, 122–23
topos and, 192–93
quaternary, 7n14
Raffman, Diana, 95n11
rarefaction, 128–29
reed instruments, 79n79
Index
Rehl, Beatrice, xii
relativity, 167
Renaissance, 294
Republic (Plato), 192
resolution, 117
Revelation, Bible Book of, 120n60
Revesz, Geza, 172–73
revolutionibus orbium coelestium, De
(Copernicus), 160
Rhea Kybele, 10n18
rhetoric, 34, 99
rhythm, 88n1, 219
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 294n104
Bacchius and, 2
musical formalism and, 20n39, 36n76,
39n79, 61n34, 79, 83n87, 87
topos and, 189n83
Richter, Lukas, 62n39
Riemann, Bernhard, xvii
Rothstein, Edward, 12–13, 18, 106,
112n46, 118n57, 174, 187n78, 206
Ruelle, Charles-Émile, 59
Russell, Bertrand, xvn7, 8nn15, 16, 21,
125
Sacred Bridge, The (Werner), 10n18
Sailing to Byzantium (Yeats), 48
St. Augustine, 170n38, 171
Sappho, 230n50
Schenker, Heinrich, 43–45
Schiller, Friedrich, 46
Schlesinger, Kathleen, 79n79, 179n61,
208
Schoenberg, Arnold, 177n54
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 19–20, 32–33
Schubert, Franz, xii, 288n89
Schumann, Robert, 183
Scientific Method in Ptolemy’s Harmonics
(Barker), 249n18
Scott, Walter, 25n51
Index
Scruton, Roger, 40n81, 43n88, 88n1, 169,
173–74
Seashore, Carl E., 4n7
Sectio Canonis (Euclid)
canonic ratios and, 134–44
Introduction of, 126, 128–29, 132–33,
135
melody and, 124–48, 153
number and, 127
pitch as ratio, 127
Propositions of, 139, 144–45, 148–51
stillness and, 126
theorems of, 132–33
Selinus, 86
semitones, 199–203
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 246–47
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
irrationality and, 210
magnitude and, 122–23
pitch/mode relationships and, 300–1
See also harmonics
Seventh Symphony (Beethoven), 29
Sextus Empiricus, 39n79
Sloboda, John A., 41–45
Socrates, ix, 85–86, 90n3, 191–92
Solomon, Jon, 49n3, 51n5, 56n16, 207–8,
212n16, 226n43, 243n8, 249n18,
270, 288n89
solos, xiii
Somnium Scipionis (Cicero), 10
Sophists, 90n3
soul, 99, 107
Sound and Symbol (Zuckerlandl), 105,
112n46
Sound of Greek, The (Stanford), xiv
Spintharus, 91n4, 92, 96
square roots, 8, 11n21, 89n2
Stance of Plato, The (Cook), 18n33
Stanford, W. B., xiv
337
Steinmayer, Otto, 48n1
Stephenson, Bruce, 18, 159n12, 160n14,
161n16
Stesichorus, 93
Strabo, 61
Stravinsky, Igor, 30–37
strings
arithmetic/geometric sequences of, 210
attunement and, 180–81, 188
Bernoulli and, 11
canonic ratios and, 134–44 (see also
canonic ratios)
concords and, 54n11
condensed/rarefied motion of, 128–29
consonance and, 7
Euclid and, 130
Geometry and, 180
human eye and, 125
increasing number of, 93n7, 94
length of, 72, 122, 130–34, 137, 144,
148, 191, 208–15, 224–26, 274 (see
also pitch)
magnitude and, 122–23
Mersenne and, 11
Pythagoras’ experiments on, 9, 10n10,
82
speed of motion of, 130
superparticular ratios and, 128, 213
Superstring theory and, 167–68,
286n86
tension and, 52n7, 102, 125, 250
topos and, 180–81
vibration and, 6n6, 13, 16, 124,
128–29, 135, 166
Strunk, Oliver, 51n5
Suidas (Fortress or Stronghold), 91n4
superparticulars, 128, 213, 221–22, 280
Superstring theory, 167–68, 286n86
Supreme Being, 165
Sylvester, James Joseph, 13n25
338
Sylvester, William, xii
synecheiē. See continuum
“Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory” (Levin),
95n11, 116n53, 204n1, 243n8
synthetos, 246–47
Tarentum, 90–91, 95n12
Tarn, W. W., 232n57, 235n62
Taylor, A. E., 154n1
Tchaikovsky, Pyotr Ilyich, 27
Telesias of Thebes, 94–95
Telestes, 86, 188–89
tension, x
Aristoxenus and, 50
as characterizing agent, 41n83
continuum and, 117
energein and, 53–54
feeling and, 25–31
motion of voice and, 109–14
pitch deviation and, 53
strings and, 52n7, 102, 125, 250
Terpander, 92
tetrachords, 74, 123n3
canonic ratios and, 222
Greater Perfect System and, 212
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53
irrationality and, 210
topos and, 184–85
See also harmonics
tetraktys, 7–8
Theaetetus (Plato), 188n80, 265n52
Theon of Smyrna, 66, 69
Theophrastus, 91n4
Aristotle and, 99–100
Aristoxenus and, 99–100, 108–9
continuum and, 105–8
harmonics and, 108–9
intellectual range of, 100
mathematics of music and, 100–1
Index
melody and, 100–9
musical instruments and, 102–3
nature of music and, 100–9
pitch and, 101–4
theory of means, 10n20
Thesleff, Holger, 230n50
thirds, 38, 215, 217n28, 278, 284–87
Thomas, Alison, xii
Thomas, Baylis, xii
three-quarters tone (eklysis), xv, 122–23
Timaeus (Plato), 10, 14, 15n29, 17n32,
116n54
timbre, 124
time
continuum and, 170–71, 187–88 (see
also continuum)
feeling and, 26–27
Fourier analysis and, 128–30
intervals and, 300 (see also intervals)
intuition and, 172
memory and, 171
relativity and, 170
rhythm and, 2, 20n39, 36n76, 39n79,
61n34, 79, 83n87, 87, 88n1,
189n83, 219, 294n104
simultaneous actions and, 170
topos of melody and, 169–203
Zeno’s paradox and, 186–87
Timeaus (Plato), 10
Timoleon, 96
Timotheus, 93
Tolstoy, Leo, 121
tonal function, 53n8
tones
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
as characterizing agent, 41n83
continuum and, 109–19
dynamic quality and, 117
isotones, 137
Index
primal bedrock of, 44–45
synthetos and, 246–47
See also pitch
topos, 110, 114n48
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 270–71,
285–86, 293–95
Aristoxenus and, 171–203, 207, 211,
219–20, 300, 302
attunement and, 179, 199–203
Chromatic genus and, 185n74, 186n73
consonance and, 195n97
continuum and, 170–71, 177–78,
187–88
Cook on, 174
Diatonic genus and, 203
divisibility and, 188, 200
dynamis and, 176n52
Enharmonic genus and, 185n74,
186n73, 192
Equal Temperament and, 200–1
Euclid and, 183n70, 184n72, 188, 199
Harmonists and, 193–94
Helmholtz and, 200–1
human ear and, 175–78, 188, 190–91,
198
infinity and, 184–87, 199n102
logic and, 219–20
magnitude and, 197–203
malleability of, 177–78
mathematics and, 180, 184–87,
198–203
measurement and, 197–203
multiplicities and, 197
musical instruments and, 180–81
notation and, 181–83
pitch/mode relationships and, 300
Proust on, 175
quarter-tone and, 192–93
Rothstein on, 174
Scruton on, 173–74
339
semitones and, 201, 203
Socrates and, 191–92
spatial metaphor and, 170–77
strings and, 180–81
tetrachords and, 184–85
Zuckerkandl on, 172–73
transcendental numbers, 89n2, 200,
225n40
transposition (tonoi), xv
triads, 27, 43–46
tuning, 9, 14n28, 204
Aristoxenus and, 73–77
canonic ratios and, 134–44
cithara, 268n58
consonance and, 73, 123n3
continuum and, 118–19
Euclid and, 139–40
trained ear and, 54–56
See also aisthēsis vs. logos debate
T (Viennese scribe), 241–42
tyranny, 99
Tyrtaeus, 92
Tyrtamus, 99–100
Understanding the Infinite (Lavine), 89n2
“Unity in Euclid’s ‘Sectio Canonis’”
(Levin), 126n8, 129n12
universe., cosmology
Universe of the Mind, The (Owen), 196n98
Upshaw, Dawn, 25
Ursatz, 43–45
vibration and, 58n25, 100n22, 122n2, 153
Aristoxenus and, 110–11 (see also
Aristoxenus)
Euclid and, 124–48, 153
frequency and, 11, 101, 104, 133–34,
200–1
harmonius universe and, 167–68
magnitude and, 125–35
Index
340
vibration and (cont.)
Plato and, 17
strings and, 6n6, 13, 16, 124, 128–29,
135, 166
Vincent, A. J. H., 10n19
Virgil, 64
Vitruvius Pollio, 57, 61, 91n4
von Stade, Frederica, 25
Wagner, Richard, 119–20
Wehril, Fritz, 57n1
Weierstrass, Karl, xvii
Werner, Eric, 10n18
West, M. L., 59, 76–81, 94n10, 210n13,
285n84
Westphal, R., 55n14
whole-tones, 300–1
aisthēsis vs. logos debate and, 246–47,
264, 284–85
Aristoxenus and, 66n51
canonic ratios and, 134–53, 214–17,
221–26
continuum and, 119–20
Greater Perfect System and, 155–58
Immutable System and, 145n29,
148–53
incommensurability of, 8–9
irrationality and, 205, 210n13
magnitude and, 122–23
pitch/mode relationships and, 300–1
Ptolemy and, 155–60
Pythagoras and, 89–90
string length and, 7
topos and, 188, 201, 203
twelve divisions of, 206–7, 218–20
zodiac and, 155–58
See also harmonics; pitch
Wilkinson, L. P., 34n71, 35nn72, 73, 39n79
Will, 32n69
Wilson, Alistair Macintosh, 199n102
Winnington-Ingram, R. P., 71–75, 77, 81,
108, 208, 216
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 3, 32, 39
Wolpert, Dorothy, xii,
Wolpert, Stanley, xii
World-Soul, 15n29, 17
Xenakis, 64
Xenophilus, 91n4, 95–97
Yeats, W. B., 48
Zeno the Eleatic, 186
zodiac
Kepler and, 160–66
Ptolemy and, 155–60
zopyron (flash of knowledge), 46
Zuckerkandl, V., 112n46, 117, 172–73,
176n52, 205
Zürcher, Joseph, 100n20